Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-25wd4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T21:30:44.008Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 September 2018

David G. Stern
Affiliation:
University of Iowa
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Wittgenstein in the 1930s
Between the <I>Tractatus</I> and the <I>Investigations</I>
, pp. 272 - 289
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackermann, Wilhelm 1924. Begründung des “tertium non datur” mittels der Hilbertschen Theorie der Widerspruchsfreiheit. Mathematische Annalen 93, 136.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry 2001. Kant’s Theory of Taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ambrose, Alice (ed.) 1979. Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1932–1935. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. (AWL)Google Scholar
Ammereller, Erich & Fischer, Eugen 2004. Wittgenstein at Work: Method in the Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 2011. The Simplicity of the Tractatus. In Geach, Mary & Gormally, Luke (eds.), From Plato to Wittgenstein: Essays by G. E. M. Anscombe. Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 171–180.Google Scholar
Appelqvist, Hanne 2013. Why Does Wittgenstein Say That Ethics and Aesthetics Are One and the Same? In Sullivan, Peter & Potter, Michael, (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4058.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Appelqvist, Hanne 2016. On Wittgenstein’s Kantian Solution of the Problem of Philosophy. The British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (4), 697719.Google Scholar
Arrington, Robert L. & Addis, Mark. (eds.) 2001. Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (ed.) 1959. Logical Positivism. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon 1979. Verehrung und Verkehrung: Waismann and Wittgenstein. In Luckhardt, C. G. (ed.), Wittgenstein: Sources and Perspectives. Hassocks: Harvester Press, 243285.Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon 2004. Wittgenstein’s Method: Neglected Aspects. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, Gordon & Hacker, P. M. S. 1980. An Analytical Commentary on Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Revised second edition, Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.Google Scholar
Baker, G. & Hacker, P. M. S. 1980a. Wittgenstein, Meaning and Understanding. Essays on the Philosophical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Revised second edition, Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.Google Scholar
Baker, G. & Hacker, P. M. S. 1985. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Revised second edition, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009.Google Scholar
Baker, G. & Hacker, P. M. S. 2005. Wittgenstein. Meaning and Understanding. Essays on the Philosophical Investigations. Revised second edition, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baker, G. & Hacker, P. M. S. 2009. Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity – Volume 2 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Revised second edition, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bakhurst, David. 2001. Wittgenstein and “I.” In Glock, Hans-Johann (ed.), Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 224245.Google Scholar
Barwise, Jon & Perry, , 1981. Situations and Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78, 668691.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, David 1987. The Art of Judgment. Mind 96 (382), 221244.Google Scholar
Bernays, Paul 1951. Über das Induktionsschema in der Rekursiven Zahlentheorie. In Menne, A., Wilhelmy, A. & Angstl, H. (eds.), Kontrolliertes Denken. Freiburg/Munich: Karl Alber Verlag, 1017.Google Scholar
Biesenbach, Hans 2014. Anspielungen und Zitate im Werk Ludwig Wittgensteins. Revised edition, Sofia: Sofia University Press.Google Scholar
Biletzki, Anat 2002. Overinterpreting vs. Misinterpreting Wittgenstein. In Haller, Rudolph & Puhl, Klaus (eds.), Wittgenstein and the Future of Philosophy. Kirchberg am Wechsel: ALWS, 1320.Google Scholar
Biletzki, Anat 2003. (Over)Interpreting Wittgenstein. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biletzki, Anat 2010. The “Language and World” of Religion. In Munz, Volker A., Puhl, Klaus & Wang, Joseph (eds.), Language and World. Kirchberg am Wechsel: ALWS, 147156.Google Scholar
Biletzki, Anat 2011. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Middle Works. In Oxford Bibliographies Online. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Biletzki, Anat & Matar, 2016. Ludwig Wittgenstein. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/wittgenstein/.Google Scholar
Boncompagni, Anna. 2016. Wittgenstein and Pragmatism. On Certainty in the Light of Peirce and James. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Boncompagni, A. Forthcoming. William James and Wittgenstein. In Klein, A. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of William James. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bouwsma, O. K. 1996. Bouwsma’s Notes on Wittgenstein’s Philosophy 1965–1975. Craft, J. L. & Hustwit, R. (eds.). Lewiston/Queenston/Lampeter: Edwin Mellen Press.Google Scholar
Breithaupt, Fritz, Raatzsch, & Bettina, Kremberg (eds.) 2003. Goethe and Wittgenstein: Seeing the World’s Unity in Its Variety. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Britton, Karl 1955. Portrait of a Philosopher. The Listener 53 #1372, June 16, 1955, 10711072. In Flowers 1999, 2, 205–206; Flowers 2016, 2, 491–497.Google Scholar
Brusotti, Marco 2014. Wittgenstein, Frazer und die “ethnologische Betrachtungsweise”. Berlin/Boston: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Cahill, Kevin 2011. The Fate of Wonder. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Calendar section (no author listed) 1929. Cambridge Review 51 (1248), November 15, 1929, viii.Google Scholar
