Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Home
Hostname: page-component-55597f9d44-mzfmx Total loading time: 0.207 Render date: 2022-08-17T02:25:10.748Z Has data issue: true Feature Flags: { "shouldUseShareProductTool": true, "shouldUseHypothesis": true, "isUnsiloEnabled": true, "useRatesEcommerce": false, "useNewApi": true } hasContentIssue true

Life, Liberty, and Property

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2009

David Kelley
Affiliation:
Philosophy, Vassar College

Extract

The words “liberty” and “liberalism” have a common root, reflecting the commitment of the original or classical liberals to a free society. Over the last century, the latter term has come to represent a political position that is willing to sacrifice liberty in the economic realm for the sake of equality and/or collective welfare. As a consequence, those who wish to reaffirm the classical version of liberalism – those who advocate liberty in economic as well as personal and intellectual matters – have invented a new word from the old root; they call themselves libertarians. Both in doctrine and in etymology, then, partisans of this view define themselves by their allegiance to liberty. Yet they spend most of their day-to-day polemical energies defending property rights and the economic system of laissez-faire capitalism that is based upon such rights. Evidently there is a strong link between liberty and property at work here. What is that link?

The history of political thought is full of ideas and controversies about precisely this question. My goal here is to raise the question in a specific form, one that I think captures a basic difference in approach between classical liberals and most libertarians today. The difference is not in the substance of the position – it is not a disagreement about how the ideal society would be constituted – but rather in the way the position is to be defended. The key question is: can the right to property be derived from the right to liberty?

Of course a property right is a right to kind of freedom.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For some examples, see n. 13 below.

2 This would of course be circular if offered as a definition of ‘possible,’ since ‘ability’ would have to be defined in terms of possibility. But I am not trying to define these concepts; I am merely specifying a range of possible actions.

3 Steiner, Hillel, “The Structure of a Set of Compossible Rights,” Journal of Philosophy 74, 767–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Ibid., 769.

5 Ibid., 772.

6 Mack, Eric, “Liberty and Justice,” in Arthur, John and Shaw, William H. (eds.) Justice and Economic Distribution (Engelwood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1978), 189Google Scholar.

7 Ibid., 188.

8 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974)Google Scholar.

9 Ibid., 163.

10 It is not surprising that many people have looked to this section of Anarchy, State, and Utopia to find Nozick's basis for affirming property rights, since he does not provide such a basis earlier in the book, where he lays out the framework of individual rights.

11 Ibid., 161.

12 Ryan, Cheyney C., “Yours, Mine and Ours: Property Rights and Individual Liberty,” in Paul, Jeffrey (ed.) Reading Nozick (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1981), 329 ffGoogle Scholar.

13 The empasis on production in the case for private property is a recurrent theme in the classical liberal tradition, from Locke's Second Treatise onward, E.g., John Stuart Mill's Principles of Political Economy, II 2. For a powerful contemporary argument of this form, see Rand, Ayn, “What is Capitalism?” in her Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal (New York: New American Library, 1967)Google Scholar.

6
Cited by

Save article to Kindle

To save this article to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Life, Liberty, and Property
Available formats
×

Save article to Dropbox

To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Life, Liberty, and Property
Available formats
×

Save article to Google Drive

To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Life, Liberty, and Property
Available formats
×
×

Reply to: Submit a response

Please enter your response.

Your details

Please enter a valid email address.

Conflicting interests

Do you have any conflicting interests? *