Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-31T23:11:59.588Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2023

Marilù Papandreou
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Bergen, Norway
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackrill, J. L. 1972. ‘Aristotle’s Definitions of Psuche’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73: 119–33.Google Scholar
Ackrill, J. L. 1981. Aristotle the Philosopher. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Adamson, P. 2023. ‘Natural, Artificial, and Organic Forms in Avicenna’, in Charles, D. (ed.), The History of Hylomorphism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Angier, T. 2010. Techne in Aristotle’s Ethics: Crafting the Moral Life. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1976. ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics: Books M and N’, The Philosophical Review 87(3): 479–85.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1982. ‘Aristotle on Inefficient Causes’, Philosophical Quarterly 32(129): 311–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, L. R. 2007. The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balme, D. M. 1992. Aristotle: De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with Passages from II.1–13). Translated with notes, with a report on recent work and additional bibliography by A. Gotthelf. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Baltussen, A., Atkinson, M., Share, M. and Mueller, I. 2012. Simplicius: On Aristotle’s Physics 1.5–9. Annotated translation. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (ed.). 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, Bollingen Series LXXI.2. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2021. ‘Technê as a Model for Virtue in Plato’, in Johansen, T. K. (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy, pp. 6285. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, K. 1965. ‘Der Begriff der Techne bei Aristoteles’, in Flashar, H. and Gaiser, K. (eds.), Synusia, pp. 275–87. Pfülligen: Neske.Google Scholar
Beckman, A. 1889. Num Plato Artefactorum Ideas Statuerit. Bonn: Bonnae, P. Hanstein.Google Scholar
Beere, J. 2006. ‘Potentiality and the Matter of Composite Substance’, Phronesis 51(4): 303–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beere, J. 2009. Doing and Being: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berryman, S. 2002. ‘Aristotle on Pneuma and Animal Self-Motion’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 23: 8597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1975. Plato’s Sophist: A Commentary. Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. 1991. ‘Aristotle’s Method in Natural Science: Physics I’ in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, pp. 129. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. 2018. ‘Two Conceptions of Practical Skill (Τέχνη) in Aristotle’, in Sfendoni-Mentzou, D. (ed.), Aristotle: Contemporary Perspectives on His Thought – On the 2400th Anniversary of Aristotle’s Birth, pp. 279–96. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. 2021. ‘Technê and Empeiria: Aristotle on Practical Knowledge’, in Johansen, T. K. (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy, pp. 131–65. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bonitz, H. 1849. Commentarius in Aristotelis Metaphysicam. Bonn.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. 1994. Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Z and H. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 1987. ‘Nature, Craft and Phronesis in Aristotle’, Philosophical Topics 15(2): 3550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. 1990. ‘Nature and Craft in Aristotelian Teleology’, in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, pp. 389403. Paris: Editions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 2004. ‘De generatione et corruptione I 4: Distinguishing Alteration’, in de Haas, F. and Mansfeld, J. (eds.), Proceedings of the XV Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 123–50. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 2007. ‘Why No Platonistic Ideas of Artefacts?’, in Scott, D. (ed.),Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat, pp. 232–53. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. 2009. ‘Aporia 8’, in Crubellier, M. and Laks, A. (eds.), Aristotle’s Metaphysics Beta: Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 135–50. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Buddensiek, F. 2018. ‘Aporia in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Beta’, in Karamanolis, G. and Politis, V. (eds.), The Aporetic Tradition in Ancient Philosophy, pp. 137–54. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 1984. Notes on Books Eta and Theta of Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2001. A Map of Metaphysics Zeta. Pittsburgh: Mathesis Publications.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. 2004. ‘Aristotle on the Foundations of Sublunary Physics’, in Haas, F. and Mansfeld, J. (eds.), Aristotle’s on Generation and Corruption I Book 1: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Butler, T. 2003. ‘Empeiria in Aristotle’, Southern Journal of Philosophy 41(3): 329–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, C. 2012. ‘Compositional & Functional Matter: Aristotle on the Material Cause of Biological Organisms’, Apeiron 48(4): 387406.Google Scholar
