Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T03:40:37.923Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The misleading simplicity of advance directives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 February 2011

Cees M. P. M. Hertogh*
Affiliation:
Professor in Geriatric Ethics, EMGO Institute for Health and Care Research, VU University Medical Center, Amsterdam, the Netherlands Email: cmpm.hertogh@vumc.nl
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

The question of what constitutes a dignified old age has always been a topic of philosophical enquiry. Already in the writings of the stoic philosophers we can find relevant contributions to an ethic of “successful” aging. Seneca, for instance, reflects upon the pleasures of old age in several of his famous “Letters to Lucilius” (Seneca, 1967). However, he also writes about the bad years that may lie ahead and confides to his pupil: “Do not hear me with reluctance as if my statement applied directly to you, but weigh what I have to say. It is this. I shall not abandon old age, if old age preserves me intact for myself, and intact as regards to the better part of myself; but if old age begins to shatter my mind, and pull its various faculties to pieces, if it leaves me, not life, but only the breath of life, I shall rush out of a house that is crumbling and tottering . . .”

Type
Guest Editorial
Copyright
Copyright © International Psychogeriatric Association 2011

The question of what constitutes a dignified old age has always been a topic of philosophical enquiry. Already in the writings of the stoic philosophers we can find relevant contributions to an ethic of “successful” aging. Seneca, for instance, reflects upon the pleasures of old age in several of his famous “Letters to Lucilius” (Seneca, Reference Seneca and Gummere1967). However, he also writes about the bad years that may lie ahead and confides to his pupil: “Do not hear me with reluctance as if my statement applied directly to you, but weigh what I have to say. It is this. I shall not abandon old age, if old age preserves me intact for myself, and intact as regards to the better part of myself; but if old age begins to shatter my mind, and pull its various faculties to pieces, if it leaves me, not life, but only the breath of life, I shall rush out of a house that is crumbling and tottering . . .”

Much has changed since Seneca wrote these words. Today, more and more people age successfully, enjoying increased physical and mental fitness and a high level of emotional and personal well-being. However, for those entering the fourth age, growing old still takes its toll, because of impending losses in learning potential and mental functioning and a strongly rising prevalence of dementia. In view of this grim perspective, Seneca's position appears to be far from anachronistic. For what dignity is there in being left with “only the breath of life”?

The instrument of the “advance directive” – or “living will” as this document was originally named when it was first introduced in 1969 – can be seen as a contemporary, originally American alternative, to the more drastic solution to this challenging question proposed by Seneca in his day. In his book Life's Dominion, legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin – a strong advocate of advance directives – presents the case of Margo, a once intellectually vibrant and independent woman who, as a consequence of dementia, has become but a shadow of her former self and is now totally dependent on the care of strangers. Although there are no signs of suffering, Margo lives a life she would never have chosen if she still had a voice to speak. Yet, as Dworkin hypothesizes, if she had executed an advance directive, refusing any and all treatment, then pneumonia could offer her a dignified way out of her deteriorated state (Dworkin, Reference Dworkin1993).

Over the years, the “Dworkinian” point of view has received much support. But do advance directives really offer a realistic solution to the complex problem that called them into existence? What can we learn in this respect from more than 30 years of experience, at least in the USA, with advance directives? This is a relevant question in view of the fact that more and more countries are issuing legislation regarding advance directives. In addition, international organizations such as Alzheimer Europe (2005) promote the use of advance directives for decisions covering a wide range of health-related issues, including treatment and care.

Definition and roles

A widely accepted definition describes advance directives as “written instructions executed by decisionally capable adults that pertain to future medical treatment preferences of the party executing the document. These directives take effect only if the patient is decisionally incapacitated at the time that specific decisions need to be made” (Kapp, Reference Kapp1995).

