Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T07:54:45.467Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PUBLIC REASON'S CHAOS THEOREM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 January 2018

Abstract

Citizens in John Rawls's well-ordered society face an assurance dilemma. They wish to act justly only if they are reasonably sure their fellow citizens will also act justly. According to Rawls, this assurance problem is solved through public reasoning. This paper argues that public reason cannot serve this function. It begins by arguing that one kind of incompleteness public reason faces that most Rawlsians grant is ubiquitous but unproblematic from a normative standpoint is problematic from an assurance perspective: it makes it possible for citizens to argue for policy conclusions that are favored by their private interests, rather than justice. In response, perhaps the thing to do is structure deliberative democratic institutions such that citizens will always be incentivized to use public reasons to only argue for conclusions they believe are favored by justice. The paper proves that this is impossible by extending the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Aumann, R. 2000. ‘Nash Equilibria Are Not Self-Enforcing.’ In Collected Papers, Vol. 1, pp. 615–20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Barbéra, S. 1977. ‘Manipulation of Social Decision Functions.’ Journal of Economic Theory, 15: 266278.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. 2010. ‘Decision-Theoretic Paradoxes as Voting Paradoxes.’ Philosophical Review, 119: 130.Google Scholar
Chung, H. Forthcoming. ‘The Instability of John Rawls's ‘Stability for the Right Reasons.’’ Episteme. doi: 10.1017/epi.2017.14.Google Scholar
Duggan, J. and Schwartz, T. 2000. ‘Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs.’ Social Choice and Welfare, 17: 8593.Google Scholar
Eliaz, K. 2004. ‘Social Aggregators.’ Social Choice and Welfare, 22: 317–30.Google Scholar
Freeman, S. 2007. Justice and the Social Contract. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 1996. Justificatory Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, G. 2011. ‘A Tale of Two Sets: Public Reason in Equilibrium.’ Public Affairs Quarterly, 25: 305–25.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1973. ‘Manipulation of Voting Schemes: a General Result.’ Econometrica, 41: 587601.Google Scholar
Hadfield, G. K. and Macedo, S. 2012. ‘Rational Reasonableness: Toward a Positive Theory of Public Reason.’ Law and Ethics in Human Rights, 6: 746.Google Scholar
Kelly, J. S. 1977. ‘Strategy-Proofness and Social Choice Functions without Single-Valuedness.’ Econometrica, 45: 439–46.Google Scholar
Kogelmann, B. and Stich, S. G. W. 2016. ‘When Public Reason Fails Us: Convergence Discourse as Blood Oath.’ American Political Science Review, 110: 717–30.Google Scholar
Le Breton, M. and Weymark, J. A. 2011. ‘Arrovian Social Choice Theory on Economic Domains.’ In Arrow, K. J., Sen, A. and Suzumura, K. (eds), Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Volume Two, pp. 191299. Oxford: Elsevier.Google Scholar
MacAskill, W. 2016. ‘Normative Uncertainty as a Voting Problem.’ Mind, 125: 9671004.Google Scholar
de Marneffe, P. 1994. ‘Rawls's Idea of Public Reason.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 75: 232–50.Google Scholar
Morreau, M. 2015. ‘Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn Vindicated.’ Mind, 124: 239–62.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. 2011. ‘Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn versus Arrow.’ Mind, 120: 83115.Google Scholar
Patty, J. W. and Penn, E. M. 2014. Social Choice and Legitimacy: The Possibilities of Impossibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Patty, J. W. and Penn, E. M. 2015. ‘Aggregation, Evaluation, and Social Choice Theory.’ The Good Society, 24: 4972.Google Scholar
Penn, E. M., Patty, J. W. and Gailmard, S. 2011. ‘Manipulability and Single-Peakedness: A General Result.’ American Journal of Political Science, 55: 436–49.Google Scholar
Quinn, P. L. 1997. ‘Political Liberalism and Their Exclusion of the Religious.’ In Weithman, P. J. (ed.), Religion and Contemporary Liberalism, pp. 138–61. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2004. ‘The Scope of Public Reason.’ Political Studies, 52: 233–50.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2011. Liberalism Without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quong, J. 2014: ‘On the Idea of Public Reason.’ In Reidy, D. and Mandle, J. (eds), A Companion to Rawls, pp. 265–80. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1963/1999. ‘The Sense of Justice.’ In Collected Papers, pp. 96116. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1993/2005. Political Liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Reny, P. J. 2001. ‘Arrow's Theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite Theorem: a Unified Approach.’ Economics Letters, 70: 99105.Google Scholar
Satterthwaite, M. A. 1975. ‘Strategy-Proofness and Arrow's Conditions.’ Journal of Economic Theory, 10: 187217.Google Scholar
Schwartzman, M. 2004. ‘The Completeness of Public Reason.’ Politics, Philosophy, & Economics, 3: 191220.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. 2004. The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stegenga, J. 2015. ‘Theory Choice and Social Choice: Okasha versus Sen.’ Mind, 124: 263–77.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. and Hastie, R. 2015. Wise: Getting Beyond Groupthink to Make Groups Smarter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business Review Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, A. D. 2005. Social Choice and the Mathematics of Manipulation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thrasher, J. and Vallier, K. 2015. ‘The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity, and Stability.’ European Journal of Philosophy, 23: 933–54.Google Scholar
Vallier, K. 2015. ‘Public Justification Versus Public Deliberation: the Case for Divorce.’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45: 139–58.Google Scholar
Vickrey, W. 1960. ‘Utility, Strategy, and Social Decision Rules.’ Quarterly Journal of Economics, 74: 507–35.Google Scholar
Weithman, P. 2010. Why Political Liberalism? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weithman, P. 2015. ‘Inclusivism, Stability, and Assurance.’ In Bailey, T. and Gentile, V. (eds), Rawls and Religion, pp. 7598. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, A. 2000. ‘The Alleged Incompleteness of Public Reason.’ Res Publica, 6: 199211.Google Scholar