Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-06-04T14:30:46.707Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 3 - Language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2022

Get access

Summary

Wittgenstein said that there can be no private language. If on a deserted island I bump my toe on a stone and call the darned thing ‘clink’, and the next time I call it ‘clunk’, there is no one to correct me. My reference to things with a word can fly off in all directions. If I think something I cannot ‘unthink’ it. It is, Wittgenstein said, like having pain: it is odd to say that you ‘think’ you have a pain.

I accept from G. H. Mead (2011) that language started out with bodily gestures and expressions and vocal gestures such as cries and shouts. Gestures and language are needed to learn from interaction with people, in communication, sharing and opposing meanings of words and gestures. As Mead argued, we develop a sense of self and consciousness by expressing ourselves, observing reactions of others, reacting to those and observing our reaction. Perhaps that is why young people flock together and find it difficult to observe the corona rule against proximity. On the other hand, distance contact by telephone rather than bodily proximity has also increased distance. Gestures and facial expressions are still important in communication, so that during the lockdown due to corona, communication in writing only did not suffice and we had to bring in visual contact, via applications like Zoom. But to many that is a poor substitute for physical proximity and bodily contact.

The old idea of meaning was that it is reference. With the word ‘chair’ we refer to an object of that nature, or all objects of that kind. This leads to the issue of knowledge and truth as correspondence of ideas with items in reality. As discussed before, Kant raised fundamental doubt on this. From the Kantian view, it is very dubious to claim that words, linguistic expressions, actually do refer in that sense.

Reference, I proposed earlier, is intentional, not ontological: people intend to refer to reality, leaving aside whether, or in what sense, and to what extent, they actually do. However, words are not always only intended to refer.

Type
Chapter
Information
Process Philosophy
A Synthesis
, pp. 53 - 66
Publisher: Anthem Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×