Advance directives can be classified into two categories: treatment directives and proxy directives. A treatment directive refers to a document specifying what kind of treatment the author desires under specific conditions in the event of incapacity, while a proxy directive empowers another person (e.g. health care proxy or durable power of attorney) to make decisions on behalf of the author. Both types of directives can also be combined (de Boer et al., Reference de Boer, Hertogh, Dröes, Jonker and Eefsting2010). Morally, advance directives are rooted in the doctrine of informed consent. With expanding technology they became a key issue of the autonomy based bio-ethics movement of the 1970s. Central to this ethic is the judgment that autonomy is the core value to guide medical decision-making. Respecting autonomy allows individuals to shape their lives according to their personal values and preferences. In case of incompetence, when contemporaneous autonomy is no longer possible, so called “precedent” or “prospective autonomy” in the form of previous statements and expressed beliefs relevant to the treatment issues at stake should govern the outcome (Dworkin, Reference Dworkin1986). This is especially true for advance statements that refuse treatment, since the informed consent doctrine holds that medical interventions are only allowed in the case of free and uncoerced consent – and consent can be withheld, even years ahead (Vezzoni, Reference Vezzoni2005).

Of course, advance directives were not designed with an exclusive focus on dementia and patients’ fear of having to live through all its stages. In fact, their promotion was highly influenced by much-debated court cases on end-of-life decision-making in patients in a persistent vegetative state (PVS), such as the Karen Ann Quinlan case (Brown, Reference Brown2003; Kirschner, Reference Kirschner2005). Such cases enforced patients’ feelings of powerlessness with regard to receiving care consistent with their preferences in case of incapacity. Hence, the anticipated role of advance directives was first and foremost to allow people to refuse “death-delaying” interventions in the event of incompetency and terminal illness or PVS.

Initially, the enthusiasm for advance directives was largely ideological, inspired as it was by the “new kid on the block” in medical ethics: the emphasis on patient autonomy (Faden and Beauchamp, Reference Faden and Beauchamp1986). Empirical knowledge on the subject was largely unavailable at the time and it was more or less taken for granted that advance directives would have a positive effect on medical culture and decision-making. However, these supposed positive effects were based on the assumption that the author of the advance directive is in a better position now than others will be in the future to decide how treatment decisions are to be made in the event of incompetency. Further, the author practices “auto-paternalism” by denying herself the right to a change of mind at a later moment and subordinates the interests of the future incompetent person to her prospective autonomy, just as Dworkin did in Margo's case. Moreover, Dworkin contended that prior choices should be implemented even if the patient with dementia explicitly expresses different wishes (Dworkin, Reference Dworkin1986). Critical reflection on these premises and their consequences was scarce at the time and Rebecca Dresser (Reference Dresser, Binstock, Post and Whitehouse1992; Reference Dresser1995; Reference Dresser2003) was one of the few scholars who drew attention to the potential conflict between prior values of the still competent person and the welfare interests of the later incompetent person.

From theory to practice

With experience, however, came awareness of the problems, and empirical research gradually revealed that the reality was far from what proponents of advance directives had expected it to be. Since the disappointing findings of the first empirical study into the practice of advance directives, the SUPPORT study (SUPPORT, 1995), a plethora of research articles and critical reviews have been published and multiple interventions were designed to stimulate the uptake of advance directives, including several attempts to redesign them in order to increase their practicability and relevance to decision-making. Of the problems that all this research has revealed, some are more practical, while others are more fundamental in nature. First of all, with the exception of one recent study suggesting a prevalence of 67.6% in a cohort of Americans aged 60 years and older (Silveira et al., Reference Silveira, Kim and Langa2010), the overall frequency of advance directives continues to be low, notwithstanding the existence of legal rules encouraging their completion, such as the Patient Self-Determination Act (PDSA) in the USA that came into force in 1990 and obliges hospitals and nursing homes to provide written information to all adults concerning their right to formulate an advance directive. Secondly, when they are completed, advance directives are often not complied with because they contain vague or ambiguous instructions, thus raising the question whether the author really understood what he conveyed to paper (Teno et al., Reference Teno1997). One way of dealing with this problem is to standardize advance statements on treatment preferences and/or stimulate consultation with health professionals when one considers drafting an advance directive (e.g. Emanuel and Emanuel, Reference Emanuel and Emanuel1989). In practice however, physicians are seldom involved in this stage and the presentation of the directive is customarily the end of the inquiry instead of the beginning (Vezzoni, Reference Vezzoni2005). In addition, when advance directives do contain clear information, it may nevertheless be uncertain whether the author wants his directive to be followed. Research has revealed that authors regularly find that their families and physicians should have “leeway” to override their directives (Sehgal et al., Reference Sehgal, Gailbraith, Chesney, Schoenfield, Charles and Lo1992). And to further complicate matters, it has been shown that proxies do a poor job in interpreting advance directives, as they are frequently biased by their own treatment preferences (Fagerlin et al., Reference Fagerlin, Ditto, Danks, Houts and Smucker2001).

