Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vvkck Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T15:18:40.566Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 October 2017

Kareem Khalifa
Affiliation:
Middlebury College, Vermont
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, Peter. 1983. The nature of explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bartelborth, Thomas. 2002. “Explanatory unification.” Synthese 130 (1):91107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batterman, Robert W. 2000. “A ‘modern’ (= Victorian?) attitude towards scientific understanding.” Monist 83 (2):228257.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert W. 2002. The devil in the details: asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction and emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert W., and Rice, Collin C.. 2014. “Minimal model explanations.” Philosophy of science 81 (3):349376. doi: 10.1086/676677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bjorken, James. 1967. “Theoretical ideas on inelastic electron and muon scattering.” In 1967 international symposium on electron and photon interactions at high energies, edited by Berman, S. M., 109127. Stanford: International Union of Pure and Applied Physics, US Atomic Energy Commission.Google Scholar
Bogen, Jim. 2005. “Regularities and causality: generalizations and causal explanations.” Studies in history and philosophy of biological and biomedical sciences 36 (2):397420.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa. 2008. “Can classical structures explain quantum phenomena?The British journal for the philosophy of science 59 (2):217235. doi: 10.1093/bjps/axn004.Google Scholar
Bonjour, Laurence. 1998. In defense of pure reason: a rationalist account of a priori justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit: reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Braverman, Mike, Clevenger, John, Harmon, Ian, Higgins, Andrew, Horne, Zachary, Spino, Joseph, and Waskan, Jonathan. 2012. “Intelligibility is necessary for scientific explanation, but accuracy may not be.” In Proceedings of the thirty-fourth annual conference of the cognitive science society, edited by Miyake, Naomi, Peebles, David, and Cooper, Richard. Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Brogaard, Berit. Manuscript. “I know. Therefore, I understand.” http://www.academia.edu/download/3458713/BrogaardOnKvanvig2.pdfGoogle Scholar
Cao, Tian Yu. 2010. From current algebra to quantum chromodynamics: a case for structural realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, J. Adam, and Gordon, Emma C.. 2014. “Objectual understanding and the value problem.” American philosophical quarterly 51 (1):113.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2004. “From causation to explanation and back.” In The future for philosophy, edited by Leiter, Brian, 230245. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, Hasok. 2012. Is water H₂O?: evidence, realism and pluralism, Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick M. 1966. Theory of knowledge, Foundations of philosophy series. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Code, Lorraine. 1987. Epistemic responsibility. Hanover, NH: Published for Brown University Press by University Press of New England.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan. 1992. An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Craver, Carl F. 2007. Explaining the brain: mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cushing, James T. 1991. “Quantum theory and explanatory discourse: endgame for understanding?Philosophy of science 58 (3):337358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
David, Marian. 2001. “Truth as the epistemic goal.” In Knowledge, truth, and duty: essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue, edited by Steup, Matthias, 151169. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
De Regt, Henk W. 2004. “Discussion note: making sense of understanding.” Philosophy of science 71:98109.Google Scholar
De Regt, Henk W. 2009a. “The epistemic value of understanding.Philosophy of science 76 (5):585597. doi: 10.1086/605795.Google Scholar
De Regt, Henk W. 2009b. “Understanding and scientific explanation.” In Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives, edited by De Regt, Henk W., Leonelli, Sabina, and Eigner, Kai, 2142. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
De Regt, Henk W. 2015. “Scientific understanding: truth or dare?Synthese 192 (12):37813797. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0538-7.Google Scholar
De Regt, Henk W., and Dieks, Dennis. 2005. “A contextual approach to scientific understanding.” Synthese 144 (1):137170.Google Scholar
DePaul, Michael R., and Grimm, Stephen R.. 2007. “Review essay on Jonathan Kvanvig’s The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding.” Philosophy and phenomenological research 74 (2):498514.Google Scholar
Devitt, Michael. 2014. “There is no a priori.” In Contemporary debates in epistemology, edited by Steup, Matthias, Turri, John, and Sosa, Ernest, 185194. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Diéguez, Antonio. 2013. “When do models provide genuine understanding, and why does it matter?History and philosophy of the life sciences 35 (4):599620.Google Scholar
Diéguez, Antonio. 2015. “Scientific understanding and the explanatory use of false models.” In The future of scientific practice: ‘Bio-TechnoLogos’, edited by Bertolaso, Marta, 161178. London: Pickering & Chatto.Google Scholar
Díez, José, Khalifa, Kareem, and Leuridan, Bert. 2013. “General theories of explanation: buyer beware.” Synthese 190 (3):379396. doi: 10.1007/s11229-011-0020-8.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather E. 2009. “Reintroducing prediction to explanation.” Philosophy of science 76 (4):444463.Google Scholar
