Skip to main content
×
Home
The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon
  • Get access
    Check if you have access via personal or institutional login
  • Cited by 1
  • Cited by
    This book has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by CrossRef.

    Follesdal, Andreas 2016. Getting to justice?. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, p. 1.


    ×
  • Export citation
  • Recommend to librarian
  • Recommend this book

    Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this book to your organisation's collection.

    The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon
    • Online ISBN: 9781139026741
    • Book DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139026741
    Please enter your name
    Please enter a valid email address
    Who would you like to send this to? *
    ×
  • Buy the print book

Book description

John Rawls is widely regarded as one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century, and his work has permanently shaped the nature and terms of moral and political philosophy, deploying a robust and specialized vocabulary that reaches beyond philosophy to political science, economics, sociology, and law. This volume is a complete and accessible guide to Rawls' vocabulary, with over 200 alphabetical encyclopaedic entries written by the world's leading Rawls scholars. From 'basic structure' to 'burdened society', from 'Sidgwick' to 'strains of commitment', and from 'Nash point' to 'natural duties', the volume covers the entirety of Rawls' central ideas and terminology, with illuminating detail and careful cross-referencing. It will be an essential resource for students and scholars of Rawls, as well as for other readers in political philosophy, ethics, political science, sociology, international relations and law.

Reviews

'Rawls' political philosophy evolved over more than 50 years, and he left us with an extremely rich and complex body of work. With more than 200 entries - from abortion to Wittgenstein - this volume is a really useful resource for finding one's way through the full range of his thinking.'

Adam Swift - University of Warwick

'The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon will prove an ideal companion to anyone writing on any topic in political philosophy today … an outstanding collection, both useful and enjoyable to read.'

Source: Political Studies Review

    • Aa
    • Aa
Refine List
Actions for selected content:
Select all | Deselect all
  • View selected items
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Send to Kindle
  • Send to Dropbox
  • Send to Google Drive
  • Send content to

    To send content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about sending content to .

    To send content to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about sending to your Kindle.

    Note you can select to send to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be sent to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

    Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

    Please be advised that item(s) you selected are not available.
    You are about to send:
    ×

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

Please provide a title, maximum of 40 characters.
×

Page 1 of 9



Page 1 of 9


This list contains references from the content that can be linked to their source. For a full set of references and notes please see the PDF or HTML where available.


ElizabethAnderson, . 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109:287–337.

RichardArneson, 1999. “Against Rawlsian Equality of Opportunity,” Philosophical Studies 93:77–112.

RichardArneson, 2000a. “Welfare Should Be the Currency of Justice,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30:497–524.

RichardArneson, 2000b. “Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism,” Ethics 110:339–349.

KennethArrow, . 1973. “Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian Notes on Rawls’s Theory of Justice,” The Journal of Philosophy 70:245–263.

KurtBaier, . 1989. “Justice and the Aims of Political Philosophy,” Ethics 99:771–790.

BrianBarry, 1995. “John Rawls and the Search for Stability,” Ethics 105:874–915.

CharlesBeitz, 2009. The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford University Press).

RichardBrandt, 1990. “The Science of Man and Wide Reflective Equilibrium,” Ethics 100:259–278.

AllenBuchanan, . 2000. “Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World,” Ethics 110:697–721.

JamesBuchanan, and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy (University of Michigan Press).

EamonnCallan, . 1997. Creating Citizens (Oxford University Press).

JosephCarens, . 1987. “Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders,” Review of Politics 49:251–273.

G. A.Cohen, 1989. “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice,” Ethics 99:906–944.

G. A.Cohen, 1993. “Equality of What? On Welfare, Goods, and Capabilities” in The Quality of Life, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (Oxford University Press).

G. A.Cohen, 1995. Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge University Press).

G. A.Cohen, 1997. “Where the Action is: On the Site of Distributive Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 26:3–30.