Calcaterra, Rosa M. (ed.) 2006. Le Ragioni del Conoscere e dell’Agire: Scritti in onore di Rosaria Egidi. Milano: Franco Angeli.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf 19311932. Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache. Erkenntnis II, 219241. (Translated as “The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language” in Ayer 1959.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, Thomas D. 2014. Wittgenstein within the Philosophy of Religion. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley 1962. The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy. Philosophical Review 71 (1), 6793.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley 1965/1969. Aesthetic Problems of Modern Philosophy. Reprinted in Cavell 1969, 7396.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley 1969. Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley 1979. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Scepticism, Morality and Tragedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chesterton, G. K. 1990. Orthodoxy. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Child, William 2011. Wittgenstein on the First Person. In Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 375401.Google Scholar
Church, Alonzo 1932. A Set of Postulates for the Foundation of Logic. Annals of Mathematics 33, 346366 & 34, 839864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. 1941. The Calculus of Lambda-Conversion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cioffi, Frank 1998. Wittgenstein on Freud and Frazer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Citron, Gabriel 2012. Simple Objects of Comparison for Complex Grammars: An Alternative Strand in Wittgenstein’s Later Remarks on Religion. Philosophical Investigations 35 (1), 1842.Google Scholar
Citron, Gabriel 2013. Religious Language as Paradigmatic of Language in General: Wittgenstein’s 1933 Lectures. In Venturinha, Nuno (ed.), The Textual Genesis of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge, 1936.Google Scholar
Conant, James 2000. Elucidation and Nonsense in Frege and Early Wittgenstein. In Crary, & Read, (eds.), The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge, 174217.Google Scholar
Conant, James 2002. The Method of the Tractatus. In Reck, E. (ed.) From Frege to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 374462.Google Scholar
Conant, James 2007. Mild Mono-Wittgensteinianism. In Crary, (eds.), Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 31142.Google Scholar
Conant, James 2011. Wittgenstein’s Methods. In Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 620645.Google Scholar
Cornforth, Maurice 1939. Recollections of Cambridge Contemporaries. In Guest, Carmel Haden (ed.), David Guest: A Scientist Fights for Freedom (1911–1938). London: Lawrence & Wishart.Google Scholar
Cornish, Kimberley 1998. The Jew of Linz: Wittgenstein, Hitler and Their Secret Battle for the Mind. London: Century.Google Scholar
Crary, Alice (ed.) 2007. Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Crary, Alice & Rupert, Read, (eds.) 2000. The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Curry, Haskell B. 1941. A Formalisation of Recursive Arithmetic. American Journal of Mathematics, 63, 263282.Google Scholar
Czernin, Franz Josef 2006. Poesie, Propositionen und nicht-propositionale Erfahrung. In Electronic Journal Literatur Primär. http://www.ejournal.at/Essay/czernwitt.html, last accessed May 29, 2015.Google Scholar
Diamond, Cora 1991. The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy and the Mind. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, Cora 2004. Criss-Cross Philosophy. In Erich Ammereller, & Fischer, (eds.), Wittgenstein at Work: Method in the Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge, 201220.Google Scholar
Diamond, Cora 2005. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief: The Gulfs between Us. In Phillips, D. Z. & von der Ruhr, Mario (eds.), Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Aldershot: Ashgate, 99137.Google Scholar
Drury, M. O’C. 1984. Conversations with Wittgenstein. In Rhees, Rush (ed.), Recollections of Wittgenstein, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 97171. In Flowers, 1999, 3, 188252.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael 1977. Elements of Intuitionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Engelmann, Mauro L. 2011. What Wittgenstein’s “Grammar” Is Not (On Garver, Baker and Hacker, and Hacker on Wittgenstein on “Grammar”). Wittgenstein-Studien 2, 71102.Google Scholar
Engelmann, Mauro L. 2013. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development: Phenomenology, Grammar, Method, and the Anthropological View. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Engelmann, Mauro L. 2016. The Faces of Necessity, Perspicuous Representation, and the Irreligious Cult of the Useful (The Spenglerian Background to the Remarks on Frazer). In Albinus, L., Rothhaupt, J. G. F. & Seery, A. (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Frazer: The Text and the Matter. Göttingen: De Gruyter, 129174.Google Scholar
Engelmann, Mauro L. 2017. What Does a Phenomenological Language Do? (Revisiting “Some Remarks on Logical Form” in Its Context). In Silva, M. (ed.), Colors in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Engelmann, Mauro L. 2018 Phenomenology in Grammar: Explicitation-verificationism, Arbitrariness, and the Vienna Circle. In: Kuusela, O., Ometita, M. & Urcan, T. (eds.), Wittgenstein and Phenomenology. London: Routledge, 2246.Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Flowers III, F. A. (ed.) 1999. Portraits of Wittgenstein. 4 volumes, Bristol: Thoemmes Press.Google Scholar
Flowers III, F. A. & Ground, Ian (eds.) 2016. Portraits of Wittgenstein. 2 vols., second edition. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Floyd, Juliet 1998. The Uncaptive Eye: Solipsism in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. Boston University Studies in Philosophy and Religion, 19, 79108.Google Scholar
Floyd, Juliet 2012. Wittgenstein’s Diagonal Argument: A Variation on Cantor and Turing. In Dybjer, P., Linström, S., Palmgren, E. & Sundholm, G. (eds.), Epistemology versus Ontology. Dordrecht: Springer, 2544.Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert 1987. Wittgenstein. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert 1994. Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, Michael N. 2004. Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frascolla, Pasquale 1997. The Tractatus System of Arithmetic. Synthese 122, 353378.Google Scholar