Doyle, Yannick, Egan, Spencer, Graham, Noah, and Khalifa, Kareem. Manuscript. “Non-factive understanding: a statement and defense.” Available from the author.Google Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z. 2004. “True enough.” Philosophical issues 14 (1):113131. doi: 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2004.00023.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z. 2007. “Understanding and the facts.” Philosophical studies 132 (1):3342.Google Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z. 2009a. “Exemplification, idealization, and scientific understanding.” In Fictions in science: philosophical essays on modeling and idealization, edited by Suárez, Mauricio, 7791. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z. 2009b. “Is understanding factive?” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Allan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 322330. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Faye, Jan. 2007. “The pragmatic-rhetorical theory of explanation.” In Rethinking explanation, edited by Persson, Johannes and Ylikoski, Petri, 4368. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael. 1974. “Explanation and scientific understanding.” Journal of philosophy 71 (1):519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galilei, Galileo. 1914. Dialogues concerning two new sciences. Translated by Crew, Henry and de Salvio, Antonio. New York: Macmillan. Original edition, 1638.Google Scholar
Garfinkel, Alan. 1981. Forms of explanation: rethinking the questions in social theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabó. 1998. “Galileo and the indispensability of scientific thought experiment.” The British journal for the philosophy of science 49 (3):397424. doi: 10.1093/bjps/49.3.397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gijsbers, Victor. 2013. “Understanding, explanation, and unification.” Studies In history and philosophy of science part A 44 (3):516522. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.12.003.Google Scholar
Gijsbers, Victor. 2014. “Unification as a measure of natural classification.” Theoria: revista de teoría, historia y fundamentos de la ciencia 29 (1):7182.Google Scholar
Glymour, Bruce. 2007. “In defence of explanatory deductivism.” In Causation and explanation, edited by Campbell, Joseph Keim, O’Rourke, Michael, and Silverstein, Harry S., 133154. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1976. “Discrimination and perceptual knowledge.” Journal of philosophy 73 (20):771791.Google Scholar
Gordon, Emma C. 2012. “Is there propositional understanding?Logos & episteme 3 (2):181192.Google Scholar
Greco, John. 2009. Achieving knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Greco, John. 2013. “Episteme: knowledge and understanding.” In Virtues and their vices, edited by Timpe, Kevin and Boyd, Craig A., 285301. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2006. “Is understanding a species of knowledge?The British journal for the philosophy of science 57 (3):515535.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2009a. “Epistemic normativity.” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Allan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 243264. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2009b. “Reliability and the sense of understanding.” In Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives, edited by De Regt, Henk W., Leonelli, Sabina, and Eigner, Kai, 8399. Pittsburgh: Univeristy of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2010. “The goal of understanding.” Studies in the history and philosophy of science 41 (4):337344. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2010.10.006.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2014. “Understanding as knowledge of causes.” In Virtue epistemology naturalized, edited by Fairweather, Abrol, 329345. Dordecht: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R. 2016. “Understanding and transparency.” In Explaining understanding: new essays in epistemology and the philosophy of science, edited by Grimm, Stephen R., Baumberger, Christoph and Ammon, Sabine, 212229. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1982. “Experimentation and scientific realism.” Philosophical topics 13:7188.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986. Change in view: principles of reasoning. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hazen, T. C., Dubinsky, E. A., DeSantis, T. Z., Andersen, G. L., Piceno, Y. M., Singh, N., Jansson, J. K., Probst, A., Borglin, S. E., Fortney, J. L., Stringfellow, W. T., Bill, M., Conrad, M. E., Tom, L. M., Chavarria, K. L., Alusi, T. R., Lamendella, R., Joyner, D. C., Spier, C., Baelum, J., Auer, M., Zemla, M. L., Chakraborty, R., Sonnenthal, E. L., D’Haeseleer, P., Holman, H. Y. N., Osman, S., Lu, Z., Van Nostrand, J. D., Deng, Y., Zhou, J., and Mason, O. U.. 2010. “Deep-sea oil plume enriches indigenous oil-degrading bacteria.” Science 330 (6001):204208. doi: 10.1126/science.1195979.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation, and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1966. Philosophy of natural science, Prentice-Hall foundations of philosophy series. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2009. “Moral testimony and moral epistemology.” Ethics 120 (1):94127. doi: 10.1086/648610.Google Scholar
Hills, Alison. 2015. “Understanding why.” Noûs 49 (2):661688. doi: 10.1111/nous.12092.Google Scholar
Hindriks, Frank. 2013. “Explanation, understanding, and unrealistic models.” Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 44 (3):523531. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.12.004.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher R. 1999. “Contrastive explanation and the demons of determinism.” The British journal for the philosophy of science 50 (4):585612.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher R., and Woodward, James. 2003. “Explanatory generalizations, part II: plumbing explanatory depth.” Noûs 37 (2):181199.Google Scholar