G. A.Cohen, 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality (Harvard University Press).

G. A.Cohen, 2011. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice, and Other Essays in Political Philosophy, ed. Michael Otsuka (Princeton University Press).

JoshuaCohen, . 2002. “For a Democratic Society” in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge University Press).

JoshuaCohen, 2009b. “Truth and Public Reason,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 37:2–42.

NormanDaniels, , 1985. Just Health Care (Cambridge University Press).

NormanDaniels, , 1996. Justice and Justification: Reflective Equilibrium in Theory and Practice (Cambridge University Press).

NormanDaniels, , 2008b. “Justice between Adjacent Generations: Further Thoughts,” Journal of Political Philosophy 16:475–494.

NormanDaniels, , 2009. “Just Health: Replies and Further Thoughts,” Journal of Medical Ethics 35:36–41.

StephenDarwall, . 1976. “A Defense of the Kantian Interpretation,” Ethics 86:164–170.

JohnDeigh, . 1983. “Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique,” Ethics 93:225–245.

GeraldDoppelt, . 1981. “Rawls’ System of Justice: A Critique from the Left,” Nous 15:259–307.

GeraldDoppelt, 2009. “The Place of Self-Respect in a Theory of Justice,” Inquiry 52:127–154.

KeithDowding, , Robert Goodin, and Carole Pateman, eds. 2004. Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry (Cambridge University Press).

MichaelDoyle, . 2006. “One World, Many Peoples: International Justice in John Rawls’s The Law of Peoples,” Perspectives on Politics 4:109–120.

BurtonDreben, . 1995. “Cohen’s Carnap, or Subjectivity Is in the Eye of the Beholder” in Science, Politics and Social Practice, ed. Kostas Gavroglu, John Stachel, and Marx Wartofsky (Kluwer).

RonaldDworkin, 2003. “Equality, Luck and Hierarchy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 31:190–198.

ColinFarrelly, . 2007. “Justice in Ideal Theory: A Refutation,” Political Studies 55:844–864.

JulietFloyd, and Sanford Shieh, eds. 2001. Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth Century Philosophy (Oxford University Press).

SamuelFreeman, 2006a. “The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice,” Social Philosophy and Policy 23:29–63.

WilliamGalston, . 1995. “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” Ethics 105:516–534.

AmyGutmann, 1995. “Civic Education and Social Diversity,” Ethics 105:557–579.

AmyGutmann, 2002. “Rawls on the Relationship between Liberalism and Democracy” in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge University Press).

JürgenHabermas, . 1995. “Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’s Liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy 92: 109–131.

PeterHammond, . 1991. “Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: Why and How They Are and Should Be Made” in Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-Being, ed. Jon Elster and John Roemer (Cambridge University Press).

R. M.Hare, 1973b. “Rawls’ Theory of Justice – II,” Philosophical Quarterly 23:241–252.

JohnHarsanyi, . 1953. “Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking,” Journal of Political Economy 61:434–435.

JohnHarsanyi, 1955. “Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility,” Journal of Political Economy 63:309–321.

H. L. A.Hart, 1955. “Are There Any Natural Rights?Philosophical Review 64:175–191.

OliverJohnson, . 1974. “The Kantian Interpretation,” Ethics 85:58–66.

ImmanuelKant, 1996 [1797]. The Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge University Press).

ImmanuelKant, 1997b [1788]. Critique of Practical Reason, ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge University Press).

GeorgeKlosko, 1994a. “Political Obligation and the Natural Duties of Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23:251–270.

GeorgeKlosko, 1994b. “Rawls’s Argument from Political Stability,” Columbia Law Review 94:1882–1897.

FrankKnight, . 1923. “The Ethics of Competition,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 37:579–624.

ChristineKorsgaard, . 1996. The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge University Press).

ChristineKorsgaard, 2009. Self–Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity (Oxford University Press).

LarryKrasnoff, . 1998. “Consensus, Stability, and Normativity in Rawls’s Political Liberalism,” Journal of Philosophy 95:269–292.