Byrne, C. 2019. Aristotle’s Science of Matter and Motion. University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Cambiano, G. 1971. Platone e le tecniche. Einaudi.Google Scholar
Cambiano, G. 2012. ‘The Desire to Know Metaphysics A 1’, in Steel, C. and Primavesi, O. (eds.), Aristotle’s Metaphysics Alpha: Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 143. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cameron, M. 2019. ‘The Moving Cause of Artefacts: The Role of Techne in Metaphysical Explanation’, DIALOGOI: Ancient Philosophy Today 1(1): 6483.Google Scholar
Cardullo, R. L. 2005. ‘L’analogia techne/physis e il finalismo universale in Fisica II’, in Cardullo, R. L. and Giardina, G. R. (eds.), La Fisica di Aristotele oggi: Problemi e prospettive, pp. 51109. Catania: CUECM.Google Scholar
Cardullo, R. L. 2012. Asclepio di Tralle: Commentario al libro Alpha meizon (A) della Metafisica di Aristotele. Acireale: Bonanno editore.Google Scholar
Castelli, L. M. 2010. Problems and Paradigms of Unity: Aristotle’s Accounts of the One. International Aristotle Studies 6. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Castelli, L. M. 2018. Aristotle: Metaphysics Book Iota. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. 2006. ‘Aristotle’s Psychology’, in Gill, M.-L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.),The Blackwell Companion to Ancient Philosophy, pp. 316–46. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 2000. Aristotle on Meaning and Essence. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 2008. ‘Aristotle’s Psychological Theory’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 24(1): 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charles, D. 2010a. ‘Definition and Explanation in the Posterior Analytics (and Beyond)’, in Charles, D. (ed.), Definition in Greek Philosophy, pp. 286318. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charles, D. 2010b. ‘Metaphysics Θ.7 and 8: Some Issues concerning Actuality and Lotentiality’, in Lennox, J. G. and Bolton, R. (eds.), Being, Nature and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, pp. 168–97. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 2021. The Undivided Self: Aristotle and the ‘Mind-Body Problem’. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charlton, W. 1970. Aristotle: Physics Books I and II. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. 1944. Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato and Academy. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
Code, A. 1976. ‘The Persistence of Aristotelian Matter’, Philosophical Studies 29(6): 357–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. 1987. ‘Soul as an Efficient Cause in Aristotle’s Embryology’, Philosophical Topics 15(2): 51–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. 1997. ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics as a Science of Principles’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 51(201): 357–78.Google Scholar
Code, A. 2003. ‘Changes, Powers and Potentialities in Aristotle’, in Reshotko, N. (ed.),Desire, Identity, and Existence: Essays in Honor of T. M. Penner, pp. 253–71. Kelowna: Academic Printing and Publishing.Google Scholar
Code, A. 2011. ‘Aristotle on the Matter of Corpses in Metaph. H 5’, Invited Lecture, Munich School of Ancient Philosophy, 14 December. www.philosophy.rutgers.edu/joomlatools-files/docman-files/Matter-of-Corpses-Draft.pdfGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. M. 1996. Aristotle on Nature and Incomplete Substance. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connell, S. 2016. Aristotle on Female Animals: A Study of the Generation of Animals. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coope, U. 2021. ‘Aristotle on Productive Understanding and Completeness’, in Johansen, T. K. (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy: The Concept of Technê, pp. 109–30. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1982. ‘Aristotle on Natural Teleology’, in Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M. (eds.), Language and Logos, pp. 197–22. Cambridge University Press; reprinted in Cooper, J. M. 2004. Knowledge, Nature and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy, pp. 107–29.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1987. ‘Hypothetical Necessity and Natural Teleology’, in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, pp. 243–74. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2009. ‘Two Notes on Aristotle on Mixtures’, in Cooper, J. M., Knowledge, Nature and the Good. Essays on Ancient Philosophy, pp. 148–73. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Corkum, P. 2023. ‘Aristotle on Artifactual Substances’, Metaphysics 6(1): 2436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornford, F. M. 1935. Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. Translation and commentary on the Theaetetus and the Sophist. New York: The Liberal Arts Press.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. 1939. Plato and Parmenides: Introduction, translation and commentary on Parmenides’ poem and the Parmenides of Plato. New York: The Liberal Arts Press.Google Scholar