Humphreys, Paul. 1989. The chances of explanation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard C. 1969. “Statistical explanation vs. statistical inference.” In Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel, edited by Rescher, Nicholas, 104113. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.Google Scholar
Kelp, Christoph. 2014. “Knowledge, understanding and virtue.” In Virtue epistemology naturalized, edited by Fairweather, Abrol, 347360. Dordrecht: Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelp, Christoph. 2015. “Understanding phenomena.” Synthese 192 (12):37993816. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0616-x.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem. 2011. “Understanding, knowledge, and scientific antirealism.” Grazer philosophische studien 83 (1):93112.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem. 2012. “Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation?Philosophy of science 79 (1):1537.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem. 2013. “Understanding, grasping, and luck.” Episteme 10 (1):117.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem. 2015. “EMU defended: reply to Newman (2014).” European journal for philosophy of science 5 (3):377385. doi: 10.1007/s13194-015-0112-2.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem. 2016. “Must understanding be coherent?” In Explaining understanding: new perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science, edited by Grimm, Stephen R., Baumberger, Christoph, and Ammon, Sabine, 139164. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem, and Gadomski, Michael C.. 2013. “Understanding as explanatory knowledge: the case of Bjorken scaling.” Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 44 (3):384392. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2013.07.001.Google Scholar
Khalifa, Kareem, Millson, Jared, and Risjord, Mark. Forthcoming. “IBE: fundamentalism’s failures.” In Best explanations: new essays on inference to the best explanation, edited by McCain, Kevin and Poston, Ted. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1994. “Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence.” Philosophical issues 5:5169. doi: 10.2307/1522873.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. 1989. “Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world.” In Scientific explanation, edited by Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley C., 410506. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. 2003. The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. 2009a. “Responses to critics.” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Allan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 339352. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. 2009b. “The value of understanding.” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Allan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 95111. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2007. “Why we don’t deserve credit for everything we know.” Synthese 158 (3):345361.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1981. “A confutation of convergent realism.” Philosophy of science 48 (1):1949.Google Scholar
Lewis, David K. 1986. “Causal explanation.” In Philosophical papers, 214240. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lipton, Peter. 2004. Inference to the best explanation. 2nd ed. New York: Routledge. Original edition, 1991.Google Scholar
Lipton, Peter. 2009. “Understanding without explanation.” In Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives, edited by De Regt, Henk W., Leonelli, Sabina, and Eigner, Kai, 4363. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1988. Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 2002. “Explanation and epistemology.” In The Oxford handbook of epistemology, edited by Moser, Paul K., 408433. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. 2004. True to life: why truth matters. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lynch, Michael P. 2009. “The values of truth and the truth of values.” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Allan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 225242. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, Darden, Lindley, and Craver, Carl F.. 2000. “Thinking about mechanisms.” Philosophy of science 67:125.Google Scholar
Marshall, Barry J., and Robin Warren, J.. 1984. “Unidentified curved bacilli in the stomach of patients with gastritis and peptic ulceration.” The Lancet 323 (8390):13111315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, Barry J., Barrett, Leah J., Prakash, Chandra, McCallum, Richard W., and Guerrant, Richard L.. 1990. “Urea protects Helicobacter (Campylobacter) pylori from the bactericidal effect of acid.” Gastroenterology 99 (3):697702.Google Scholar
Marshall, Barry J., Stewart Goodwin, C., Robin Warren, J., Raymond Murray, Elizabeth D. Blincow, Stephen J. Blackbourn, Michael Phillips, Waters, Thomas E., and Sanderson, Christopher R.. 1988. “A prospective double-blind trial of duodenal ulcer relapse after eradication of Campylobacter pylori.” The Lancet 2:14371442.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra D. 1997. “Pragmatic laws.” Philosophy of science 64:468479.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra D. 2000. “Dimensions of scientific law.” Philosophy of science 67 (2):242265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mizrahi, Moti. 2012. “Idealizations and scientific understanding.” Philosophical studies 160 (2):237252. doi: 10.1007/s11098-011-9716-3.Google Scholar
Morris, Kevin. 2012. “A defense of lucky understanding.The British journal for the philosophy of science 63 (2):357371. doi: 10.1093/bjps/axr023.Google Scholar