However, the most poignant problems of advance directives pertain to the stability of preferences and the effects of advance directives on the quality of care-giving in the final stage of life.

Stability of preferences over time

Studies on the stability of treatment preferences have produced varying results and many of them are based on hypothetical not real-life decisions (Kirschner, Reference Kirschner2005). We know, however, that our anticipatory beliefs often fail to recognize our ability to adapt and that it is notoriously difficult to imagine how one's current preferences will hold in a given situation (such as dementia) that one has never experienced before (Hertogh et al., Reference Hertogh, Boer, Dröes and Eefsting2007). In general, preferences for life sustaining treatments are probably most stable in people with a stable health condition. Hence, advance directives are most applicable in case of acute (traumatic) disorders, such as severe brain injury resulting in PVS (Kirschner, Reference Kirschner2005). Unstable health, on the other hand, will lead to changing preferences. This phenomenon is often so impressive that it has been termed “the disability paradox”: a life that was once despised before the advent of chronic disease is accepted and even embraced with advancing illness (Albrecht and Devlieger, Reference Albrecht and Devlieger1999). Dementia is no exception to this “rule”, as is testified by a growing body of research on living with dementia from the patients’ perspective (de Boer et al., Reference de Boer, Hertogh, Dröes, Riphagen, Jonker and Eefsting2007). People do not become demented overnight; instead the gradual course of the disease allows for adaptation and a shift in response. As a rule of thumb, one may say that vulnerable persons often change their minds, particularly when their minds have changed (Kirschner, Reference Kirschner2005). But what if they forget to change their advance directive, or are no longer able to do so? Here we touch upon a key obstacle for complying with advance directives.

Effect on care-giving in the final stage of life

In several jurisdictions the condition of applicability of advance directives is restricted to terminal illness or imminent death situations; in others (e.g. the Netherlands) such restrictions do not exist and advance directives take effect from the outset of decisional incapacity. In dementia and associated neurodegenerative disorders, however, mental incapacity precedes the end of life and related medical decisions for an extended period. During this period patients may enjoy relatively good physical health, although they may suffer from intercurrent ailments (e.g. respiratory and urinary tract infections), exacerbation of comorbidity (e.g. heart failure), or trauma (hip fracture). Yet, advance directives offer no guidance with regard to routine medical care, and how they affect the many decisions that have to be taken during the final stage of life is largely unknown (Messinger-Rapport et al., Reference Messinger-Rapport, Baum and Smith2009; Gillick, Reference Gillick2010). Nonetheless, we do have some data. One qualitative study performed in the Netherlands showed that doctors and families of demented patients with an advance directive tend to base their decisions more often on a best interest standard, rather than on the advance directive: the directive is discussed repeatedly but seldom complied with (The et al., Reference The, Pasman, Onwuteaka-Philipsen, Ribbe and van derWal2002). The findings of this study suggest that the conflict between precedent autonomy and current welfare interests, envisaged by Dresser, does not arise as such in actual practice and that the way past preferences are weighed is not influenced by the presence of an advance directive. However, research into the practice of advance directives for euthanasia in dementia has yielded some opposite results (Rurup et al., Reference Rurup, Onwuteaka-Philipsen, van der Heide, van der Wal and van der Maas2005). Although euthanasia was never performed, it can be gathered from this study that advance directives for euthanasia were occasionally respected by adopting a radical non-treatment policy, resulting in undertreatment of burdensome symptoms and insufficient palliative care. Thus, acting in accordance with prior instructions may very well conflict with the duty to protect incompetent persons from harm. In such a situation, strict adherence to an advance directive can result in the opposite of a dignified death and must be considered unethical.