Frazer, Sir James George 1922. The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic and Religion. One volume abridged edition. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob 1956. The Thought: A Logical Inquiry. Mind 65 (259) 289311.Google Scholar
Fronda, Earl Stanley, B. 2010. Wittgenstein’s (Misunderstood) Religious Thought. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
De Gaynesford, Maximilian 2017. Wittgenstein on “I” and the Self. In Glock, H-J. & Hyman, J. (eds.), A Companion to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 478490.Google Scholar
Gibson, Arthur 2010. The Wittgenstein Archive of Francis Skinner. In Venturinha, Nuno ed., Wittgenstein after His Nachlass. Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 6477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 1990. Philosophical Investigations: Principles of Interpretation. In Haller, Rudolf & Brandl, Johannes (eds.), Wittgenstein – Towards a Re-Evaluation. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 152162.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 1992. Cambridge, Jena, or Vienna? The Roots of the Tractatus. Ratio 5 (1), 123.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 1996. A Wittgenstein Dictionary. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 1997. Kant and Wittgenstein: Philosophy, Necessity and Representation. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (2), 285305.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann(ed.) 2001. Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 2001a. The Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. In Glock, Hans-Johann (ed.), Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 125.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann 2007. Perspectives on Wittgenstein: An Intermittently Opinionated Survey. In Kahane, , Guy, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and his Interpreters. Oxford: Blackwell 3765.Google Scholar
Glock, Hans-Johann & Hacker, P. M. S. 1996. Reference and the First-Person Pronoun. Language and Communication 16, 95105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldfarb, Warren 1997. Metaphysics and Nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit. Journal of Philosophical Research 22, 5773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, Laurence 1999. Clear and Queer Thinking: Wittgenstein’s Development and His Relevance to Modern Thought. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Goodstein, Reuben L. 1939. Mathematical Systems. Mind 48, 5873. Reprinted in Goodstein, 1965, 7996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1944. On the Restricted Ordinal Theorem. Journal of Symbolic Logic 9, 3341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1945. Function Theory in an Axiom-Free Equation Calculus. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 48, 401434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1947. Transfinite Ordinals in Recursive Number Theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic 12, 123129.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1951. Constructive Formalism. Leicester: Leicester University Press.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1954. Logic-Free Formalisations of Recursive Arithmetic. Mathematica Scandinavica 2, 247261.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1957. Recursive Number Theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1961. Recursive Analysis. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1965. Mathematical Logic. Leicester: Leicester University Press.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1971. The Development of Mathematical Logic. London: Logos Press.Google Scholar
Goodstein, R. L. 1972. Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics. In Ambrose, A. & Lazerowitz, M (eds.), Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophy and Language. London: Allen & Unwin: 271286.Google Scholar
Graham, Gordon 2014. Wittgenstein and Natural Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1972. Insight and Illusion: Wittgenstein on Philosophy and the Metaphysics of Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Revised second edition, 1986.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1986. Insight and Illusion: Themes in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. Revised second edition. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1990. Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind. An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, vol. 3. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1996. Wittgenstein: Mind and Will. An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, vol. 4. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1996a. Wittgenstein’s Place in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 2001. Wittgenstein: Connections and Controversies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 2010. Human Nature: The Categorical Framework. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 2010a. Wittgenstein’s Anthropological and Ethnological Approach. In Gálvez, Jesús Padilla (ed.), Philosophical Anthropology: Wittgenstein’s Perspective. Heusenstamm: Ontos, 1532.Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 2013. Two Conceptions of Language. In Hacker, Wittgenstein: Comparisons and Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 128151.Google Scholar
Hadot, Pierre 2002. What Is Ancient Philosophy? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hancock, P. & Martin-Löf, P. 1975. Syntax and Semantics of the Language of Primitive Recursive Functions. Preprint no. 3, Department of Mathematics, University of Stockholm.Google Scholar
Haugeland, John 1998. Truth and Rule-Following. In , Haugeland (ed.), Having Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 305361.Google Scholar
Herbrand, Jacques 1971. Écrits Logiques. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Hertz, H. R. 1899. The Principles of Mechanics Presented in a New Form. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hilbert, David & Bernays, P. 1934. Grundlagen der Mathematik. Vol. 1. Berlin: Springer (Second edition, 1968.)Google Scholar
Hilbert, David & Ackermann, W. 1928. Grundzüge der Theoretischen Logik. Berlin: Springer (Second edition, 1938.)Google Scholar
