Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-2pzkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-11T18:50:02.994Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Logic and language: Humanistic logic

from PART 2 - PHILOSOPHY AND ITS PARTS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

LOGIC: CRITICISMS BY HUMANISTS

Introduction

Humanism encountered Aristotelian logic as a central component in the scholastic curriculum, a curriculum which it was humanists' ambition to replace with one more appropriate to a ‘classical’ education. Because it was from their position as teachers of the liberal arts that humanists challenged traditional treatments of logic, their interventions in the field have tended to be characterised as crucially disruptive and destructive, and they have been blamed for producing a hiatus in the development of formal logic from which the discipline has barely recovered. Although recent scholarly work has established humanist dialectic as an area of energetic intellectual activity, the secondary literature continues to give credence to the view that the activity was fragmented and eclectic, and continues to assume a fundamental lack of relevance of developments associated with humanist dialectic to the development of logic proper.

This is, however, to underestimate the importance of Renaissance developments in logic, both in the context of specifically humanist interventions and, perhaps even more importantly, in the light of cross-influence and interaction between humanist and scholastic scholarly contributions. In spite of scholastic logicians' insistence on the formal nature of their concern with ratiocination (as opposed to the more ‘linguistic’ interest of terminists and moderni), technical exploration of argument forms was inevitably conducted with at least sidelong glances at other available approaches. Furthermore, separate specialist discussions do not remain neatly cut off from one another in the context of the curriculum and the textbook. Thus (to take a single example) the Aristotelian Agostino Nifo chooses to react to the humanist Lorenzo Valla's reformulated dialectic in his Dialectica ludicra (‘Schoolroom dialectic/Playful dialectic’), rather than to dismiss it out of hand.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agricola, Rudolph (1539). De inventione dialectica, Cologne (repr. Nieuwkoop, 1967).Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1516–17). Dialectica cum quinque vocibus Porphyrii, trans. Argyropulos, J., comment. Eck, J., 2 vols., Augsburg.Google Scholar
Aristotle on Dialectic (1968). ed. Owen, G. E. L., Oxford.Google Scholar
Armstrong, C. J. R. (1976). ‘The dialectical road to truth: the dialogue’, French Renaissance Studies, 1540–1570, ed. Sharratt, P., Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Ashworth, E. J. (1974a). Language and Logic in the Post-Medieval Period, Dordrecht–Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashworth, E. J. (1976). ‘Agostino Nifo's reinterpretation of medieval logic’, Rivista critica di storia della filosofia, 31.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1982). ‘Medicine, experience and logic’, in Science and Speculation: Studies in Hellenistic Theory and Practice, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Bird, O. (1960). ‘The formalizing of topics in medieval logic’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, O. (1962). ‘The tradition of logical topics: Aristotle to Ockham’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boethius, (1978). De topicis differentiis, ed. and comment. Stump, E., Ithaca.Google Scholar
Boethius: His Life, Thouτand Influence (1981). ed. Gibson, M., Oxford.Google Scholar
Boisset, J. (1967). Melanchthon, éducateur de l'Allemagne, Paris.Google Scholar
Bolgar, R. R. (1954). The Classical Tradition and Its Beneficiaries, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruyère, N. (1984). Méthode et dialectique dans l'oeuvre de La Ramée, Paris.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1982a). ‘The origins of non-deductive inference’, in Science and Speculation, ed. Barnes, J. et al., Cambridge.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1982b). ‘Gods and heaps’, in Language and Logos, ed. Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M. C., Cambridge.Google Scholar
Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (1982). ed. Kretzmann, N., Kenny, A. and Pinborg, J., Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomarat, J. (1981). Grammaire et rhétorique chez Érasme, 2 vols., Paris.Google Scholar
Cranz, F. E. andSchmitt, C. B. (1984). A Bibliography of Aristotle Editions, 1501–1600, 2nd edn, Baden-Baden.Google Scholar
Crescini, A. (1965). Le origini del metodo analitico: il Cinquecento, Udine.Google Scholar
Dear, P. R. (1984). ‘Marin Mersenne and the probabilistic roots of “mitigated scepticism”’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraunce, Abraham (1588). The Lawiers Logike, London.Google Scholar
Garin, E. (1969). L'età nuova, Naples.Google Scholar