D’Hoine, P. 2006a. ‘The Status of the Arts: Proclus’ Theory of Artefacts’, Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 2(2): 305–44.Google Scholar
D’Hoine, P. 2006b. ‘Proclus and Syrianus on Ideas of Artefacts: A Test Case for Neoplatonic Hermeneutics’, in Perkams, M. and Piccione, R. M. (eds.), Proklos: Methode, Seelenlehre, Metaphysik, pp. 279302. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Haas, F. A. 2016. ‘Mixture in Philoponus: An Encounter with a Third Kind of Potentiality’, in Sorabji, R. (ed.), Aristotle Re-Interpreted: New Findings on Seven Hundred Years of the Ancient Commentators, pp. 413–36. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
De Ribera-Martin, I. 2017. ‘Unity and Continuity in Aristotle’, Apeiron 50(2): 225–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dipert, R. R. 1993. Artifacts, Art Works and Agency. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Elder, C. L. 2004. Real Natures and Familiar Objects. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, C. L. 2007. ‘On the Place of Artefacts in Ontology’, in Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds.), Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation, pp. 3351. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emilsson, E. 2021. ‘Plotinus on the Arts’, in Johansen, T. K. (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy: The Concept of Technê, pp. 245–62. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Evnine, S. 2016. Making Objects and Events: A Hylomorphic Theory of Artefacts, Actions, and Organisms. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falcon, A. 2019. ‘Aristotle on Causality’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-causality/.Google Scholar
Fernandez, P. A. and Mittelmann, J. 2017. ‘ἡ κίνησις τῆς τέχνης: Crafts and Souls as Principles of Change’, Phronesis 62(2): 136–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferro, A. 2021. Aristotle on Self Motion. Basel: Schwabe Verlag.Google Scholar
Fine, G. 1993. On Ideas. Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Theory of Forms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 1995. ‘The Problem of Mixture’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76: 266369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 1998. ‘Mixing Matters’, Ratio 11(3): 278–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forcignanò, F. 2014. ‘Il problema delle idee di artefatto in Platone’, Méthexis 27: 6193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forcignanò, F. 2016. Forme, linguaggio, sostanze. Il dibattito sulle idee nell’Academia antica. Sesto San Giovanni: Mimesis.Google Scholar
Frank, D. H. 1984. The Arguments ‘From the Sciences’ in Aristotle’s ‘Peri ideon’. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Frank, J. 2005. A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Franks, C. 2009. He Became Poor: The Poverty of Christ and Aquinas’s Economic Teachings. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Franssen, M. 2009. ‘Philosophy of Technology’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/technology/.Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2004. ‘GC I 10: On Mixture and Mixables’, in Haas, F. and Mansfeld, J. (eds.), Aristotle’s on Generation and Corruption I Book 1: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1987. ‘The Unity of General and Special Metaphysics: Aristotle’s Conception of Metaphysics’, in Frede, M. (ed.), Essays in Ancient Philosophy, pp. 8195. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1994. ‘Aristotle’s Notion of Potentiality in Metaphysics’, in Scaltsas, T., Charles, D. and Gill, M.-L. (eds.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, pp. 173–93. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1996. ‘Aristotle’s Rationalism’, in Frede, M. and Striker, G. (eds.), Rationality in Greek Thought, pp. 157–73. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M. and Patzig, G. 1988. Aristoteles, ‘Metaphysik Z’ Text, Übersetzung Und Kommentar, Band 1 and 2. Munich: C.H. Beck.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. 1987. ‘Aristotle on Bodies, Matter, and Potentiality’, in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, pp. 392407. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frey, C. 2016. ‘Organic Unity and the Matter of Man’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 32: 167204.Google Scholar
