Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xm8r8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-15T03:45:49.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Propositions: General Criteria

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

John Gerring
Affiliation:
Boston University
Get access

Summary

The logic of historical thought is not a formal logic of deductive inference. It is not a symmetrical structure of Aristotelian syllogisms, or Ramean dialectics, or Boolean equations. Nor is it precisely an inductive logic, like that of Mill or Keynes or Carnap. It consists neither in inductive reasoning from the particular to the general, nor in deductive reasoning from the general to the particular. Instead, it is a process of adductive reasoning in the simple sense of adducing answers to specific questions, so that a satisfactory explanatory “fit” is obtained … History is, in short, a problem-solving discipline. A historian is someone (anyone) who asks an open-ended question about past events and answers it with selected facts which are arranged in the form of an explanatory paradigm.

–David Hackett Fischer

The foregoing passage, drawn from Fischer's classic, Historians' Fallacies, proposes that history is a problem-solving exercise. Why did the Roman Empire fall? What factors accounted for the industrial revolution in Europe? Who assassinated John F. Kennedy? History is the study of such questions, just as sociology is the study of a rather different (though not unrelated) set of questions. Arguably, every field and subfield within the social sciences takes its cue from a set of core questions. Anthropology, economics, history, political science, psychology, and sociology are all problem-solving disciplines, in this minimal sense.

But where do these questions come from? What distinguishes a good question from a bad or uninteresting one?

Type
Chapter
Information
Social Science Methodology
A Criterial Framework
, pp. 89 - 117
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×