LarryKrasnoff, 2014. “Kantian Constructivism” in The Blackwell Companion to Rawls, ed. Jon Mandle and David Reidy (Blackwell).

AndrewKuper, . 2000. “Rawlsian Global Justice: Beyond the Law of Peoples to a Cosmopolitan Law of Persons,” Political Theory 28:640–674.

CharlesLarmore, . 1996. The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge University Press).

MarkLeBar, . 2008. “Aristotelian Constructivism,” Social Philosophy and Policy 25:182–213.

S. A.Lloyd, 1998. “Contemporary Uses of Hobbes’s Political Philosophy” in Rational Commitment and Social Justice, ed. Jules Coleman and Christopher Morris (Cambridge University Press).

GeraldMacCallum, . 1967. “Negative and Positive Freedom,” Philosophical Review 76:312–334.

StephenMacedo, . 1995. “Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls?Ethics 105:468–496.

NormanMalcolm, . 1954. “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations,” Philosophical Review 63:530–559.

JonMandle, . 2005. “Tolerating Injustice” in The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism, ed. Gillian Brock and Harry Brighouse (Cambridge University Press).

JonMandle, 2009. Rawls’s A Theory of Justice: An Introduction (Cambridge University Press).

RexMartin, and David Reidy, eds. 2006. Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? (Blackwell).

ErnanMcMullin, . 1985. “Galilean Idealization,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 16:247–273.

FrankMichelman, . 1972. “In Pursuit of Constitutional Welfare Rights: One View of Rawls’ Theory of Justice,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 121:962–1019.

DarrelMoellendorf, 2009. Global Inequality Matters (Palgrave Macmillan).

DennisMueller, . 2003. Public Choice III (Cambridge University Press).

VéroniqueMunoz-Dardé, . 1988. “John Rawls, Justice in and Justice of the Family,” The Philosophical Quarterly 48:335–352.

LiamMurphy, . 1998. “Institutions and the Demands of Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 27:251–291.

LiamMurphy, and Thomas Nagel. 2002. The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice (Oxford University Press).

R. A.Musgrave, 1974. “Maximin, Uncertainty, and the Leisure Trade-Off,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 88:625–632.

ThomasNagel, 1997. “Justice and Nature,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17:303–321.

ThomasNagel, 2005. “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33:113–147.

MarthaNussbaum, . 1993. “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach” in The Quality of Life, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (Oxford University Press).

MarthaNussbaum, 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge University Press).

MarthaNussbaum, 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge University Press).

MarthaNussbaum, 2011. Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach (Harvard University Press).

MarthaNussbaum, , and Amartya Sen, eds. 1993. The Quality of Life (Oxford University Press).

MartinO’Neill, and Thad Williamson, eds., 2012. Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond (Wiley-Blackwell).

AlanPatten, . 2005. “Should We Stop Thinking about Poverty in Terms of Helping the Poor?Ethics & International Affairs 19:19–27.

R. G.Peffer, 1990. Marxism, Morality, and Social Justice (Princeton University Press).

ThomasPogge, 1992. “Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty,” Ethics 103:48–75.

ThomasPogge, 1994. “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23:195–224.

ThomasPogge, 1995. “Three Problems with Contractarian-Consequentialist Ways of Assessing Social Institutions,” Social Philosophy and Policy 12:241–266.

ThomasPogge, 2000. “On the Site of Distributive Justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 29:137–169.

ThomasPogge, 2002b. “Can the Capability Approach be Justified?Philosophical Topics 30:167–228.

ThomasPogge, 2005. “Human Rights and Global Health: A Research Program,” Metaphilosophy 36:182–209.

ThomasPogge, 2007 [1994]. John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice, trans. Michelle Kosch (Oxford University Press).

ThomasPogge, 2012. “The Health Impact Fund: Enhancing Justice and Efficiency in Global Health,” Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 13:537–559.