Advance care planning beyond the living will

In view of these dilemmas, what role can be accorded to advance directives in planning for future care? Looking back on more than three decades of prodigious efforts to implement and increase the uptake of advance directives, Muriel Gillick summarizes a growing consensus among experts when she writes that “the directives have been a resounding failure” (Gillick, Reference Gillick2010). They were a naive solution, proposed by an empirically uninformed bio-ethics for a human problem of overwhelming complexity. Yet, notwithstanding this failure, what the practice of advance directives does demonstrate is the relevance for health professionals to invest in helping people to plan ahead, specifically those who are facing a future of uncertainty with a high risk for incapacity, such as patients diagnosed with dementia and their families. The challenge now is to move on from static documents to a more dynamic practice of advance care planning, defined as a dialogical process of supporting patients and their proxies to think ahead and formulate goals of care as they confront the challenge of a progressive illness trajectory (Messinger-Rapport et al., Reference Messinger-Rapport, Baum and Smith2009; Gillick, Reference Gillick2010, Hertogh, Reference Hertogh, Hughes, Lloyd-Williams and Sachs2010). Such advance care planning should start early and must be firmly rooted in doctor-patient communication. It involves clarifying the patient's health status, determining his/her needs and values, and subsequently developing treatment plans that will be reassessed regularly and following any significant change in health. Furthermore, this process should be flexible and sensitive to the patient's views on autonomy. Indeed, the lesson that must be learned from the experience with advance directives is that clearly not everyone desires to manage and control their future (Winzelberg et al., Reference Winzelberg, Hanson and Tulsky2005). Some people prefer to live life one day at a time and many wish to share the burden of decision-making with others, or even delegate this responsibility to their families and health professionals. Nonetheless, a timely start in exploring their ideas about how to deal with the challenges that lie ahead will allow others to better represent the interests of persons with dementia as the illness advances and capacity diminishes. It follows that this approach to advance care planning is time consuming and calls for high quality communicative skills, as well as for preparedness of doctors to take on a (pro)active role, using their knowledge of the disease trajectory in a way that is tailored to the patient's needs and preferences (Hertogh, Reference Hertogh, Hughes, Lloyd-Williams and Sachs2010). Although they may feel a little uncomfortable with this responsibility after so many years of autonomy-centered decision-making, this approach is central to an ethic of care for people with dementia and will better serve their interests and those of their families than the mere signing of a form or the ticking of a checklist of interventions to be accepted or denied.