Furley, D. 1978. ‘Self-Movers’, in Lloyd, G. E. R. and Owen, G. E. L. (eds.), Aristotle on Mind and the Senses, pp. 165–79. Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Furley, D. 1994. ‘Self-Movers’, in Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Self-Motion From Aristotle to Newton, pp. 3–14. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Furth, M. 1985. Metaphysics: Books VII-X, Zeta, Eta, Theta, Iota. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Furth, M. 1988. Substance, Form and Psyche: An Aristotelean Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galluzzo, G. 2006. Aristotle’s Metaphysics Book Zeta: The Contemporary Debate. Pisa: Edizioni della Scuola Normale.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2011. ‘Artifacts, Substances and Essences’, Apeiron 18: 5058.Google Scholar
Gill, M.-L. 1989. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Golitsis, P. 2016. ‘Who Were the Real Authors of the Metaphysics Commentary Ascribed to Alexander and Ps.-Alexander?’, in Sorabji, R. (ed.), Aristotle Re-Interpreted: New Findings on Seven Hundred Years of the Ancient Commentators, pp. 565–88. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. 2012. ‘Understanding Aristotle’s Teleology’, in Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology, pp. 6789. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregorić, P. and Grgić, F. 2006. ‘Aristotle’s Notion of Experience’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88(1): 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halper, E. 2005. One and Many in Aristotle’s Metaphysics: The Central Books. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. 2020. ‘Aristotle and the Mechanics of Desire: De Motu Animalium 7 (from 701b2)–8’, in Rapp, C. and Primavesi, O. (eds.), Aristotle’s De motu animalium: Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 387415. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasper, P. S. and Yurdin, J. 2014. ‘Between Perception and Scientific Knowledge: Aristotle’s Account of Experience’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 119–50.Google Scholar
Heinze, R. 1892. Xenocrates: Darstellung der Lehre und Sammlung der Fragmente. Hildesheim: Gg. Olms.Google Scholar
Henning, B. 2009. ‘The Four Causes’, Journal of Philosophy 106: 137–60.Google Scholar
Henry, D. 2005. ‘Embryological Models in Ancient Philosophy’, Phronesis 50(1): 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henry, D. 2019. Aristotle on Matter, Form, and Moving Causes: The Hylomorphic Theory of Substantial Generation. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilpinen, R. 1992. ‘Artifacts and Works of Art’, Theoria 58: 5882.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilpinen, R. 1993. ‘Authors and Artifacts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93: 155–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilpinen, R. 2011. ‘Artifact’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/artifact/.Google Scholar
Houkes, W. and Vermaas, P. E. 2009. ‘Artefacts in Analytic Metaphysics: Introduction’, Techné 13(2): 7481.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1988. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. 1962. ‘A proposito di un’interpretazione cinquecentesca del rapporto teoria-prassi in Aristotele e Platone’, La parola del passato 17: 436–47.Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. 1964. ‘Platone e la prima academia di fronte al problema degli artefatti’, Rivista Critica di Storia della Filosofia 19: 123–58.Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. 1966. Techne: Momenti del pensiero greco da Platone a Epicuro. Firenze: Nuova Italia.Google Scholar
Jackson, H. 1982a. ‘Plato’s Later Theory of Ideas I’, Journal of Philosophy 10: 253–98.Google Scholar
Jackson, H. 1982b. ‘Plato’s Later Theory of Ideas II’, Journal of Philosophy 11: 287331.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. W. 1912. ‘Studien zur Entstehungsgeschichte der Metaphysik des Aristoteles’, Journal of Hellenic Studies 32: 415–18.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. W. 1923. ‘Aristoteles: Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung’, Journal of Hellenic Studies 43(130): 201.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. H. 1922. Aristotle: On Coming-to-be and Passing-away. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2010. ‘Should Aristotle Have Recognized Final Causes in Plato’s Timaeus?’, in Mohr, R. and Sattler, B. (eds.), One Book, the Whole Universe: Plato’s Timaeus Today, pp. 179200. Las Vegas: Parmenidies.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2012. The Powers of Aristotle’s Souls. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2016. ‘Natural and Artificial Bodies in Plato and Aristotle’, in Buchheim, T. and Meissner, D. (eds.), Body in Ancient Philosophy and Literature, pp. 455–70. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2017. ‘Aristotle on the Logos of the Craftsman’, Phronesis 62(2): 97135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2021. ‘Crafting the Cosmos: Plato on the Limitations of Divine Craftsmanship’, in Johansen, T. K. (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy: The Concept of Technê, pp. 86108. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, B. J. 1974. ‘Aristotle’s Introduction of Matter’, The Philosophical Review 83: 474500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judson, L. 2000. ‘Formlessness and the Priority of Form: Metaphysics Zeta 7–9 and Lambda 3’, in Charles, D. and Frede, M. (eds.), Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Karamanolis, G. and Politis, V. (eds.). 2018. The Aporetic Tradition in Ancient Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Katayama, E. G. 1999. Aristotle on Artifacts: A Metaphysical Puzzle. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Katayama, E. G. 2008. ‘Substantial Unity and Living Things in Aristotle’, Apeiron 41(3): 99128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelsey, S. 2003. ‘Aristotle’s Definition of Nature’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 25: 5987.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kidd, S. 2019. ‘What Do Pleasure-Objects Do? An Inquiry into Toys’, in Kidd, S. (ed.), Play and Aesthetics in Ancient Greece, pp. 97121. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, R. A. H. 2001. Aristotle on Life and Death. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Kirwan, C. 1993. Metaphysics: Books Gamma, Delta, and Epsilon. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kornblith, H. 2007. ‘How to Refer to Artifacts’, in Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds.), Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation, pp. 138–49. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. 1997. ‘Four-Eighths Hephaistos: Artifacts and Living Things in Aristotle’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 14(1): 7798.Google Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2008. The Structure of Objects. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2018. Form, Matter, Substance. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosman, A. 1987. ‘Animals and Other Beings in Aristotle’, in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, pp. 360–91. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kosman, A. 2013. The Activity of Being: An Essay on Aristotle’s Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krizan, M. 2018. ‘Mixing and the Formation of Homoeomers in On Generation and Corruption 2.7’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 54: 187226.Google Scholar
Kroes, P. 2012. Technical Artefacts: Creations of Mind and Matter – A Philosophy of Engineering Design. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kroes, P. and Meijers, A. 2006. ‘The Dual Nature of Technical Artefacts’, Studies in History Philosophy of Science 37(1): 1158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krohs, U. 2009. ‘Structure and Coherence of Two-Model-Descriptions of Technical Artefacts’, Techne: Research in Philosophy and Technology 13: 150–61.Google Scholar
Krohs, U. and Kroes, P. 2009. Functions in Biological and Artificial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LaBarge, S. 2006. ‘Aristotle on Empeiria’, Ancient Philosophy 26(1): 2344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leigh, R. 2015. On Theriac to Piso, Attributed to Galen. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1982. ‘Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 20(3): 219–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 2004. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals I-IV. Translation with introduction and commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Leszl, W. 1975. Il De Ideis di Aristotele e la teoria platonica delle idee. Florence: Olschki.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2010. Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewens, T. 2004. Organisms and Artifacts Design in Nature and Elsewhere. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, F. A. 1994. ‘Aristotle on the Relation between a Thing and Its Matter’, in Scaltsas, T. Charles, D. and Gill, M.-L. (eds.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, pp. 247–78. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, F. A. 2013. How Aristotle Gets By in Metaphysics Zeta. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Livingston, P. 2011. ‘History of the Ontology of Art’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/art-ontology-history/.Google Scholar
Loux, M. J. 1991. Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Z and H. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Löbl, R. 1997. Τέχνη-Techne Untersuchung zur Bedeutung dieses Wortes in der Zeit von Homer Bis Aristoteles, vol. 1, Von Homer bis zu den Sophisten. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
Löbl, R. 2003. Τέχνη-Techne: Untersuchungen zur Bedeutung dieses Wortes in der Zeit von Homer bis Aristoteles, vol. 2, Von den Sophisten bis Aristoteles. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
Löbl, R. 2008. Τέχνη-Techne: Untersuchungen zur Bedeutung dieses Wortes in der Zeit nach Aristoteles, vol. 3, Die Zeit des Hellenismus. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
Madigan, A. 1999. Aristotle: Metaphysics Books B and K 1-2. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Majcherek, K. 2022. ‘The Medieval Problem of the Productivity of Art’, Philosophies 7(5): article 101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makin, S. 2006. Aristotle: Metaphysics Theta. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Malcolm, J. 1967. ‘Plato’s Analysis of τὸ ὄν and τὸ μὴ ὄν in the Sophist’, Phronesis 12: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds.). 2007. Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmodoro, A. 2013. ‘Aristotle’s Hylomorphism without Reconditioning’, Philosophical Inquiry 36(1–2): 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R. D. 1978. ‘Aristotle’s Subordinate Sciences’, British Journal for the History of Science 11(3): 197220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meikle, S. 1997. Aristotle’s Economic Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Meißner, B. 1999. Die technologische Fachliteratur der Antike. Struktur, Uberlieferung und Wirkung technischen Wissens in der Antike (ca. 400 v. Chr.– ca. 500 n. Chr.). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
Merlan, P. 1957. ‘Metaphysik: Name und Gegenstand’, Journal of Hellenic Studies 77(1): 8792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merricks, T. 2001. Objects and Persons. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menn, S. (n.d.). The Aim and the Argument of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, www.philosophie.hu-berlin.de/de/lehrbereiche/antike/mitarbeiter/menn/contents.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 2002. ‘Aristotle’s Definition of Soul and the Programme of the De Anima’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22: 83139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, S. S. 1992. ‘Aristotle, Teleology, and Reduction’, The Philosophical Review 101(4): 791825.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mignucci, M. 1988. ‘Platone e Relativi’, Elenchos 9: 259–94.Google Scholar
Mirus, C. V. 2006. ‘The Homogeneous Bodies in Meteorology iv 12’, Ancient Philosophy 26(1): 4564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Modrak, D. 1987. Aristotle: The Power of Perception. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Morel, P. M. 2015. Aristote, Métaphysique – Livre Èta. Translation with commentary. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Morel, P. M. 2017. ‘Substance et artefact. Sur Aristote, Mét. H’, Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 35(2): 169–96.Google Scholar
Morison, B. 2002. On Location: Aristotle’s Concept of Place. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morison, B. 2004. ‘Self Motion in Physics VIII’, in Laks, A. and Rashed, M. (eds.), Aristote et le mouvement des animaux, pp. 6779. Presses universitaires du Septentrio.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, J. 2014. ‘Right Reason in Plato and Aristotle: On the Meaning of Logos’, Phronesis 59(3): 181230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mueller, I. 1970. ‘Aristotle on Geometrical Objects’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52: 156–71. Reprinted in Barnes, J., Schofield, M. and Sorabji, R. (eds.). 1979. Articles on Aristotle, vol. 3. London: Duckworth.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller, J. 2018. Practical and Productive Thinking in Aristotle, Phronesis 63(2): 148–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Natorp, P. 1888. ‘Über Aristoteles’ Metaphysik, K 1-8, 1065a26’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 1(2): 178–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norman, D. A. 2001. The Design of Everyday Things. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1960. ‘Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle’, in Düring, I. and Owen, G. E. L. (eds.), Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-Fourth Century (Studia graeca et latina gothoburgensia, XI, pp. 163–90. Gothenburg: Almquist & Wiksell.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1971. ‘Plato on Not-Being’, in Vlastos, G., Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays, vol. 1, Metaphysics and Epistemology, pp. 223–67. New York: Doubleday and Anchor.Google Scholar
Owens, J. 1951. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics: A Study in the Greek Background of Mediaeval Thought. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.Google Scholar
Papandreou, M. 2018. ‘Aristotle’s Hylomorphism and the Contemporary Metaphysics of Artefacts’, Discipline Filosofiche 28(1): 113–36.Google Scholar
Papandreou, M. 2020. ‘The Shape of the Statue: The Greek Commentators on Aristotle’s Metaphysics on Forms of Artefacts’, History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 23(2): 398422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papandreou, M. 2021. ‘Aristotle’s Take on Inadvertently Made Objects’, Esercizi Filosofici 16: 2641.Google Scholar
