Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T16:25:29.448Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral motivation and the evil-god challenge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 February 2020

LUKE WILSON*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Purdue University, West LafayetteIN, 47907, USA

Abstract

The evil-god challenge holds that theism is highly symmetrical to the evil-god hypothesis and thus it is not more reasonable to accept one rather than the other. But, since it is not reasonable to accept the evil-god hypothesis, it is not reasonable to accept theism. This article will primarily focus on defending the challenge from two recent objections which hold that it follows from the nature of moral motivation that theism is intrinsically much more likely to be true than the evil-god hypothesis. However, I will also argue that there is a different intrinsic asymmetry between the hypotheses which favours theism.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arruda, C. T. (2017) ‘What kind of theory is the Humean theory of motivation?’, Ratio, 30, 322342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, C. A. (1938/1967) In Defence of Free Will: With other Philosophical Essays (Abingdon: Routledge).Google Scholar
Clarke, Bridget (2018) ‘Virtue as a sensitivity’, in Snow, N. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3556.Google Scholar
Collins, J. M. (2019) ‘The evil-god challenge: extended and defended’, Religious Studies, 55, 85109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan (1993) Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Döring, Sabine (2003) ‘Explaining actions by emotions’, Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 214230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, Paul (2016) ‘Simplicity and natural theology’, in Bergmann, M. & Brower, J. (eds) Reason and Faith: Themes from Richard Swinburne (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 4863.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, Paul (2017) ‘God, evil, and the nature of light’, in Meister, C. & Moser, P. (eds) Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, Paul (2019) ‘What if God makes hard choices?’, in Buchak, L., Zimmerman, D. W., & Swenson, P. (eds) Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion, IX (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 1830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farmer, D. D. (2010) ‘Defining omniscience: a feminist perspective’, Faith and Philosophy, 27, 306320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Findlay, J. N. (1948) ‘Can God's existence be disproven?’, Mind, 57, 176183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, Peter (2007) Developmental Theism: From Pure Will to Unbounded Love (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, Peter (2012) ‘Replying to the anti-God challenge: a God without moral character acts well’, Religious Studies, 48, 3543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Hendricks, Perry (2018) ‘Sceptical theism and the evil-god challenge’, Religious Studies, 54, 549561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howsepian, A. A. (1991) ‘Is God necessarily good?’, Religious Studies, 27, 473484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah (2012) ‘Moral motivation, moral phenomenology, and the alief/belief distinction’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 469486.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lancaster-Thomas, Asha (2018a) ‘The evil-god challenge part I: history and recent developments’, Philosophy Compass, 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lancaster-Thomas, Asha (2018b) ‘The evil-god challenge part II: objections and responses’, Philosophy Compass, 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lancaster-Thomas, Asha (forthcoming) ‘Truth, consequences, and the evil-god challenge: a response to Anastasia Scrutton’, Religious Studies.Google Scholar
Stephen, Law (2010) ‘The evil-god challenge’, Religious Studies, 46, 353373.Google Scholar
Leslie, John (1979) Value and Existence (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Little, M. O. (1995) ‘Seeing and caring: the role of affect in feminist moral epistemology’, Hypatia, 10, 117137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Little, M. O. (1997) ‘Virtue as knowledge: objections from the philosophy of mind’, Nous, 31, 5979.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John (1978) ‘Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volumes, 52, 1329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John (1979) ‘Virtue and reason’, The Monist, 62, 331350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calum, Miller (forthcoming) ‘Why God is probably good: a response to the evil-god challenge’, Religious Studies.Google Scholar
Morriston, Wes (1985) ‘Is God significantly free?’, Faith and Philosophy, 2, 257264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes (2004) ‘The evidential argument from goodness’, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 42, 87101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphree, W. A. (1997) ‘Natural theology: theism or antitheism?’, Sophia, 36, 7583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark (2017) God's Own Ethics: Norms of Divine Agency and the Argument from Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (1970) The Possibility of Altruism (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
New, Christopher (1993) ‘Antitheism: a reflection’, Ratio, 6, 3643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oddie, Graham (2005) Value, Reality, and Desire (Oxford: Clarendon Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oddie, Graham (2017) ‘Desire and the good: in search of the right fit’, in Lauria, F. & Deonna, J. A. (eds) The Nature of Desire, (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2956.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1974) The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Radcliffe, Elizabeth (2006) ‘Moral internalism and moral cognitivism in Hume's metaethics’, Synthese, 152, 353370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Bruce (1980) ‘Why is God good?’, Journal of Religion, 60, 5166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowe, William (2004) Can God Be Free? (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Sarot, Marcel (1992) God, Passibility, and Corporality (Kampen: Kok Pharos).Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark (2007) Slaves of the Passions (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schueler, G. F. (1995) Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scrutton, A. P. (2011) Thinking Through Feeling: God, Emotion and Passibility (New York: Continuum).Google Scholar
Scrutton, A. P. (2013) ‘Divine passibility: God and emotion’, Philosophy Compass, 8, 866874.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scrutton, A. P. (2016) ‘Why not believe in an evil God? Pragmatic encroachment and some implications for philosophy of religion’, Religious Studies, 52, 345360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinhababu, Neil (2017) Humean Nature: How Desire Explains Action, Thought, and Feeling (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael (1994) The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Swartzer, Steven (2013) ‘Appetitive besires and the fuss about fit’, Philosophical Studies, 165, 975988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1997) Simplicity as Evidence of Truth (Marquette MI: Marquette University Press).Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (2004) The Existence of God, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, Sergio (2007) Appearances of the Good: An Essay on the Nature of Practical Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tresan, Jon (2006) ‘De dicto internalist cognitivism’, Nous, 40, 143165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weaver, C. G. (2015) ‘Evilism, moral rationalism, and reasons internalism’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 77, 324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar