Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-mwx4w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T13:16:22.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 November 2021

Christoph Kelp
Affiliation:
University of Glasgow
Mona Simion
Affiliation:
University of Glasgow
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Sharing Knowledge
A Functionalist Account of Assertion
, pp. 197 - 204
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s Own Ethics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1985) [350 BCE]. The Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Bach, K. (2008). Applying Pragmatics to Epistemology. Philosophical Issues 18: 6888.Google Scholar
Ball, B. (2014a). Deriving the Norm of Assertion. Journal of Philosophical Research 39: 7585.Google Scholar
Ball, B. (2014b). Response to Hindriks and Kooi. Journal of Philosophical Research 39: 9399.Google Scholar
Benton, M. A. (2011). Two More for the Knowledge Account of Assertion. Analysis 71: 684–87.Google Scholar
Benton, M. A. (2016a). Expert Opinion and Second-hand Knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92(2): 492508.Google Scholar
Benton, M. A. (2016b). Gricean Quality. Noûs 50: 689703.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. and Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. Journal of Philosophy 86: 181–96.Google Scholar
Bird, A. (2007). Justified Judging. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 81110.Google Scholar
Blaauw, M. (2012). Reinforcing the Knowledge Account of Assertion. Analysis 72: 105–8.Google Scholar
Bolton, G. (1991). A Comparative Model of Bargaining: Theory and Evidence. The American Economic Review 81: 1096–136.Google Scholar
Bondy, P. (2007). Epistemic Rationality and Epistemic Normativity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, J. (2010). Knowledge and Assertion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81: 549–66.Google Scholar
Buller, D. (1998). Etiological Theories of Function: A Geographical Survey. Biology and Philosophy 13: 505–27.Google Scholar
Capes, J. (2012). Blameworthiness without Wrongdoing. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93(3): 417–37.Google Scholar
Cappelen, H. (2011). Against Assertion. In Brown, J. and Cappelen, H. (eds.), Assertion: New Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1964). The Ethics of Requirement. American Philosophical Quarterly 1: 147–53.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 5789.Google Scholar
Copp, D. (1997). Defending the Principle of Alternate Possibilities: Blameworthiness and Moral Responsibility. Noûs 31: 441–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, D. (2003). ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’, Blameworthiness, and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities. In Widerker, D. and McKenna, M. (eds.), Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities: Essays on the Importance of Alternative Possibilities. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Copp, D. (2008). ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’ and the Derivation of the Principle of Alternate Possibilities. Analysis 68: 6775.Google Scholar
Davis, E. (2016). Typecasts, Tokens, and Spokespersons: A Case for Credibility Excess as Testimonial Injustice. Hypatia 31: 485501.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. (1991). Epistemic Possibilities. Philosophical Review 100(4): 581605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, Knowledge, and Context. Philosophical Review 111: 167203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, K. (2009). The Case for Contextualism: Knowledge, Skepticism, and Context. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing. Hypathia 26(2): 236–57Google Scholar
Douven, I. (2002). A New Solution to the Paradoxes of Rational Acceptability. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53: 391410.Google Scholar
Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, Knowledge, and Rational Credibility. Philosophical Review 115: 449–85.Google Scholar
Douven, I (2009). Assertion, Moore and Bayes. Philosophical Studies 144: 361–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douven, I. and Kelp, C. (2012). In Defense of the Rational Credibility Account: A Reply to Casalegno. dialectica 66: 289–97.Google Scholar
Fantl, J. and McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an Uncertain World. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. (2006). My Way: Essays on Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility. Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–39.Google Scholar
Fricker, E. (2012). I – Stating and Insinuating. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86(1): 6194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
García-Carpintero, M. (2004). Assertion and the Semantics of Force-Markers. In Bianchi, Claudia (ed.), The Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Gazdar, G. (1979). Pramatics: Implicature, Presupposition, and Logical Form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Geach, P. (1956). Good and Evil. Analysis 17: 3242.Google Scholar
Gerken, M. (2011). Warrant and Action. Synthese 178: 529–47.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gibbons, J. (2013). The Norm of Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). Functions: Consensus without Unity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74: 196208.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). A Modern History Theory of Functions. Noûs 28: 344–62.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2015). Assertion: On the Philosophical Significance of Assertoric Speech. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2020). Conversational Pressure: Normativity in Speech Exchanges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, P. (2010). Testimonial Entitlement and the Function of Comprehension. In Haddock, A., Millar, A. and Pritchard, D. (eds.), Social Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, P. (2012). Epistemic Entitlement. Noûs 46: 449–82.Google Scholar
Graham, P. (2014a). The Function of Perception. In Fairweather, A. (ed.), Virtue Epistemology Naturalized. Bridges between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Graham, P. (2014b). Functions, Warrant, History. In Fairweather, A. and Flanagan, O. (eds.), Naturalizing Epistemic Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Green, M. (2015). Speech Acts. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/speech-acts/Google Scholar
Green, M. (2020). Speech Acts. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/speech-acts/Google Scholar
Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Griffith, P. (1993). Functional Analysis and Proper Functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44: 409–22.Google Scholar
Haji, I. (1998). Moral Appraisability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hinchman, E. S. (2005). Telling as Inviting to Trust. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 562–87.Google Scholar
Hinchman, E. S. (2013). Assertion, Sincerity, and Knowledge. Nous 47: 613–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hindriks, F. (2007). The Status of the Knowledge Account of Assertion. Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 393406.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Kooi, B. (2014). Reaffirming the Status of the Knowledge Account of Assertion. Journal of Philosophical Research 39: 8792.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, W. (1919). Fundamental Legal Conceptions. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. (1995). Disempowered Speech. Philosophical Topics 23(2): 127–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, J. and Langton, R. (1998). Free Speech and Illocution. Legal Theory 4: 2137.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (2007). Virtue Ethics. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (July 2007 Edition).Google Scholar
Jenkins Ichikawa, J. (2014). Justification Is Potential Knowledge. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44(2): 184206.Google Scholar
Jenkins Ichikawa, J. (2017). Contextualising Knowledge: Epistemology and Semantics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2011). Not Without Justificationdialectica 65: 581–95.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2014). Two for the Knowledge Goal of Inquiry. American Philosophical Quarterly 51: 227–32.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2016). Justified Belief: Knowledge First-Style. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93: 79100.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2017). Lotteries and Justification. Synthese 194: 1233–44.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2018). Good Thinking: A Knowledge First Virtue Epistemology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. (2021). Inquiry, Knowledge, and Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelp, C. and Simion, M. (2017a). Commodious Knowledge. Synthese 1941487–502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelp, C. and Simion, M. (2017b). Criticism and Blame in Action and Assertion. Journal of Philosophy 114(2): 7693.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1994). Function and Design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 18: 379–97.Google Scholar
Kneer, M. (2018). The Norm of Assertion: Empirical Data. Cognition. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.03.020.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. L. (2009). Assertion, Knowledge and Lotteries. In Pritchard, D. and Greenough, P. (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. L. (2011). Norms of Assertion. In Brown, J. & Cappelen, H. (eds.), Assertion: New Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. L. (2017). Reply to Simion. Logos and Episteme 8(1): 113–16.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2007). Norms of AssertionNoûs 41: 594626.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source for Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2011). Assertion and Isolated Second-hand Knowledge. In Brown, J. and Cappelen, H. (eds.), Assertion: New Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2016). Assertion and Expertise. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92: 509–17.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2018). Credibility and the Distribution of Epistemic Goods. In McCain, K. (ed.), Believing in Accordance with the Evidence. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. (2020). False Confessions and Testimonial Injustice. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 110: 4368.Google Scholar
Langton, R. (1993). Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts. Philosophy and Public Affairs 22(4): 293330.Google Scholar
Lenzen, W. (1980). Glauben, Wissen und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Vienna: Springer.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2014). Know Your Rights: On Warranted Assertion and Truth. Erkenntnis 79(6):1355–65.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (Forthcoming). A Plea for Epistemic Excuses. In Dorsch, D. and Dutant, J. (eds.), The New Evil Demon Problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luzzi, F. (2016). Testimonial Injustice without Credibility Deficit (or Excess). Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 5(3): 203–11.Google Scholar
Madison, B. (2010). Is Justification Knowledge? Journal of Philosophical Research 35: 173–91.Google Scholar
Maitra, I. (2011). Assertion, Norms and Games. In Brown, J. and Cappelen, H. (eds.), Assertion: New Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McGlynn, A. (2014). Knowledge First? New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
McHugh, C. (2012). The Truth Norm of Belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93: 830.Google Scholar
McKinnon, R. (2015). The Norms of Assertion. Truth, Lies and Warrant. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
McKinnon, R. and Turri, J. (2013). Irksome Assertions. Philosophical Studies 166: 123–26.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1963). Essays on Ethics, Religion, and Society. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. 10. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Miller, D. (2017). Justice. In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/justice/Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of Meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod Lectures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Miracchi, L. (2015). Competence to Know. Philosophical Studies, 172 (1): 2956.Google Scholar
Montminy, M. (2013). Why Assertion and Practical Reasoning Must Be Governed by the Same Epistemic Norm. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94(1): 5768.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1942). A Reply to My Critics. In Schilpp, P. (ed.), The Philosophy of G.E. Moore, The Library of Living Philosophers. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1962). Commonplace Book: 1919–1953. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Moran, D. (2006). Getting Told and Being Believed. In Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.), The Epistemology of Testimony. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Neander, K. (1991a). Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defence. Philosophy of Science 58: 168–84.Google Scholar
Neander, K. (1991b). The Teleological Notion of ‘Function’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69: 454–68.Google Scholar
Nolfi, K. (2014). Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Inquiry 57: 97121.Google Scholar
Ochs, J. and Roth, A. E. (1989). An Experimental Study of Sequential Bargaining. American Economic Review 79: 355–84.Google Scholar
Pagin, P. (2016). Problems with Norms of Assertion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93: 178207.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pelling, C. (2013a). Assertion and Safety. Synthese 190: 3777–96.Google Scholar
Pelling, C. (2013b). Assertion and the Provision of KnowledgeThe Philosophical Quarterly 63: 293312.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. (2014). Epistemic Luck, Safety and Assertion. In Littlejohn, C. and Turri, J. (eds.), Epistemic Norms: New Essays on Action, Belief and Assertion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D., Millar, A. and Haddock, A. (2010). The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reuter, K. and Broessel, P. (2018). No Knowledge Required. Episteme. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2018.10.Google Scholar
Reynolds, S. (2013). Justification as the Appearance of Knowledge. Philosophical Studies 163: 367–83.Google Scholar
Ridge, M (2014). Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. (2009). Getting the Meno Requirement Right. In Pritchard, D., Haddock, A. and Millar, A. (eds.), Epistemic Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rudy-Hiller, F. (2018). The Epistemic Condition for Moral Responsibility. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/moral-responsibility-epistemic/Google Scholar
Rysiew, P. (2016). Epistemic Contextualism. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/contextualism-epistemology/Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. (2021). Value Theory. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/value-theory/Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2016a). Assertion: Knowledge Is Enough. Synthese 193(10): 3041–56.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2016b). Assertion: Just One Way to Take It Back. Logos and Episteme 7(3): 385–91.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2016c). Knowledge, Rational Credibility and Assertion: The Scoreboard. In Grajner, M. and Schmechtig, P. (eds.), Epistemic Reasons, Epistemic Norms and Epistemic Goals. Berlin and Boston, MA: DeGruyter.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2019a). Assertion: The Context Shiftiness Dilemma. Mind & Language 34: 503–17.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2019b). Knowledge‐first Functionalism. Philosophical Issues 29(1): 254–67.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2019c). Saying and Believing: The Norm Commonality Assumption. Philosophical Studies  176(8):  1951–66.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2020a). A Priori Perceptual Entitlement, Knowledge‐first. Philosophical Issues 30(1): 311–23.Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2020b). Testimonial Contractarianism: A Knowledge First Social Epistemology. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12337Google Scholar