Perl, E. D. 1999. ‘The Presence of the Paradigm: Immanence and Transcendence in Plato’s Theory of Forms’, Review of Metaphysics 53(2): 339–62.Google Scholar
Petroski, H. 1992. The Evolution of Useful Things: How Everyday Artifacts – From Forks and Pins to Paper Clips and Zippers – Came to Be as They Are. New York: Knopf Doubleday.Google Scholar
Pfeiffer, C. 2018a. Aristotle’s Theory of Bodies. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pfeiffer, C. 2018b. ‘Aristotle and the Thesis of Mereological Potentialism’, Philosophical Inquiry 42: 34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Politis, V. 2003. ‘Aristotle on Aporia and Searching in Metaphysics’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 18: 145–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Politis, V. 2004. ‘Aristotle and the Metaphysics’, Mind 114(455): 760–64.Google Scholar
Preston, B. 2012. A Philosophy of Material Culture: Action, Function, and Mind. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Preus, A. 1975. Science and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Biological Works. Hildesheim: Olms Verlag.Google Scholar
Quarantotto, D. 2005. Causa Finale, Sostanza, Essenza in Aristotele. Napoli: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Rackham, H. 1932. Aristotle: Politics. Loeb Classical Library 264. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rapp, C. 2016. ‘The Principles of Sensible Substance in Metaphysics Λ 2-5’, in Horn, C. (ed.), Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda – New Essays, pp. 87118. Boston: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rapp, C. 2020. Introduction Part I: The Argument of De Motu Animalium, in Rapp, C. and Primavesi, O. (eds.). Aristotle’s De motu animalium: Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 166. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rapp, C. and Primavesi, O. (eds.). 2020. Aristotle’s De motu animalium: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rashed, M. 2012. ‘Il Timeo: negazione del principio di necessità condizionale, matematica e teodicea’, in Chiaradonna, R. (ed.), Il Platonismo e le Scienze, pp. 6579. Roma: Carocci.Google Scholar
Rea, M. C. 1995. ‘The Problem of Material Constitution’, The Philosophical Review 104: 525–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, M. C. 1998. ‘Sameness without Identity: An Aristotelian Solution to the Problem of Material Constitution’, Ratio 11: 316–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2000. Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2016. Aristotle: Metaphysics. Translation with commentary. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. 2012. ‘Philosophy of Technology’, in Feiser, J. and Dowden, B. (eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/technolo/.Google Scholar
Robin, L. 1908. La théorie platonicienne des idées et des nombres d’aprés Aristote. Ètude historique et critique. Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1924. Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1936. Aristotle’s Physics. Translation with commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1951. Plato’s Theory of Ideas. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Salmieri, G. 2010. ‘Αἴσθησις, Ἐμπειρία, and the Advent of Universals in Posterior Analytics II 19’, Apeiron 43(2–3): 155–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scaltsas, T. 2009. ‘Mixing the Elements’, in Anagnostopoulos, G. (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, pp. 242–59. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Scaltsas, T. 2015. ‘Substantial Holism’, Philosophical Inquiry 39(1): 146–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scharle, M. 2015. ‘Man from Man but not Bed from Bed: Nature, Art and Chance in Phys. II’, in Leunissen, M. (ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A Critical Guide, pp. 88106. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnurrenberger, D. and Bryan, A. L. 1985. ‘A Contribution to the Study of the Naturefact-Artifact Controversy’, in Plew, M. G., Woods, J. C., and Pavesic, M. G. (eds.), Stone Tool Analysis: Essays in Honor of Don E. Crabtree, pp. 133–59. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1991. ‘Is Aristotle’s Teleology Anthropocentric?’, Phronesis 36(2): 179–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. 2007. Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. 2010. ‘Teleology, Aristotelian and Platonic’, in Lennox, J. G. and Bolton, R. (eds.), Being, Nature and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf, pp. 529. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. 2013. ‘Plato and the One-over-Many Principle’, in Chiaradonna, R. and Galluzzo, G. (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, pp. 113–37. Pisa: Edizioni della Normale.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1967. ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics: An Introduction’, in Sellars, W., Philosophical Perspectives. History of Philosophy, pp. 73124. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company .Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2005. ‘Review of Harte, V., Plato on Parts and Wholes (2002)’, The Philosophical Review 114: 273–77.Google Scholar
