Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
  • Get access
    Check if you have access via personal or institutional login
  • Cited by 3
  • Print publication year: 1994
  • Online publication date: June 2012

7 - Is there an objective spirit?

Summary

In his book on Hegel, Charles Taylor presents the Hegelian notion of an objective spirit, and defends it against the objections to which it is commonly subjected. He does not ask us to endorse the concept wholesale. As we know, Hegel's philosophy of spirit, of which the philosophy of objective spirit forms the second part, serves a number of functions in the system. As Taylor points out, the doctrine has become most foreign to us on precisely the point which Hegel would have deemed most important, namely, when it is seen as a theodicy which makes of the human community a kind of corpus mysticum through which the divine can achieve its full presence. The concept of objective spirit does, however, possess a certain value if it is taken rather as the descendant of the notion of the ‘spirit of the laws’ which was elaborated by Montesquieu. The defence of this notion would simply be that a concept of this kind is required in the ‘moral’ or ‘social sciences’ (Geisteswissenschaften). As Taylor has remarked, however, the objections voiced by our contemporaries to the Hegelian doctrine bear not only on Hegelian theodicy, but also on the very idea of a social thought, or of a social form of thought. As faithful heirs of the Enlightenment project, many of our contemporaries believe that thought can only occur in a personal form. In other words, it is senseless, in their view, to construe thought, or meaning, or representation, etc., without implying that it is someone's thought, that of a personal thinking subject.