Gilbert, N. W. (1960). Renaissance Concepts of Method, New York.Google Scholar
Gouveia, Antonio (1543). Pro Aristotele responsio adversus Petri Rami calumnias, Paris.Google Scholar
Grafton, A. and Jardine, L. (1982). ‘Humanism and the school of Guarino: a problem of evaluation’, Past and Present, 96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grafton, A. (1986). From Humanism to the Humanities, London.Google Scholar
Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies, London.Google Scholar
Heath, T. (1971). ‘Logical grammar, grammatical logic and humanism in three German universities’, Studies in the Renaissance, 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howell, W. S. (1956). Logic and Rhetoric in England, 1500–1700, Princeton.Google Scholar
Jardine, L. (1974a). Francis Bacon: Discovery and the Art of Discourse, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Jardine, L. (1974b). ‘The place of dialectic teaching in sixteenth-century Cambridge’, Studies in the Renaissance, 21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardine, L. (1977). ‘Lorenzo Valla and the intellectual origins of humanist dialectic’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardine, L. (1981). ‘Dialectic or dialectical rhetoric? Agostino Nifo's criticism of Lorenzo Valla’, Rivista critica di storia della filosofia, 36.Google Scholar
Jardine, L. (1983). ‘Lorenzo Valla: Academic skepticism and the new humanist dialectic’, in The Skeptical Tradition, ed. Burnyeat, M. F., Berkeley.Google Scholar
Jardine, N. (1976). ‘Galileo's road to truth and the demonstrative regress’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardine, N. (1979). ‘The forging of modern realism: Clavius and Kepler against the sceptics’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardine, N. (1984). The Birth of History and Philosophy of Science, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Kneale, W. and , M. (1962). The Development of Logic, Oxford.Google Scholar
Kristeller, P. O. (1964a). Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance, Stanford.Google Scholar
Marrou, H.-I. (1958). Saint Augustin et la fin de la culture antique, 4th edn, Paris.Google Scholar
Minio-Paluello, L. (1972). Opuscula: The Latin Aristotle, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Mullally, J. P. (1945). The Summulae logicales of Peter of Spain, Notre Dame.Google Scholar
Nuchelmans, G. (1980). Late Scholastic and Humanist Theories of the Proposition, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Ong, W.J. (1958a). Ramus, Method, and the Decay of Dialogue, Cambridge, Mass..Google Scholar
Ong, W.J. (1958b). Ramus and Talon Inventory, Cambridge, Mass.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. (1968). ‘Tithenai ta phainomena’, in Aristotle: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Moravcsik, J., London.Google Scholar
Peter, of Spain (1933–42). Le familiari, ed. Rossi, V. and Bosco, U., 4 vols., Florence.Google Scholar
Poliziano, Angelo (1553). Opera, Basle (repr. Turin, 1971, ed. Maïer, I.).Google Scholar
Porzio, Simone (1551a). An homo bonus vel malus volens fiat, Florence.Google Scholar
Prantl, C. (1855–70). Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande, 4 vols., Leipzig (repr. Graz, 1955).Google Scholar
Reynolds, B. (1955). ‘Latin historiography, a survey 1400–1600’, Studies in the Renaissance, 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Risse, W. (1964). Die Logik der Neuzeit, 1: 1500–1640, Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Risse, W. (1965). Bibliographia logica, 1: 1472–1800, Hildesheim.Google Scholar
Robey, D. (1980). ‘Humanism and education in the early Quattrocento: the De ingenuis moribus of P. P. Vergerio’, Bibliothèque d'humanisme et Renaissance, 42.Google Scholar
Schmitt, C. B. (1983a). Aristotle and the Renaissance, Cambridge, Mass.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmitt, C. B. (1983b). John Case and Aristotelianism in Renaissance England, Kingston–Montreal.Google Scholar
Schüling, H. (1969). Die Geschichte der axiomatischen Methode im 16. und beginnenden 17. Jahrhundert, Hildesheim.Google Scholar
Seifert, A. (1978). Logik zwischen Scholastik und Humanismus: Das Kommentarwerke Johann Ecks, Munich.Google Scholar
Ullman, B. L. (1973). Studies in the Italian Renaissance, 2nd edn, Rome.Google Scholar
Valla, Lorenzo (1982). Repastinatio dialectice et philosophie, ed. Zippel, G., 2 vols., Padua.Google Scholar
Vasoli, C. (1968a). La dialettica e la retorica dell'umanesimo, Milan.Google Scholar
Vasoli, C. (1970). ‘La retorica e la dialettica umanistiche e le origini delle concezioni moderne del “metodo”’, Il Verri, 35–6.Google Scholar
Vives, Juan Luis (1979a). Against the Pseudodialecticians: A Humanist Attack on Medieval Logic, ed. and trans. Guerlac, R., Dordrecht–Boston.Google Scholar
Wright, C. (1976). ‘Language mastery and the sorites paradox’, in Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, ed. Evans, G. and McDowell, J., Oxford.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×