Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T04:39:28.766Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Changing Status of Moral Authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 June 2011

Donald R. Burrill
Affiliation:
California State College at Los Angeles, Calif. 90032

Extract

King Creon had, for political reasons, forbidden the burial of Polyneices. But Antigone, for religious ones, defied Creon and buried her brother. She justified her act by drawing a distinction between the changing regulations of a human ruler and the eternal laws of heaven. Creon speaks: “Knowest thou the edict that forbade this deed?” Antigone answers: I knew it. Why, how else? for it was public. Creon: And such laws thou couldst dare to overstep? Antig.: Yes; for it was not Zeus that published them … I did not deem your edicts of such force That a mere mortal could o'erride the Gods' Unwritten, never-failing ordinances. For these live not today nor yesterda But always; none knows when they first came forth.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © President and Fellows of Harvard College 1966

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Whitney J. Oates and Eugene O'Neill, Jr., eds., The Complete Greek Drama, trans. R. C. Jebb (New York, 1946).

2 The Holy Bible, Revised Standard Version, Joshua 7:25.

3 Macdonald, Margaret, “Ethical and Ceremonial Uses of Language,” Black, Max, ed., Philosophical Analysis (New York, 1950).Google Scholar

4 See Sir Henry Sumner Maine, Ancient Law (London, 1906), 1–6; also Crane Brinton, A History of Western Morals (New York, 1959), 32–33.

5 Crime and Custom in Savage Society (London, 1949).

6 Laws, Book IV.

7 Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, Ch. 9; Book X, Ch. 8.

8 John Dewey, The Quest for Certainty (New York, 1929), 91.

9 Economic Philosophy (New York, 1964), 11.

10 (New York, 1964).

11 Ibid., 28.

12 Ethics and Language (New Haven, 1944).

13 An error that I doubt naturalists have actually committed. Mill certainly did not assume ethics to be a deducible logical relation between the happiness principle and moral decisions. The relation is inductive in the same manner as psychological or sociological theories are inductively related to individual or social behavior.

14 Value and Obligation (New York, 1964), 75.

15 “On Grading,” Mind 59, 169.

16 “Empiricism and Value Judgments,” The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp (La Salle, 1963), 840.

17 Loc. cit., 196.

18 See George H. von Wright, Norms and Actions (New York, 1963), 77.

19 “The Authority of Moral Judgments,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 12 (1952), 521.

20 On the Knowledge of Good and Evil (New York, 1955), 238.

21 Ibid., 239.

22 See the significant contribution of H. L. A. Hart, Alf Ross, H. Kelsen.

23 “Religion, Nature and the Autonomy of Law,” Ethics 73/1 (Oct., 1962), 8.

24 Reconstruction in Philosophy (New York, 1958), Chapter 7.