Hilbert, David 1967. On the Foundations of Logic and Arithmetic. In van Heijenoort, (ed.), From Frege to Gödel. A Sourcebook in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 130138. First published as “Über die Grundlagen der Logik und der Arithmetik,” in Verhandlungen des dritten Internationalen Mathematiker-Kongresses in Heidelberg vom 8. bis 13. August 1904. Leipzig: Teubner, 1904, 174–85.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D. 1998. The New Grounding of Mathematics. First Report. In Mancosu, P. (ed.), From Brouwer to Hilbert. The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s. New York: Oxford University Press 198214. First published as “Neubegründung der Mathematik. Erste Mitteilung,” Abhandlungen aus dem Mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, vol. 1, 1922, 57–177.Google Scholar
Hilmy, S. S. 1987. The Later Wittgenstein: The Emergence of a New Philosophical Method. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko 1991. An Impatient Man and His Papers. Synthese 87, 183201.Google Scholar
Hintikka, Merrill & Hintikka, Jaakko 1986. Investigating Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hrachovec, Herbert 2006. Wittgenstein’s Paperwork. An Example from the Big Typescript. In Papers of the 29th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Gasser, G., Kanzian, Chr, Runggaldier, E. (eds.), Kirchberg a.W.: ALWS, 131133.Google Scholar
Hyman, John 2001. The Gospel According to Wittgenstein. In Arrington, Robert L. & Addis, Mark (eds.), Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. London and New York: Routledge, 111.Google Scholar
James, William 1975. Pragmatism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Johannessen, Kjell S. 1988. The Concept of Practice in Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy. Inquiry 31 (3), 357369.Google Scholar
Johannessen, Kjell S. 1994. Philosophy, Art and Intransitive Understanding. In Kjell S. Johannessen, Rolf O. Larsen & Knut Olav Åmås (eds.),Wittgenstein and Norway. Oslo: Solum, 217250.Google Scholar
Joseph, H. W. B. 1931. Some Problems in Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kahane, Guy, Kanterian, Edward & Kuusela, Oskari (eds.) 2007. Wittgenstein and His Interpreters. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kannisto, Heikki 1986. Thoughts and Their Subject. Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica 40.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Edited and translated by Guyer, Paul and Wood, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (CPR)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Guyer, Paul and translated by Guyer, Paul & Matthews, E.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (CPJ)Google Scholar
Kaplan, David 1989. Demonstratives. In Almog, J., Perry, J. & Wettstein, H. (eds.), Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 481564.Google Scholar
Kenny, Anthony 1973. Wittgenstein. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Revised second edition, 2006.Google Scholar
Kienzler, Wolfgang 1997. Wittgensteins Wende zu seiner Spätphilosophie 1930–1932. Eine Historische und Systematische Darstellung [Wittgenstein’s turn to his late philosophy 1930–1932: a historical and systematic presentation]. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Kienzler, Wolfgang 2013. Wittgenstein und Spengler. In: , Rothhaupt/, Vossenkuhl, (eds.), Kulturen und Werte. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter, 317336.Google Scholar
Kirby, Laurie & Paris, J. 1982. Accessible Independence Results for Peano Arithmetic. Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society 14, 285293.Google Scholar
Klagge, James 2013. Wittgenstein and His Audience: Esotericist or Evangelist? In Nuno Venturinha (ed.), The Textual Genesis of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kukla, Rebecca 2006. Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wolfgang, Künne 2009. Wittgenstein and Frege’s Logical Investigations. In Hans-Johann, Glock & John, Hyman (eds.), Wittgenstein and Analytic Philosophy: Essays for P.M. S. Hacker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari 2001. Wittgenstein’s Way out of Kantian Philosophy. Papers of the 24th International Wittgenstein Symposium IX (1), 435439.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari 2008. The Struggle against Dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari 2011. The Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. In Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 597619.Google Scholar
Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie, (eds.) 2011. The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Labron, Tim 2013. Wittgenstein’s Religious Point of View. London, New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Lambek, J. 1988. On the Unity of Algebra and Logic. In Borceux, F. (ed.), Categorical Algebra and Its Applications. Berlin: Springer, 221229.Google Scholar
Lazenby, J. Mark 2006. The Early Wittgenstein on Religion. London, New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Lee, Desmond 1979. Wittgenstein 1929–1931. Philosophy 54, 211220. Reprinted in Flowers, & Ground, 2016, vol. 2, 476485.Google Scholar
Lewy, Casimir 1976. Meaning and Modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1689. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1975.Google Scholar
Longuenesse, Béatrice 1998. Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Luckhardt, C. G. (ed.) 1979. Wittgenstein: Sources and Perspectives. Hassocks: Harvester Press.Google Scholar
Lugg, Andrew 2013. Wittgenstein in the Mid-1930s: Calculi and Language-games. In Venturinha, Nuno (ed.), The Textual Genesis of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge, 135154.Google Scholar
Maatsch, Jonas (ed.) 2014. Morphologie und Moderne. Berlin/Boston: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Mácha, Jakub 2015. Wittgenstein on Internal and External Relations: Tracing All the Connections. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Malcolm, Norman 1954. Math Notes by [sic] Ludwig Wittgenstein. San Francisco. (A bootleg printing of Malcolm’s notes from the 1939 lectures.)Google Scholar
Malcolm, Norman 1984. Ludwig Wittgenstein. A Memoir with a Biographical Sketch by G. H. von Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mancosu, Paulo & Marion, Mathieu 2003. Wittgenstein’s Constructivization of Euler’s Proof of the Infinity of Primes. In Stadler, F. (ed.), The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism: Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives. Netherlands: Kluwer, 171188.Google Scholar
Marconi, Diego 2013. Wittgenstein and the “Idly Turning Wheels”. In Rovatti, P. A. & Vattimo, G., (eds.), Weak Thought. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Marion, Mathieu 1995. Wittgenstein and Finitism. Synthese 105, 141176.Google Scholar
Marion, M. 1998. Wittgenstein, Finitism and the Foundations of Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Marion, M. 2011. Wittgenstein on the Surveyability of Proofs. In Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 138161.Google Scholar
McDowell, John 2009. How Not to Read Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: Brandom’s Wittgenstein. In McDowell, The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays, 96112. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McGuinness, Brian 1981. Freud and Wittgenstein. In Brian McGuinness, 2002, 224235.Google Scholar
McGuinness, Brian 2002. Approaches to Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McGuinness, Brian 2016. Arthur MacIver’s Diary: Cambridge (October 1929 – March 1930). Wittgenstein-Studien 7, 201256.Google Scholar
Misak, Cheryl 2016. Cambridge Pragmatism. From Peirce and James to Ramsey and Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Monk, Ray 1990. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Moore, Adrian 1985. Transcendental Idealism in Wittgenstein, and Theories of Meaning. The Philosophical Quarterly 35 (139), 134155.Google Scholar
Moore, Adrian 2013. Was the Author of the Tractatus a Transcendental Idealist? In Sullivan, Peter & Potter, Michael (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 239255.Google Scholar
Moore, Adrian & Sullivan, Peter, 2003. Ineffability and Nonsense. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 77 (1), 195223.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. Add. 8875, 15/10 Wittgenstein’s use of “grammar.” Cambridge: Cambridge University Library.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1942. Autobiography. In: Schilpp, P. A., (ed.), G. E. Moore (The Library of Living Philosophers). Evanston, IL: Open Court, 1–38.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1955. “Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930–33.” First published in three parts in Mind in 1954–1955. References are to PO, 45114. (MWL)Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1959. Philosophical Papers, London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., Joseph, H. W. B. & Taylor, A. E. 1932. Symposium: Is Goodness a Quality? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 11, 116168.Google Scholar
Moore, Gregory H., 1988. The Emergence of First-Order Logic. In Aspray, W. & Kitcher, P. (eds.), History and Philosophy of Modern Mathematics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 95135.Google Scholar
Mulhall, Stephen 2011. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief. In Oskari Kuusela & Marie McGinn (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 755774.Google Scholar
Nielsen, Kai 1967. Wittgensteinian Fideism. Philosophy 42, 191209.Google Scholar
Nielsen, Kai & Phillips, D. Z. 2005. Wittgensteinian Fideism? London: SCM Press.Google Scholar
Noë, Alva 1994. Wittgenstein, Phenomenology and What It Makes Sense to Say. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54, (1), 142.Google Scholar
Nordmann, Alfred 2005. Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nyíri, J. C. 1986. Gefühl und Gefüge: Studien zum Entstehen der Philosophie Wittgensteins [Structure and Sentiment: Studies on the Emergence of the Philosophy of Wittgenstein]. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Nyíri, J. C. 1992. Tradition and Individuality. Essays. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Ogden, C. K. & Richards, I. A., 1960. The Meaning of Meaning. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Okada, Mitsuhiro & Scott, P. J. 2000. A Note on Rewriting Theory for Uniqueness of Iteration. Theory and Application of Categories 6 (4), 4764.Google Scholar
Okada, Mitsuhiro 2007. On Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Recursive Proofs: A Preliminary Report. In Okada, M. (ed.), Essays in the Foundations of Logical and Phenomenological Studies. Tokyo: Keio University Press, 121131.Google Scholar
Pears, David 1987. The False Prison vol. I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pears, David 1988. The False Prison vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Perissinotto, Luigi & Sanfélix, Vincente (eds.) 2010. Doubt, Ethics and Religion: Wittgenstein and the Counter-Enlightenment. Heusenstamm: Ontos.Google Scholar
Phillips, D. Z. & von der Ruhr, Mario. (eds.) 2005. Religion and Wittgenstein’s Legacy. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Pichler, Alois 1994. Untersuchungen zu Wittgensteins Nachlaß. Working Papers from the Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen 8. Bergen: WAB.Google Scholar
Pichler, Alois 2004. Wittgensteins Philosophische Untersuchungen: Vom Buch zum Album. Studien zur Österreichischen Philosophie 36 (Edited by Haller, Rudolf). Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Pichler, Alois 2007. The Interpretation of the Philosophical Investigations: Style, Therapy, Nachlass. In Guy Kahane, , Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.) Wittgenstein and his Interpreters. Oxford: Blackwell, 123144.Google Scholar
Pichler, Alois & Säätelä, Simo (eds.) 2005. Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works. Bergen: Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen. Second edition, 2006. Frankfurt am Main: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
Potter, Michael 2000. Reason’s Nearest Kin. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Potter, M. 2011. Wittgenstein on Mathematics. In Kuusela, Oskari & McGinn, Marie (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 122137.Google Scholar
Ramsey, Frank. P. 1923. Critical Notice: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Mind 32, 465478.Google Scholar
Ramsey, Frank P. 1990. Philosophical Papers. Edited by Mellor, David H.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Reid, L. A., Knight, H. & Joad, C. E. M. 1932. The Limits of Psychology in Aesthetics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 11, 169215.Google Scholar
Rhees, Rush, (ed.), 1984. Recollections of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Richards, I. A. 1972. Internal Colloquies: Poems and Plays of I.A. Richards. New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich.Google Scholar
Richter, Duncan 1996. Nothing to Be Said: Wittgenstein and Wittgensteinian Ethics. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 34, 243256.Google Scholar
Ricketts, Thomas 2018. Sketches of Blurred Landscapes: Wittgenstein and Ethics. In Wittgenstein’s Moral Thought, Reshef Agam-Segal & Edmund Dain (eds.), 153173. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ricketts, Thomas 2013. Logical Segmentation and Generality in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In Sullivan, Peter & Potter, Michael (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 125142.Google Scholar
Rose, H. E. 1988. Obituary: R. L. Goodstein. Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society 20, 159166.Google Scholar
Rothhaupt, Josef 1996. Farbthemen in Wittgenstein’s Gesamtnachlass [Colour Themes in Wittgenstein’s Complete Writings] Weinheim: Beltz.Google Scholar
Rothhaupt, Josef 2007. Moores Statement über “Wittgenstein’s Expressions ‘Rule of Grammar’ or ‘Grammatical Rule.’” In W. Lütterfelds, (ed.), Wittgenstein Jahrbuch 2003/2006. Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 209229.Google Scholar
Rothhaupt, Josef 2008. Kreation und Komposition. München: LMU Habilitationsschrift.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand 1921. The Analysis of Mind. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand 1927. An Outline of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand 19351936. The Limits of Empiricism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society New Series, 36.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand 1998. Autobiography. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schönbaumsfeld, Genia 2007. A Confusion of the Spheres: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on Philosophy and Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Severin 2001. The Coded-Message Model of Literature. In Allen, R. & Turvey, M. (eds.), Wittgenstein, Theory, and the Arts. New York: Routledge, 210228.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 1982. Chor und Gesetz: Zur “morphologischen Methode” bei Goethe und Wittgenstein. In Schulte 1990, 1142.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 1990. Chor und Gesetz: Wittgenstein im Kontext. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 1992. Wittgenstein: An Introduction. Transl. Brenner, William H. & Holley, John F.. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 1998. Review of Wolfgang Kienzler Wittgensteins Wende zu seiner Spätphilosophie 1930–1932. European Journal of Philosophy 6, 379385.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2002. Wittgenstein’s Method. In Haller, Rudolf & Puhl, Klaus (eds.), Wittgenstein and the Future of Philosophy. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 399410.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2003. Goethe and Wittgenstein on Morphology. In Breithaupt, Fritz, Richard, Raatzsch and Bettina, Kremberg (eds.), Goethe and Wittgenstein: Seeing the World’s Unity in Its Variety. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 5572.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2005. What Is a Work by Wittgenstein? In Pichler, Alois & Säätelä, Simo (eds.), Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works. Bergen: Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen, 356363.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2006. The Pneumatic Conception of Thought. Grazer Philosophische Studien 71, 3955.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2006a. Phenomenology and Grammar. In Calcaterra, Rosa M. (ed.), Le Ragioni del Conoscere e dell’Agire: Scritti in onore di Rosaria Egidi. Milano: Franco Angeli, 228240.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2011. Waismann as Spokesman for Wittgenstein. In McGuinness, B.F., (ed.), Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, 15. Dordrecht: Springer, 225241.Google Scholar
Schulte, Joachim 2014. Ideen mit den Augen sehen: Goethe und Wittgenstein über Morphologie. In Maatsch, Jonas (ed.), Morphologie und Moderne. Berlin/Boston: Walter de Gruyter, 141156.Google Scholar
Sedmak, Clemens 1996. Kalkül und Kultur: Studien zu Genesis und Geltung von Wittgensteins Sprachspielmodell [Calculus and Culture: studies of the genesis and validity of Wittgenstein’s language game model]. Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney 1968. Self-Reference and Self-Awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65, 555567.Google Scholar
Skolem, Thoralf 1967a. Some Remarks on Axiomatized Set Theory. In van Heijenoort 1967, 291–301. First published as Einige Bemerkungen zur axiomatischen Begründung der Mengenlehre, reprinted in Skolem, 1970, 137152.Google Scholar
Skolem, Thoralf 1967b. “The Foundations of Elementary Arithmetic established by Means of the Recursive Mode of Thought, without Use of Apparent Variables Ranging over Infinite Domains.” In van Heijenoort 1967, 303333. First published as Begründung der elementaren Arithmetik durch die rekurrierende Denkweise ohne Anwendung scheinbarer Veränderlichen mit unendlichen Ausdehnungsbereich, reprinted in Skolem, , 1970, 153188.Google Scholar
Skolem, Thoralf 1970. Selected Works in Logic. Fenstad, J. E. (ed.). Oslo: Universtetsforlaget.Google Scholar
Sloan, Pat (ed.) 1938. John Cornford: A Memoir. London: Jonathan Cape.Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans 1996. “Whose House Is That?” Wittgenstein on the Self. In Sluga, Hans & Stern, D., (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 320353.Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans 2004. Wittgenstein and Pyrrhonism. In Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans 2011. Wittgenstein. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans 2013. Beyond the “New” Wittgenstein. In Greif, Hajo & Weiss, Martin Gerhard (eds.), Ethics, Society, Politics. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter, 1134.Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans & Stern, David G. (eds.) 1996. The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second, revised edition, 2018.Google Scholar
Stenius, Erik 1960. Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: A Critical Exposition of Its Main Lines of Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 1991. The “Middle Wittgenstein”: From Logical Atomism to Practical Holism. Synthese 87, 203226.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 1995. Wittgenstein on Mind and Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 1996. The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. In Sluga, Hans & Stern, D. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 442476.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2004. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2005. How Many Wittgensteins? In Pichler, Alois & Säätelä, Simo (eds.), Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works. Bergen: Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen, 164188.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2010. Another Strand in the Private Language Argument. In Ahmed, Arif (ed.) Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 178196.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2010a. Tracing the Development of Wittgenstein’s Writing on Private Language. In Venturinha, Nuno (ed.), Wittgenstein after His Nachlass. Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 110127.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2014. The “Middle Wittgenstein” Revisited. In Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, Munz, Volker A. & Coliva, Annalisa (eds.), Mind, Language and Action. Göttingen: de Gruyter, 181204.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2017. Wittgenstein’s Texts and Style. In Glock, Hans-Johann & Hyman, John (eds.), A Companion to Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell, 41–55.Google Scholar
Stern, David G. 2018. Wittgenstein in the 1930s. In Hans, Sluga, & David, Stern (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein, second edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 126–151.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1959. Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1994. The First Person – And Others. In Cassam, Q. (ed.), Self-Knowledge, 210215. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sturgeon, Nicholas & Brown, Stuart Jr. 1991. Memorial Minutes for Max Black. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 64 (5), January 1991.Google Scholar
Peter, Sullivan & Potter, Michael 2013. Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Peter 1996. The Truth in Solipsism, and Wittgenstein’s Rejection of the A Priori. European Journal of Philosophy 4 (2), 195219.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Peter 2013. Idealism in Wittgenstein: A Further Reply to Moore. In Sullivan, Peter & Potter, Michael (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: History and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 256270.Google Scholar
Szeltner, Sarah 2013. “Grammar” in the Brown Book. In Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, Munz, Volker A. & Coliva, Annalisa (eds.), Mind, Language and Action: Contributions to the 36th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society, 403405.Google Scholar
Trevelyan, Julian 1957. Indigo Days. London: MacGibbon & Kee.Google Scholar
van Heijenoort, Jean (ed.) 1967. From Frege to Gödel. A Sourcebook in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Venturinha, Nuno (ed.) 2010. Wittgenstein after His Nachlass. Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Venturinha, Nuno (Ed.) 2013. The Textual Genesis of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
von Plato, Jan 2014. Generality and Existence: Quantificational Logic in Historical Perspective. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20, 417448.Google Scholar
von Wright, Georg Henrik 1982. Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
von Wright, Georg Henrik 1984. A Biographical Sketch. In Malcolm, Norman (ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein. A Memoir with a Biographical Sketch by G. H. von Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 320.Google Scholar
von Wright, Georg Henrik 1993. The Wittgenstein Papers. In PO, 480515.Google Scholar
Waismann, Friedrich 1997. The Principles of Linguistic Philosophy. Second edition; first edition 1965. Basingstoke, Hampshire: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Waismann, Friedrich 2003. Introduction to Mathematical Thinking: The Formation of Concepts in Modern Mathematics. Mineola, NY: Dover. Reprint of the fourth, 1966, printing of the Harper Torchbook edition. A translation of Einführung in das mathematische Denken by Benac, Theodore J..Google Scholar
Wallgren, Thomas 2006. Transformative Philosophy. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translation on facing pages by Ogden, C. K.. Second edition, 1933. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (TLP)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Translation on facing pages by Anscombe, G. E. M.. Oxford: Blackwell. Second edition, 1958. Third, revised edition, 2001. Revised fourth edition. Edited by Hacker, P. M. S. & Schulte, Joachim, 2009. Translation on facing pages by Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S. & Schulte, Joachim. (PI)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Preliminary Studies for the “Philosophical Investigations”. References are to The Blue Book (BLBK) or The Brown Book (BRBK). Second edition, 1969. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1961a. Notebooks 1914–1916. Edited by von Wright, G. H. & Anscombe, G. E. M., translated by Anscombe, G. E. M.. Second edition, 1979. Oxford: Blackwell. (NB)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1961b. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by Pears, D. F. & McGuinness, B. F.. London: Routledge. (TLP)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1964. Philosophical Remarks. First published as Philosophische Bemerkungen, German text only. Edited by Rhees, R.. Oxford: Blackwell. Second edition, 1975, translated by Hargreaves, R. & White, R.. Oxford: Blackwell. (PR)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1966. Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Edited by Barrett, Cyril. Berkeley: University of California Press. (LC)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1967a. Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. In PO, 118155.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1967b. Zettel. Anscombe, G. E. M. & von Wright, G. H. (eds.) translation on facing pages by Anscombe, G. E. M.. Oxford: Blackwell. Second edition, 1981.(Z)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1974a. On Certainty. Anscombe, G. E. M. & von Wright, G. H. (eds.). Oxford: Blackwell. Second revised edition, first published in 1969. (OC)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1974b. Philosophical Grammar. First published in 1969 as Philosophische Grammatik, German text only. Edited by Rhees, R.. Oxford: Blackwell. English translated by Kenny, A., 1974. Oxford: Blackwell. (PG)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1976. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge 1939. Edited by Diamond, C.. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (LFM)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1978. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Revised edition, von Wright, G. H. & Anscombe, G. E. M. (eds.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (RFM)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979a. Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. Edited by McGuinness, B., translated by Schulte, J. & McGuinness, B.. Oxford: Blackwell. First published in German in 1967. (WWK)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979b. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge 1932–1935: From the Notes of Alice Ambrose and Margaret MacDonald. Edited by Ambrose, Alice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (AWL)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980a. Wittgenstein’s Lectures: Cambridge, 1930–1932, from the Notes of John King and Desmond Lee. Edited by Lee, Desmond. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (LWL)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1980b. Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology. Edited by Anscombe, G. E. M. & von Wright, G. H.. Two volumes. Oxford: Blackwell. (RPP)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1988. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on Philosophical Psychology: 1946–47. Edited by Geach, Peter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1993a. Philosophical Occasions 1912–1951. Edited by Klagge, James & Nordmann, Alfred. Indianapolis: Hackett. (PO)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1993b. Wiener Ausgabe [Vienna Edition]. Edited by Nedo, Michael. Vienna: Springer.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1994. Wiener Ausgabe, vol. 2. Edited by Nedo, M.. Vienna: Springer. (Wi2)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1995. Wiener Ausgabe, vol. 3. Edited by Nedo, M.. Vienna: Springer. (Wi3)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1996. Wiener Ausgabe, vol. 5. Edited by Nedo, M.. Vienna: Springer. (Wi5)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1998. Culture and Value. Edited by von Wright, G. H. & Pichler, A., translated by Winch, P.. Oxford: Blackwell. First edition, 1977; second edition, 1980. Revised edition by von Wright, G. H., Nyman, Heikki & Pichler, Alois, with a new translated by Winch, Peter, 1998. (CV)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2000. Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (TS/MS)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2001. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Kritisch-genetische Edition. [Philosophical Investigations. Critical-genetic edition.] Edited by Schulte, Joachim. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2003. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Public and Private Occasions. Edited by Klagge, James & Nordmann, Alfred. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. (PPO)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2005. The Big Typescript: TS 213. Edited by Luckhardt, C. Grant & Maximilian, A. E. Aue, translation on facing pages. Oxford: Blackwell. (BT)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2008. Wittgenstein in Cambridge: Letters and Documents 1911–1951. Edited by McGuinness, Brian. Oxford: Blackwell. Revised edition, 2012. (WC)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2009. Wittgenstein Source Bergen Nachlass Edition. Edited by the Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen under the direction of Alois Pichler. Bergen: WAB. [Ts/Ms]Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2016. Wittgenstein: Lectures, Cambridge 1930–1933, From the Notes of G. E. Moore. Edited by Stern, David, Rogers, Brian, & Citron, Gabriel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Citations are to print and MS pages. (M)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2017. Wittgenstein’s Whewell’s Court Lectures, Cambridge 1938–1941. Edited by Munz, Volker A. & Ritter, Bernhard. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. (WWCL)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig & Waismann, Friedrich, 2003. The Voices of Wittgenstein: The Vienna Circle. Edited by Baker, Gordon and translated by Baker, et al. London: Routledge. (VW)Google Scholar
Zach, Richard 2003. The Practice of Finitism: Epsilon Calculus and Consistency Proofs in Hilbert’s Program. Synthese 137, 211259.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by David G. Stern, University of Iowa
  • Book: Wittgenstein in the 1930s
  • Online publication: 17 September 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108349260.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by David G. Stern, University of Iowa
  • Book: Wittgenstein in the 1930s
  • Online publication: 17 September 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108349260.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by David G. Stern, University of Iowa
  • Book: Wittgenstein in the 1930s
  • Online publication: 17 September 2018
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108349260.017
Available formats
×