Simion, M. (2021). Shifty Speech and Independent Thought: Epistemic Normativity in Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Simion, M. and Kelp, C. (2016). The Tertiary Value Problem and the Superiority of KnowledgeAmerican Philosophical Quarterly 53(4): 397411.Google Scholar
Simion, M., Kelp, C. and Ghijsen, H. (2016). Norms of Belief. Philosophical Issues 16: 374–92.Google Scholar
Slote, M. (1979). Assertion and Belief. In Dancy, J. (ed.), Papers on Language and Logic. Keele: Keele University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, H. (1991). Varieties of Moral Worth and Moral Credit. Ethics 101: 279303.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (2005). Norms and Regulations: Three Issues – Discussion. Philosophical Studies 124: 221–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2003). The Place of Truth in Epistemology. In Zagzebski, L. and DePaul, M. (eds.), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing Full Well. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. (2001). An Evolutionary Perspective on Testimony and Argumentation. Philosophical Topics 29 (1/2): 401–13.Google Scholar
Speak, D. (2005). PAPistry: Another Defense. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29: 262–68.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and Practical Interest. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sutton, J. (2005). Stick To What You Know. Noûs 39: 359–96.Google Scholar
Tappolet, C. (2014). The Normativity of Evaluative Concepts. In Reboul, A. (ed.), Mind, Values and Metaphysics: Philosophical Essays in Honour of Kevin Mulligan, Vol. 2. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Thijsse, E. (2000). ‘The Doxastic-Epistemic Force of Declarative Utterances.’ In Black, W. and Bunt, H. (eds.), Abduction, Beliefs and Context in Dialogue: Studies in Computational Pragmatics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. (2008). Normativity. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2010). Prompting Challenges. Analysis 70: 456–62.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2011). The Express Knowledge Account of Assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89(1): 3745.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2013). The Test of Truth: An Experimental Investigation of the Norm of Assertion. Cognition 129: 279–91.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2014). Knowledge and Suberogatory Assertion. Philosophical Studies 167: 557–67.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2015). Knowledge and the Norm of Assertion: A Simple Test. Synthese 192: 385–92.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2016). Knowledge and the Norm of Assertion: An Essay in Philosophical Science. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.Google Scholar
Turri, J., Friedman, O. and Keefner, A. (2017). Knowledge Central: A Central Role for Knowledge Attributions in Social Evaluations. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 70: 504–15.Google Scholar
Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Walsh, D. and Ariew, A. (1996). A Taxonomy of Functions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26: 493514.Google Scholar
Weiner, M. (2005). Must We Know What We Say? Philosophical Review 114: 227–51.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. (2013). Stick to the Facts: On the Norms of Assertion. Erkenntnis 78: 847–67.Google Scholar
Whiting, D. (2015). Truth Is (Still) the Norm for Assertion: A Reply to Littlejohn. Erkenntnis 80(6): 1245–53.Google Scholar
Widerker, D. (1991). Frankfurt on ‘Ought Implies Can’ and Alternative Possibilities. Analysis 51: 222–24.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (1996). Knowing and Asserting. Philosophical Review 105(4): 489523.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T (2009). Replies to Critics. In Greenough, P. and Pritchard, D. (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, M. (1997). Moral Responsibility and Ignorance. Ethics 107(3): 410–26.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Christoph Kelp, University of Glasgow, Mona Simion, University of Glasgow
  • Book: Sharing Knowledge
  • Online publication: 18 November 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009036818.016
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Christoph Kelp, University of Glasgow, Mona Simion, University of Glasgow
  • Book: Sharing Knowledge
  • Online publication: 18 November 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009036818.016
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Christoph Kelp, University of Glasgow, Mona Simion, University of Glasgow
  • Book: Sharing Knowledge
  • Online publication: 18 November 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009036818.016
Available formats
×