Shields, C. 2008. ‘Substance and Life in Aristotle’, Apeiron 41: 129–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simons, P. M. 1987. Parts: A Study in Ontology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Soavi, M. 2009. Antirealismo e artefatti. Sui limiti della natura. Milano: Franco Angeli.Google Scholar
Stavrianeas, S. 2015. Νature as a Principle of Change’, in Leunissen, M. J. (ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stein, N. 2011. ‘Aristotle’s Causal Pluralism’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93(2): 121–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, R. B. 2012. Themistius: On Aristotle Physics 1-3. Annotated translation. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 1999. Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2003. ‘Realism and Human Kinds’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67: 580609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2007a. Ordinary Objects. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, A. L. 2007b. ‘Artifacts and Human Concepts’, in Margolis, E. and Laurence, S. (eds.), Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation, pp. 5273. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tipton, J. 2014. Philosophical Biology in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals. Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuozzo, T. 2011. ‘How Dynamic Is Aristotle’s Efficient Cause?’, Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 15(2): 447–64.Google Scholar
Unger, P. 1979. ‘There Are No Ordinary Things’, Synthese 41: 117–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1990. Material Beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Vattimo, G. 1961. Il concetto di fare in Aristotele. Università di Torino.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M. and Lanza, D. 1971. Aristotele. Opere biologiche. Translation with commentary. UTET: Torino.Google Scholar
Viano, C. 2015. ‘Mixis and Diagnôsis: Aristotle and the “Chemistry” of the Sublunary World’, Ambix 62(3): 203–14.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wardy, R. 2005. ‘The Mysterious Aristotelian Olive’, Science in Context 18(1): 6991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterlow, S. 1982. Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle’s Physics: A Philosophical Study. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, J. 1992. ‘Living Bodies’, in Nussbaum, M. and Rorty, A. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s de Anima, pp. 7591. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 2001. Sameness and Substance Renewed. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, C. J. F. 1982. Aristotle’s De Generatione et Corruptione. Translated with notes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilpert, P. 1949. Zwei aristotelische Frühschriften über die Ideenlehre. Regensburg: Habbel.Google Scholar
Witt, C. 2003. Ways of Being: Potentiality and Actuality in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witt, C. 2015a. ‘In Defence of the Craft Analogy: Artifacts and Natural Teleology’, in Leunissen, M. (ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A Critical Guide, pp. 107–20. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Witt, C. 2015b. ‘“As If by Convention Alone”: The Unstable Ontology of Aristotle’s Ethics’, in Henry, D. and Nielsen, K. M. (eds.), Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle’s Science and Ethics, pp. 276–92. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, R. and Weisberg, M. 2004. ‘Interpreting Aristotle on Mixture: Problems about Elemental Composition from Philoponus to Cooper’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35(4): 681706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zedda, S. 2000. ‘How to Build a World Soul: A Practical Guide’, in Wright, M. R. (ed.), Reason and Necessity: Essays on Plato’s Timaeus, pp. 2341. London: Duckworth.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Marilù Papandreou, Universitetet i Bergen, Norway
  • Book: Aristotle's Ontology of Artefacts
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009340557.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Marilù Papandreou, Universitetet i Bergen, Norway
  • Book: Aristotle's Ontology of Artefacts
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009340557.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Marilù Papandreou, Universitetet i Bergen, Norway
  • Book: Aristotle's Ontology of Artefacts
  • Online publication: 14 December 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009340557.011
Available formats
×