Newman, Mark. 2012. “An inferential model of scientific understanding.” International studies in the philosophy of science 26 (1):126. doi: 10.1080/02698595.2012.653118.Google Scholar
Newman, Mark. 2013. “Refining the inferential model of scientific understanding.” International studies in the philosophy of science 27 (2):173197. doi: 10.1080/02698595.2013.813253.Google Scholar
Newman, Mark. 2014. “EMU and inference: what the explanatory model of scientific understanding ignores.” European journal for philosophy of science 4 (1):5574. doi: 10.1007/s13194-013-0075-0.Google Scholar
Norton, John D. 2007. “Causation as folk science.” In Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited, edited by Price, Huw and Corry, Richard, 1144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Orozco, Joshue. 2011. “Epistemic luck.” Philosophy compass 6 (1):1121. doi: 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00365.x.Google Scholar
Peacocke, Christopher. 2008. Truly understood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew. 1984. Constructing quarks: a sociological history of particle physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, Michael. 2009. The tacit dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Original edition, 1966.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl Raimund. 1963. Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2005. Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2007. “Recent work on epistemic value.” American philosophical quarterly 44 (2):85.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2008. “Knowing the answer, understanding, and epistemic value.” Grazer philosophische studien 77:325339.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2009a. “Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value.” Royal institute of philosophy supplements 64:1943. doi: 10.1017/S1358246109000046.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2009b. “Safety-based epistemology: whither now?Journal of philosophical research 34:3345.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2010. “Knowledge and understanding.” In The nature and value of knowledge: three investigations, edited by Pritchard, Duncan, Millar, Allan, and Haddock, Adrian, 390. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2012. “Anti-luck virtue epistemology.” Journal of philosophy 109 (3):247279.Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2014. “Knowledge and understanding.” In Virtue epistemology naturalized, edited by Fairweather, Abrol, 315327. Dordrecht: Springer International Publishing.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1978. “A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation.” Philosophy of science 45 (2):206226.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter. 1981. “Probability, explanation, and information.” Synthese 48:233256.Google Scholar
Riaz, Amber. 2015. “Moral understanding and knowledge.” Philosophical studies 172 (1):113128. doi: 10.1007/s11098-014-0328-6.Google Scholar
Riggs, Wayne. 2009. “Understanding, knowledge, and the meno requirement.” In Epistemic value, edited by Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Alan, and Pritchard, Duncan, 331338. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Riordan, Michael. 1987. The hunting of the quark: a true story of modern physics. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Risjord, Mark. 2000. Woodcutters and witchcraft: rationality and interpretive change in the social sciences. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Rohwer, Yasha. 2014. “Lucky understanding without knowledge.” Synthese 191 (5):945959. doi: 10.1007/s11229-013-0322-0.Google Scholar
Rohwer, Yasha, and Rice, Collin C.. 2013. “Hypothetical pattern idealization and explanatory models.” Philosophy of science 80 (3):334355. doi: 10.1086/671399.Google Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. 1997. “Easy possibilities.” Philosophy and phenomenological research 57 (4):907919. doi: 10.2307/2953809.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1984. Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1989. “Four decades of scientific explanation.” In Scientific Explanation, edited by Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley C., 3219. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Schoener, Thomas W., Spiller, David A., and Losos, Jonathan B.. 2001. “Predators increase the risk of catastrophic extinction of prey populations.” Nature 412 (6843):183186.Google Scholar
Schrenk, Markus A. 2004. “Galileo vs. Aristotle on free falling bodies.” Logical analysis and the history of philosophy 7.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard, and Lambert, Karel. 1994. “Outline of a theory of scientific understanding.” Synthese 101 (1):65120.Google Scholar
Scriven, Michael. 1959. “Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory.” Science 130 (3374):477482.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. Science, perception and reality. New York: Routledge & K. Paul.Google Scholar
Shadish, William R., Cook, Thomas D., and Campbell, Donald Thomas. 2001. Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for generalized causal inference. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 1980. Causal necessity: a pragmatic investigation of the necessity of laws. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliot. 1986. “Explanatory presupposition.” Australasian journal of philosophy 64:143149.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 1980. “The raft and the pyramid: coherence versus foundations.” Midwest studies in philosophy 5:325.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 1991. Knowledge in perspective: selected essays in epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 1999. “How to defeat opposition to Moore.” Noûs 33:141153.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 2007. Apt belief and reflective knowledge, volume 1: a virtue epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 2009. Apt belief and reflective knowledge, volume 2: reflective knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steel, Daniel. 2013. “Acceptance, values, and inductive risk.Philosophy of science 80 (5):818828. doi: 10.1086/673936.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2000. “Do large probabilities explain better?Philosophy of science 67 (3):366390.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2008. Depth: an account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2013. “No understanding without explanation.” Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 44 (3):510515. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.12.005.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2016. “How idealizations provide understanding.” In Explaining understanding: new essays in epistemology and philosophy of science, edited by Grimm, Stephen R., Baumberger, Christoph, and Ammon, Sabine, 3749. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Suárez, Mauricio. 2009. Fictions in science: philosophical essays on modeling and idealization, Routledge studies in the philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Emily. Manuscript. “Transforming knowledge into understanding.” Available from the author.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Emily, and Khalifa, Kareem. Manuscript. “Do idealizations provide non-factive understanding?” Available from the author.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 1978. “The best explanation: criteria for theory choice.” Journal of philosophy 75:7692.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 1992. Conceptual revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 1999. How scientists explain disease. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 2003. “Pathways to biomedical discovery.” Philosophy of science 70 (2):235254.Google Scholar
Thalos, M. 2002. “Explanation is a genus: an essay on the varieties of scientific explanation.” Synthese 130 (3):317354.Google Scholar
Trout, J. D. 2002. “Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding.” Philosophy of science 69:212233.Google Scholar
Trout, J. D. 2005. “Paying the price for a theory of explanation: de Regt’s discussion of Trout.” Philosophy of science 72:198208.Google Scholar
Trout, J. D. 2007. “The psychology of scientific explanation.” Philosophy compass 2/3:564591.Google Scholar
Turner, Stephen P. 2013. “Where explanation ends: understanding as the place the spade turns in the social sciences.” Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 44 (3):532538. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2012.12.001.Google Scholar
Turri, John. 2016. “Knowledge as achievement, more or less.” In Performance epistemology, edited by Fernandez, Miguel A., 124135. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The scientific image. New York: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vickers, Peter. 2013. Understanding inconsistent science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilkenfeld, Daniel A. 2013. “Understanding as representation manipulability.” Synthese 190 (6):9971016. doi: 10.1007/s11229-011-0055-x.Google Scholar
Wilkenfeld, Daniel A. 2014. “Functional explaining: a new approach to the philosophy of explanation.” Synthese 191 (14):33673391. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0452-z.Google Scholar
Wilkenfeld, Daniel A., and Hellmann, Jennifer K.. 2014. “Understanding beyond grasping propositions: A discussion of chess and fish.” Studies in history and philosophy of science part A 48 (0):4651. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2014.09.003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilkenfeld, Daniel A., Plunkett, Dillon, and Lombrozo, Tania. 2016. “Depth and deference: when and why we attribute understanding.” Philosophical studies 173 (2):373393. doi: 10.1007/s11098-015-0497-y.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James. 2002. “Explanation.” In Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science, edited by Machamer, Peter and Silberstein, Michael, 3754. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Woodward, James. 2003. Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James, and Hitchcock, Christopher R.. 2003. “Explanatory generalizations, part I: a counterfactual account.” Noûs 37 (1):124.Google Scholar
Worrall, John. 1989. “Structural realism: the best of both worlds?Dialectica 43 (1–2):99124.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad. 2001. “Collective belief and acceptance.” Synthese 129 (3):319333. doi: 10.1023/a:1013148515033.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda. 1996. Virtues of the mind: an inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda. 2001. “Recovering understanding.” In Knowledge, truth, and duty: essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue, edited by Steup, Matthias, 235252. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Kareem Khalifa, Middlebury College, Vermont
  • Book: Understanding, Explanation, and Scientific Knowledge
  • Online publication: 12 October 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108164276.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Kareem Khalifa, Middlebury College, Vermont
  • Book: Understanding, Explanation, and Scientific Knowledge
  • Online publication: 12 October 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108164276.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Kareem Khalifa, Middlebury College, Vermont
  • Book: Understanding, Explanation, and Scientific Knowledge
  • Online publication: 12 October 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108164276.009
Available formats
×