JonathanQuong, . 2005. “Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy,” Politics, Philosophy, Economics 4:301–330.

JamesRay, . 1998. “Does Democracy Cause Peace?Annual Review of Political Science 1:27–46.

JosephRaz, . 1998. “Disagreement in Politics,” American Journal of Jurisprudence 43:25–52.

DavidReidy, . 1996. “Education for Citizenship in a Pluralist Liberal Democracy,” Journal of Value Inquiry 30:25–42.

DavidReidy, 2004. “Rawls on International Justice: A Defense,” Political Theory 32:291–319.

DavidReidy, 2006a. “Political Authority and Human Rights” in Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? ed. Rex Martin and David Reidy (Blackwell).

DavidReidy, 2006b. “Three Human Rights Agendas,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 19:237–254.

DavidReidy, 2007. “Reciprocity and Reasonable Disagreement: From Liberal to Democratic Legitimacy,” Philosophical Studies 132:243–291.

DavidReidy, 2010. “Human Rights and Liberal Toleration,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 23:287–317.

WalterRiker, . 2009. “The Democratic Peace is Not Democratic: On Behalf of Rawls’s Decent Societies,” Political Studies 57:617–638.

MathiasRisse, . 2005. “Do We Owe the Global Poor Assistance or Rectification?Ethics & International Affairs 19:9–18.

T. M.Scanlon, 2003. The Difficulty of Tolerance (Cambridge University Press).

T. M.Scanlon, 2006. “Justice, Responsibility, and the Demands of Equality” in The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G. A. Cohen, ed. Christine Sypnowich (Oxford University Press).

SamuelScheffler, 2003b. “What Is Egalitarianism?Philosophy and Public Affairs 31:5–39.

DavidSchmidtz, . 2011. “Nonideal Theory: What It Is and What It Needs to Be,” Ethics 121:772–796.

JohnSearle, . 1969. Speech Acts (Cambridge University Press).

AmartyaSen, 1985. “Well-being, Agency, and Freedom: The Dewey Lectures 1984,” Journal of Philosophy 82:169–221.

AmartyaSen, 1993. “Capability and Well-Being” in The Quality of Life, ed. Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (Oxford University Press).

DannyShapiro, . 2007. Is the Welfare State Justified? (Cambridge University Press).

HenryShue, . 1975. “Liberty and Self-Respect,” Ethics 85:195–203.

A. John.Simmons, 2010. “Ideal and Nonideal Theory,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 38:5–36.

PhilipSoper, . 1984. A Theory of Law (Harvard University Press).

Kok-ChorTan, . 1998. “Liberal Toleration in Rawls’ Law of Peoples,” Ethics 108:276–295.

CharlesTaylor, . 1985. Philosophical Papers, volume II, Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge University Press).

LarryTemkin, . 2003. “Equality, Priority, or What?Economics and Philosophy 19:61–88.

PeterVallentyne, 2011. “Nozick’s Libertarian Theory of Justice” in Anarchy, State, and Utopia – A Reappraisal, ed. Ralf Bader and John Meadowcroft (Cambridge University Press).

JeremyWaldron, . 1986. “John Rawls and the Social Minimum,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 3:21–33.

PaulWeithman, 2011. Why Political Liberalism? (Oxford University Press).

LeifWenar, . 1995. “Political Liberalism: An Internal Critique,” Ethics 106:32–62.

LeifWenar, and Branko Milanovic. 2009. “Are Liberal Peoples Peaceful?Journal of Political Philosophy 17:462–486.

KnutWicksell, . 1958. “A New Principle of Just Taxation,” in Classics in the Theory of Public Finance, ed. R. A. Musgrave and A. T. Peacock (Macmillan).

AndrewWilliams, . 1995. “The Revisionist Difference Principle,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25:257–281.

BernardWilliams, 1981. Moral Luck (Cambridge University Press).

IrisYoung, 2006. “Taking the Basic Structure Seriously,” Perspectives on Politics 4:91–97.