References

Albrecht, G. L. and Devlieger, P. J. (1999). The disability paradox: high quality of life against all odds. Social Science and Medicine, 48, 977988.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Alzheimer Europe (2005). Advance Directives: A Position Paper, 6/2005. Available at: http://www.alzheimer-europe.org/upload/SPTUNFUYGGOM/downloads/7939D9FD4CEE.pdf.Google Scholar
Brown, B. A. (2003). The history of advance directives. Journal of Gerontological Nursing, 29, 414.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
de Boer, M. E., Hertogh, C. M., Dröes, R. M., Riphagen, I. I., Jonker, C. and Eefsting, J. A. (2007). Suffering from dementia: the patient's perspective. International Psychogeriatics, 19, 10211039.Google ScholarPubMed
de Boer, M. E., Hertogh, C. M., Dröes, R.M., Jonker, C. and Eefsting, J. A. (2010). Advance directives in dementia: issues of validity and effectiveness. International Psychogeriatrics, 22, 201208.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dresser, R. (1992). Autonomy revisited: the limits of anticipatory choices. In Binstock, H., Post, S.G. and Whitehouse, P.J. (eds.), Dementia and Aging. Ethics, Values, and Policy Choices (pp. 7185). Baltimore/London: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Dresser, R. (1995). Dworkin on dementia: elegant theory, questionable policy. Hastings Center Report, 25, 6, 3238.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dresser, R. (2003). Precommitment: a misguided strategy for securing death with dignity. Texas Law Review, 81, 7, 18231847.Google ScholarPubMed
Dworkin, R. (1986). Autonomy and the demented self. The Milbank Quarterly, 64 (Suppl. 2), 416.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dworkin, R. (1993). Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Emanuel, L. L. and Emanuel, E. J. (1989). The medical directive: a new comprehensive advance care document. JAMA, 261, 32883293.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Faden, R. R. and Beauchamp, T. L. (1986). A History and Theory of Informed Consent. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fagerlin, A., Ditto, P. H., Danks, J. H., Houts, R. M. and Smucker, W. D. (2001). Projection in surrogate decisions about life-sustaining treatments. Health Psychology, 20, 166175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillick, M. R. (2010). Reversing the code status of advance directives? New England Journal of Medicine, 362, 12391240.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hertogh, C. M. P. M. (2010). Advance care planning and palliative care in dementia: a view from the Netherlands. In Hughes, J. C., Lloyd-Williams, M., and Sachs, G. A. (eds.), Supportive Care for the Person with Dementia (pp. 271280). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hertogh, C. M. P. M., Boer, M. E. de, Dröes, R. M. and Eefsting, J. A. (2007). Beyond a Dworkinean view on autonomy and advance directives: response to open peer commentaries. American Journal of Bioethics, 7, W46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapp, M. B. (1995). Key Words in Ethics, Law and Aging. New York: Springer Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Kirschner, K. L. (2005). When written advance directives are not enough. Clinics in Geriatric Medicine, 21, 193209.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Messinger-Rapport, B., Baum, E. E. and Smith, M. L. (2009). Advance care planning: beyond the living will. Cleveland Clinic Journal of Medicine, 76, 276285.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rurup, M. L., Onwuteaka-Philipsen, B. D., van der Heide, A., van der Wal, G., and van der Maas, P. J. (2005). Physicians’ experiences with demented patients with advance euthanasia directives in the Netherlands. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 53, 11381144.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sehgal, A., Gailbraith, A., Chesney, M., Schoenfield, P., Charles, G. and Lo, B. (1992). How strictly do dialysis patients want their advance directives followed? JAMA, 267, 5963.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Seneca, (1967). Ad Lucilium Epistulae Morales, trans. Gummere, R. M.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Silveira, M. J., Kim, S. Y. and Langa, K. M. (2010). Advance directives and outcomes of surrogate decision making before death. New England Journal of Medicine, 362, 12111218.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
SUPPORT (1995). A controlled trial to improve care for seriously ill hospitalized patients in the Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatment (SUPPORT). JAMA, 274, 15911598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teno, J. M. et al. (1997). Do advance directives provide instructions that direct care? Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 45, 508512.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
The, B. A. M., Pasman, H. R. W., Onwuteaka-Philipsen, B. D., Ribbe, M. W. and van derWal, G. (2002). Withholding the artificial administration of fluids and food from elderly patients with dementia: ethnographic study. BMJ, 325, 15.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vezzoni, C. (2005). The Legal Status and Social Practice of Treatment Directives in the Netherlands (doctoral thesis). Groningen: Rijksuniversiteit Groningen. Available at http://irs.ub.rug.nl/ppn/28903504X.Google Scholar
Winzelberg, G. S., Hanson, L. C. and Tulsky, J. A. (2005). Beyond autonomy: diversifying end-of-life decision-making approaches to serve patients and families. Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, 53, 10461050.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed