Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-wq484 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T20:55:35.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2017

Reidar Maliks
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Johan Karlsson Schaffer
Affiliation:
Göteborgs Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Moral and Political Conceptions of Human Rights
Implications for Theory and Practice
, pp. 13 - 154
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bibliography

Beitz, C. (2009) The Idea of Human Rights, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2013) The Heart of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J. (2004) “Minimalism about Human Rights: The Most We Can Hope For?” Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 12 no.2, pp. 190213.Google Scholar
Gilabert, P. (2011) “Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights,” Political Theory, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 439–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, J. (2008) On Human Rights, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Liao, S. M. and Etinson, A. (2012) “Political and Naturalistic Conceptions of Human Rights: A False Polemic?Journal of Moral Philosophy, vol. 9 no. 3, pp. 327–52.Google Scholar
Nickel, J. (2007) Making Sense of Human Rights, 2nd edition, Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pogge, T. (2008) World Poverty and Human Rights, 2nd edition, Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (2010) “Human Rights without Foundations,” in Besson, S. and Tasioulas, J. (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 321–37.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. J. (2001) “Human Rights and World Citizenship: The Universality of Human Rights in Kant and Locke,” In Simmons, A. J. (Ed.), Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, John (2017 Forthcoming) “Exiting the Hall of Mirrors: Morality and Law in Human Rights.” In Campbell, Tom and Bourne, Kylie (Ed.), Confronting Moral, Political and Legal Approaches to Human Rights, Routledge.Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2012) “Ideal vs. Non-ideal Theory: A Conceptual Map,” Philosophy Compass, vol. 7 no. 9, pp. 654–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Bibliography

Bates, E. (2010) The Evolution of the European Convention on Human Rights: From Its Inception to the Creation of a Permanent Court of Human Rights, Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baynes, K. (2009) “Toward a Political Conception of Human Rights,” Philosophy & Social Criticism, vol. 35 no. 4, pp. 371–90.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. (2009) The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Besson, S. (2010) “Human Rights qua Normative Practice: Sui Generis or Legal?,” Transnational Legal Theory, vol. 1 no. 1, pp. 127–33.Google Scholar
Brysk, A. (2009) Global Good Samaritans: Human Rights as Foreign Policy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2010) “The Egalitarianism of Human Rights,” Ethics, vol. 120 no. 4, pp. 679710.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, A. S. (2005) “Sweden: Once a Moral Superpower, Always a Moral Superpower?,” International Journal, vol. 61, p. 895.Google Scholar
Donnelly, J. (2002) Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Donnelly, J. (2006) “The Virtues of Legalization,” in Meckled-Garcia, S. and Çalı, B. (eds.), The Legalization of Human Rights: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on Human Rights and Human Rights Law, London: Routledge, pp. 6780.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1970) “The Nature and Value of Rights,” The Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 4 no. 4, pp. 243–60.Google Scholar
Forst, R. (2010) “The Justification of Human Rights and the Basic Right to Justification: A Reflexive Approach,” Ethics, vol. 120 no. 4, pp. 711–40.Google Scholar
Gallie, W.B. (1956) “Essentially Contested Concepts,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 56, pp. 167–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, J. (2010) “The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights,” Metaphilosophy, vol. 41 no. 4, pp. 464–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hafner-Burton, E.M. (2012) “International Regimes for Human Rights,” Annual Review of Political Science, vol. 15 no. 1, pp. 265–86.Google Scholar
Hafner-Burton, E.M. (2014) “A Social Science of Human Rights,” Journal of Peace Research, vol. 51 no. 2, pp. 273–86.Google Scholar
Hessler, K. (2013) “Hard Cases: Philosophy, Public Health, and Women’s Human Rights,” The Journal of Value Inquiry, vol. 47 no. 4, pp. 375–90.Google Scholar
Ho, K.T. (2014) “On Rights and Demands: How Theorists of Rights Can Benefit from Taking Demands Seriously,” Thesis [Electronic], University of St. Andrews. Available at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/handle/10023/5892 [Accessed 4 February 2015].Google Scholar
Ignatieff, M. (2001) Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ingram, D. (2009) “Of Sweatshops and Subsistence: Habermas on Human Rights,” Ethics & Global Politics, vol. 2 no. 3, pp. 193217.Google Scholar
Karp, D.J. (2013) “The Location of International Practices: What Is Human Rights Practice?,” Review of International Studies, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 969–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langford, M. & Schaffer, J.K. (2014) “The Nordic Human Rights Paradox,” Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, [Electronic]: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2275905 [Accessed 1 October 2014].Google Scholar
Meckled-Garcia, S. (2013) “The Practice-Dependence Red Herring and Substantive Reasons for Restricting the Scope of Justice,” Raisons Politiques [Electronic], vol. 51. Available at: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2137525 [Accessed 7 February 2013].Google Scholar
Nickel, J.W. (2006) “Are Human Rights Mainly Implemented by Intervention?,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 263–77.Google Scholar
Nickel, J.W. (2007) Making Sense of Human Rights, Malden, MA; Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
Nickel, J.W. (n.d.) “Assigning Roles to Human Rights,” in Etinson, A. (ed.), Human Rights: Moral or Political?, Oxford: Oxford University Press (forthcoming). Available at: https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B_VH8cWdlkJSamRrYVFEOXNzd00/edit?pref=2&pli=1.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (2010) “Human Rights without Foundations,” In Besson, S. & Tasioulas, J., eds. The Philosophy of International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 321–38.Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, C. (2009) “On Rights and Institutions,” in Beitz, C. R. and Goodin, R. E. (eds.), Global Basic Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2548.Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, C. (2011a) “Human Rights in a Global Ecumene,” International Affairs, vol. 87 no. 5, pp. 1205–18.Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, C. (2011b) “Struggles for Individual Rights and the Expansion of the International System,” International Organization, vol. 65 no. 2, pp. 207–42.Google Scholar
Risse, T., Ropp, S.C. & Sikkink, K. (eds.) (2013) The Persistent Power of Human Rights: From Commitment to Compliance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J.K. (2013) “Legitimacy, Global Governance and Human Rights Institutions: Inverting the Puzzle,” in Føllesdal, A. Schaffer, J.K. & Ulfstein, G. (eds.) The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes: Legal, Political and Philosophical Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 212–42. Available at: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2066563.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J.K. (2014) “A Pluralist Approach to the Practice of Human Rights,” Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, [Electronic]: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2490964 [Accessed 23 September 2014].Google Scholar
Schaffer, J.K. (2015) “The Co-originality of Human Rights and Democracy in an International Order,” International Theory, vol. 7 no. 1, pp. 96124.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J.K. (2017) “Mellan Aktivism och Ambivalens: Norden och de Mänskliga Rättigheterna,” Retfærd: Nordic Journal of Law and Justice, vol. 40 no. 1.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J.K., Føllesdal, A. & Ulfstein, G. (2013) “International Human Rights and the Challenge of Legitimacy,” in. Føllesdal, A. Schaffer, J.K. & Ulfstein, G. (eds.) The Legitimacy of International Human Rights Regimes: Legal, Political and Philosophical Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 131. Available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2276835.Google Scholar
Scheingold, S.A. (2010) The Politics of Rights: Lawyers, Public Policy, and Political Change, Michigan: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Schmitz, H.P. (2004) “Domestic and Transnational Perspectives on Democratization,” International Studies Review, vol. 6 no. 3, pp. 403–26.Google Scholar
Shapiro, I. (2005) The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, B. (2009) Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2009) “Are Human Rights Essentially Triggers for Intervention?,” Philosophy Compass, vol. 4 no. 6, pp. 938–50.Google Scholar
De Tocqueville, A. (1997) Memoir on Pauperism, London: Civitas.Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2011) “Global Justice and Practice-Dependence: Conventionalism, Institutionalism, Functionalism,” Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 19 no. 4, pp. 399418.Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2012) “In What Sense Are Human Rights Political? A Preliminary Exploration,” Political Studies, vol. 60 no. 1, pp. 180–94.Google Scholar

Bibliography

Altman, A. and Wellman, C. H. (2009) A Liberal Theory of International Justice, Oxford: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beitz, C. (2000) “Rawls’s Law of Peoples,” Ethics, vol. 110 no. 4, pp. 669–96.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. (2009) The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brock, G. (2014) “Human Rights,” in Mandle, J. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), A Companion to Rawls, Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2000) “Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World,” Ethics, vol. 110 no. 4, pp. 697721.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2004) Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2010) “The Egalitarianism of Human Rights,” Ethics, vol. 120 no. 4, pp. 679710.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2013) The Heart of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, S, (2002) “Survey Article: Cosmopolitanism and the Law of Peoples,” The Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 10 no. 1, pp. 95123.Google Scholar
Etinson, A. and Liao, M. S. (2012) “Political and Naturalistic Conceptions of Human Rights: A False Polemic?,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, vol. 9, no. 3, pp. 327352.Google Scholar
Freeman, S. (2006) “The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice,” Social Philosophy and Policy, vol. 23 no. 1, pp. 2968.Google Scholar
Gilabert, P. (2011) “Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights,” Political Theory, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 439–67.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. (2008) On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hinsch, W. and Stepanians, M. (2006) “Human Rights as Moral Claim Rights,” in Reidy, D. A. and Martin, R. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples, A Realistic Utopia?, Malden: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Ladwig, B. (2014) “Menschenrechte, Institutionen und moralische Arbeitsteilung,” Politische Vierteljahresschrift, vol. 55 no. 3, pp. 472492.Google Scholar
Moellendorf, D. (1996) “Constructing the Law of Peoples,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 77 no. 2, pp. 132154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickel, J. W. (2006) “Are Human Rights Mainly Implemented by Intervention?,” in Reidy, D. A. and Martin, R. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples. A Realistic Utopia?, Malden: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Nickel, J. W. (2007) Making Sense of Human Rights, Malden: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Nickel, J. W. (2014) “Human Rights,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward, N. Zalta (ed.), [Electronic]: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/rights-human/Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of-Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. (1980) “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory,” The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 77 no. 9, pp. 515–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, with: The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (2010) “Human Rights without Foundations,” in Besson, S. and Tasioulas, J. (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reidy, D. A. (2006) “Political Authority and Human Rights,” in Reidy, D. A. and Martin, R. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples. A Realistic Utopia?, Malden: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Ripstein, A. (2009) Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Soper, P. (1984) A Theory of Law, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2009) “Are Human Rights Essentially Triggers for Intervention?,” Philosophy Compass, vol. 4 no. 6, pp. 938–50.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2012) “The Moral Reality of Human Rights,” in Pogge, T. (ed.), Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right. Who Owes What to the Very Poor? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tesón, F. (1998) A Philosophy of International Law, Colorado: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2012) “In What Sense Are Human Rights Political?,” Political Studies, vol. 60, no. 1, pp. 180–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenar, L. (2004) “The Unity of Rawls’s Work,” The Journal of Moral Philosophy, vol. 1 no. 3, pp. 265–75.Google Scholar

Bibliography

Alter, K. (2013) The New Terrain of International Law: International Courts in International Politics, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. R. (1989) Political Equality, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. R. 2001) “Human Rights as a Common Concern,” American Political Science Review, vol. 95 no. 2, pp. 269282.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. R. (2009) The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Besson, S. (2015) “Human Rights and Constitutional Law: Patterns of Mutual Validation and Legitimation,” in Cruft, R. et al. (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 279299.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2013) The Heart of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carozza, P. G. (2003) “Subsidiarity as a Structural Principle of International Human Rights Law,” American Journal of International Law, vol. 97, pp. 3879.Google Scholar
Christiano, T. (2011) “An Instrumental Argument for a Human Rights to Democracy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 39 no. 2, pp. 142176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J. (2006) “Is There a Human Right to Democracy?” in Sypnowich, Christine (ed.), The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G.A. Cohen, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 226248.Google Scholar
Cruft, R. et al. (2015) “The Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights: An Overview,” in Cruft, R. et al. (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dai, X. (2005) “Why Comply? The Domestic Constituency Mechanism,” International Organization, vol. 59 no. 2, pp. 363398.Google Scholar
Dzehtsiarou, K. (2015) European Consensus and the Legitimacy of the Strasbourg Court, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Follesdal, A. (1997) “The Standing of Illiberal States: Stability and Toleration in John Rawls’ ‘Law of Peoples,’” in Koller, P. & Puhl, K. (ed.), Current Issues in Political Philosophy: Justice in Society and World Order, Vienna: Verlag Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, pp. 165174Google Scholar
Follesdal, A. (2011) “The Distributive Justice of a Global Basic Structure: A Category Mistake?Politics, Philosophy and Economics, vol. 10 no.1, pp. 4665.Google Scholar
Follesdal, A. (2015) “Social Primary Goods,” in Mandle, J. and Reidy, D. (eds.), The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 643647.Google Scholar
Follesdal, A. (2016) “Subsidiarity and International Human Rights Courts: Respecting Self Governance and Protecting Human Rights – or Neither?Law and Contemporary Problems, vol. 79, no.2, pp. 147163.Google Scholar
Freeman, S. (2006) “Distributive Justice and the Law of Peoples,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 243260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilabert, P. (2011) “Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights,” Political Theory, vol. 39 no. 4, pp. 439467.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. (2009) On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, W. N. (1964) Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ignatieff, M. (2001) Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Koskenniemi, M. (2009) “Miserable Comforters: International Relations as New Natural Law,” European Journal of International Relations, vol. 15, 395422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lafont, C. (2012) Global Governance and Human Rights – Spinoza Lectures, Amsterdam: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Lemmens, P. (2015) “The European Court of Human Rights,” in De Baere, G. & Wouters, J. (ed.), The Contribution of International and Supranational Courts to the Rule of Law, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing, pp. 225241.Google Scholar
Liao, S. M. and Etinson, A. (2012) “Political and Naturalistic Conceptions of Human Rights: A False Polemic?Journal of Moral Philosophy, vol. 9, pp.327352.Google Scholar
Luban, D. (2015) “Human Rights Pragmatism and Human Dignity,” in Renzo, M. et al. (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 263.Google Scholar
McCrudden, C. (2014) “Human Rights: Law, Politics and Philosophy,” [Electronic]: www.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/u32/chr_mccrudden_human_rights_law_politics_and_philosophy.pdfGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (2005) “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 33, pp. 113147.Google Scholar
Pogge, T. W. (1994) “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, pp. 195225.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1960) Word and Object, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993a) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993b) “Law of Peoples,” in Shute, S. and Hurley, S. (eds.), On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York: Basic Books, pp. 175216.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (1986) The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (2010) “Human Rights without Foundations,” in Besson, S. and Tasioulas, J. (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 321338.Google Scholar
Salomon, M. E. (2008) Global Responsibility for Human Rights: World Poverty and the Development of International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, A. (2008) “Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality,” Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 16 no. 2, pp. 137164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1997) The Diversity of Objections to Inequality. The Lindley Lecture, Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. (1999) “Democracy as a Universal Value,” Journal of Democracy, vol. 10 no. 3, pp. 317.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. and Dréze, J. (1990) Hunger and Public Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shelton, D. (2006) “Subsidiarity and Human Rights Law,” Human Rights Law Review, vol. 27, pp. 411.Google Scholar
Simmons, B. A. (2009) Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Spano, R. (2014) “Universality or Diversity of Human Rights? Strasbourg in the Age of Subsidiarity,” Human Rights Law Review, vol. 14 no. 3, pp. 116.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2010) “Taking Rights out of Human Rights,” Ethics, vol. 120 no. 4, pp. 647678.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2012a) “Towards a Philosophy of Human Rights,” Current Legal Problems, vol. 65, pp. 130.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2012b) “On the Nature of Human Rights,” in Ernst, G. and Heilinger, J. (eds.), The Philosophy of Human Rights: Contemporary Controversies, Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 1761.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2013) “Human Rights, Legitimacy and International Law,” American Journal of Jurisprudence, vol. 58 no. 1, pp. 125.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2017) “Exiting the Hall of Mirrors: Morality and Law in Human Rights,” in Campbell, T. & Bourne, K. (ed.), Confronting Moral, Political and Legal Approaches to Human Rights, (to Appear) London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Tierney, B. (1997) The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 1150–1625, Grand Rapids/Cambridge: Eerdmans Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Tsereteli, N. (2015) Legal Validity and Legitimacy of the Pilot Judgment Procedure of the European Court of Human Rights PhD dissertation, Oslo: University of Oslo.Google Scholar
United Nations General Assembly (1966) International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.Google Scholar
Valentini, L. (2012) “In What Sense Are Human Rights Political?Political Studies, vol. 60 no. 1, pp. 180194.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2013) “Human Rights: A Critique of the Raz/Rawls Approach,” NYU School of Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 13–32.Google Scholar
Zuckert, M. P. (1996) “Toward a Theory of Corrective Federalism: The United States Constitution, Federalism, and Rights,” in Katz, E. & Tarr, G. A. (ed.), Federalism and Rights, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 76100.Google Scholar

Bibliography

Apel, K. O. (2002) “Regarding the Relationship of Morality, Law, and Democracy: On Habermas’s Philosophy of Law from a Transcendental Pragmatic Point of View,” in Aboulafia, M., Bookman, M., and Kemp, C. (eds.), Habermas and Pragmatism, New York: Routledge, pp. 1730.Google Scholar
Baynes, K. (2009) “Discourse Ethics and the Political Conception of Human Rights,” Ethics and Global Policy, vol. 2 no. 1, pp. 121.Google Scholar
Benhabib, S. (2013) “Reason-Giving and Rights-Bearing: Constructing the Subject of Rights,” Constellations, vol. 20 no. 1, pp. 3851.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2013) The Heart of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A. (2006) “Taking the Human Out of Human Rights,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 150–68.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jean. (2004) “Whose Sovereignty? Empire versus International Law,” Ethics and International Affairs, vol. 18 no. 3, pp. 124.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua.(2004) “Minimalism About Human Rights: The Most We Can Hope For?,” The Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 12 no. 2, pp. 190213.Google Scholar
Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.) (2011) Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Flynn, J. (2014) Reframing the Intercultural Dialogue on Human Rights, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Forst, R. (2011) “The Justification of Justice: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue,” In Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, pp. 153180.Google Scholar
Forst, R. (2012) The Right to Justification, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Gilabert, P. (2015) “Human Rights, Human Dignity, and Power,” In Cruft, R., Liao, M., and Renzo, M. (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 196213.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. (2008). On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1988) “Law and Morality,” in McMurrin, S. M. (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 8, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, pp. 217279.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1995) “Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s Political Liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92 no. 3, pp. 109131.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (2001) The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1998a) The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1998b) “Reasonable versus True, or, the Morality of Worldviews,” in Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, pp. 75101.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (2006) The Divided West, London: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (2010) “The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights,” Metaphilosophy, vol. 41 no. 1, pp. 464480.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (2011) “A Reply to My Critics,” In Finlayson, J. G. and Freyenhagen, F. (eds.), Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, pp. 283304.Google Scholar
Hedrick, T. (2010) Rawls and Habermas: Reason, Pluralism, and the Claims of Political Philosophy, Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Ingram, D. (2003) “Between Political Liberalism and Postnational Cosmopolitanism: Toward an Alternative Theory of Human Rights,” Political Theory, vol. 31 no. 3, pp. 259291.Google Scholar
Ingram, D. (2010) Habermas: Introduction and Analysis, Ithaca: Cornell University.Google Scholar
Ingram, D. (2014a) “Pluralizing Constitutional Review in International Law: A Critical Theory Approach,” Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, special issue: Law and Philosophy: Foundations and Hermeneutics, vol. 70 no. 2–3, pp. 261286.Google Scholar
Ingram, D. (2014b) “Reconciling Positivism and Realism: Kelsen and Habermas on Democracy and Human Rights,” Philosophy and Social Criticism, vol. 40 no. 3, pp. 237267.Google Scholar
Lafont, C. (2014) Human Rights, Sovereignty, and the Right to Protect. Critical Theory in Critical Times, New York: Columbia.Google Scholar
Letsas, G. (2014) “Review of Allen Buchanan’s The Heart of Human Rights,” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews [Electronic Journal], May 5th 2014.Google Scholar
Macleod, A. (2006) “Rawls’s Narrow Doctrine of Human Rights,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 134149.Google Scholar
Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.) (2006) Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
Nickel, J, (2006) “Are Human Rights Mainly Implemented by Intervention?,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 263–77.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2000) Women and Human Development, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, T. (2006) “Do Rawls’s Two Theories of Justice Fit Together?,” in Martin, R. and Reidy, D. A. (eds.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, pp. 206225.Google Scholar
Pogge, T. (2008) World Poverty and Human Rights, 2nd Edition, London: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993a) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1993b) “Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92 no. 3, pp. 132–80.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (1999) Development as Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Bibliography

Kant, ’s works are cited from the Akademische Ausgabe (Berlin, 1898 onwards) and Kant’s Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). The pagination in English is given second. A small number of translations also refer to Kant’s Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)Google Scholar
Beitz, C. (2009) The Idea of Human Rights, Oxford University Press: Oxford.Google Scholar
Bingham, T. (2011) The Rule of Law, London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Bird, G. (2006) The Revolutionary Kant, Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Cassese, A. (2001) International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clapham, A. (2007) Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cmiel, K. (2004) “The Recent History of Human Rights,” American Historical Review, vol. 109 no. 1, pp. 117–35.Google Scholar
Glendon, M. A. (2001) A World Made New, New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Green, L. (2003) “Legal Positivism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, [Electronic]: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/#tocGoogle Scholar
Griffin, R. (2008) On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1959) Principles of International Law, New York: Reinhardt and Company.Google Scholar
Klabbers, J. (2013) International Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moeckli, D., Shah, S. and Sivakumaran, S. (2010) International Human Rights Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pendas, D. O. (2012) “Toward a New Politics? On the Recent Historiography of Human Rights,” Contemporary European History, vol. 21 no. 1, pp. 95111.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Reidy, D. A. (2007) On the Philosophy of Law, Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Williams, H. (2007) “Kantian Cosmopolitan Right,” Politics and Ethics Review, vol. 3 no. 1, pp. 5772.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×