Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T10:47:05.144Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 August 2020

John Greco
Affiliation:
Georgetown University, Washington DC
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, Peter, The Nature of Explanation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983).Google Scholar
Adler, Jonathan, “Transmitting Knowledge,” Noûs 30, 1 (1996): 99111.Google Scholar
Adler, Jonathan, “Epistemological Problems of Testimony,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 edition), available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/testimony-episprob.Google Scholar
Alston, William P., “Christian Experience and Christian Belief,” in Plantinga, Alvin and Wolterstorff, Nicholas, eds., Faith and Rationality (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 103134.Google Scholar
Alston, William P., Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991).Google Scholar
Alston, William P., The Reliability of Sense Perception (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Anscombe, G.E.M, “What Is It to Believe Someone?” in Faith in a Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics (Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic Philosophy Documentation Center, 2008).Google Scholar
Austin, J.L., “Other Minds,” in Austin, J.L., Philosophical Papers, 3rd edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).Google Scholar
Baillargeon, Renée, and DeVos, Julie, “Object Permanence in Young Infants: Further Evidence,” Child Development 62, 6 (1991): 12271246.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bechtel, William, “Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind: An Overview,” in Lycan, William, ed., Mind and Cognition (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990).Google Scholar
Beer, A.L., Heckel, A.H., and Greenlee, M.W., “A Motion Illusion Reveals Mechanisms of Perceptual Stabilization,” PLoS ONE 3, 7 (2008): e2741.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Michael, “Skeptical Theism and Rowe’s New Evidential Argument from Evil,” Noûs 35, 2 (2001): 278296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, Cristina, The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Bicchieri, Cristina, Muldoon, Ryan, and Sontuoso, Alessandro, “Social Norms,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 edition), available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/social-norms/Google Scholar
Bogardus, Tomas, “The Problem of Contingency for Religious Belief,” Faith and Philosophy 30, 4 (2013): 371392.Google Scholar
Bowles, Samuel, and Gintis, Herbert, “Origins of Human Cooperation,” in Hammerstein, Peter, ed., Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2003), pp. 429443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowles, Samuel, and Gintis, Herbert, A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael E., “Shared Cooperative Activity,” Philosophical Review 101, 2 (1992): 327341.Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael E., “Shared Intention,” Ethics 104, 1 (1993): 97113.Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael E., Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael E., “Shared Agency,” in Mantzavinos, C., ed., Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Philosophical Theory and Scientific Practice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 4159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler, “Content Preservation,” The Philosophical Review 102, 4 (1993): 457488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carballo, Alejandro Pérez, “On Greco on Transmission,” Episteme 13, 4 (2016): 499505.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy, “From Causation to Explanation and Back,” in Leiter, Brian ed., The Future for Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 230245.Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick, Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edition (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1977).Google Scholar
Christensen, David, “Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News,” Philosophical Review 116, 2 (2007): 187217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Herbert H., Using Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Coady, C.A.J., Testimony: A Philosophical Study (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Coliva, Annalisa, Moore and Wittgenstein: Scepticism, Certainty and Common Sense (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010).Google Scholar
Collins, Patricia Hill, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment (London: Routledge, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, Earl, and Feldman, Richard, “The Generality Problem for Reliabilism,” Philosophical Studies 89, 1 (1998): 129.Google Scholar
Craig, Edward, Knowledge and the State of Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).Google Scholar
Elga, Adam, “Reflection and Disagreement,” Noûs, 41, 3 (2007): 478502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, Catherine, Considered Judgment (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Falcon, Andrea, “Aristotle on Causality,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2011), available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/aristotle-causality.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy, and McGrath, Matthew, “Evidence, Pragmatics, and Justification,” Philosophical Review 111, 1 (2002): 694.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy, and McGrath, Matthew, Knowledge in an Uncertain World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar
Faulkner, Paul, Knowledge on Trust (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frances, Bryan, “Disagreement,” in Pritchard, Duncan & Bernecker, Sven, eds., Routledge Companion to Epistemology (New York: Routledge, 2010), pp. 6874.Google Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth, “The Epistemology of Testimony,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 61 (suppl.) (1987): 5783.Google Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth, “Against Gullibility,” in Matilal, B.K. and Chakrabarti, A., eds., Knowing from Words (Boston, MA: Kluwer, 1994), pp. 125161.Google Scholar
Fricker, Elizabeth, “Second-Hand Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73, 3 (2006): 592618.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda, Epistemic injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, Susan A., The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, Edmund, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis 23, 6 (1963): 121123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, “Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15, 1 (1990): 114.Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, “Reductionism and the Distinctiveness of Testimonial Knowledge,” in Lackey, Jennifer and Sosa, Ernest, eds., The Epistemology of Testimony (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 127144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, Anti-Individualism: Mind and Language, Knowledge and Justification (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, “Testimonial Knowledge in Early Childhood, Revisited,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76, 1 (2008): 136.Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, Relying on Others: An Essay in Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, “The Division of Epistemic Labor,” Episteme 8, 1 (2011): 112125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, “A Proposed Research Program for Social Epistemology,” in Reider, P., ed., Social Epistemology and Epistemic Agency (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2017).Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, “‘Analytic Social Epistemology’ and the Epistemic Significance of Other Minds,” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 2, 8 (2013): 2648.Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford, and Henderson, David, “Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72, 3 (2006): 576593.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin, “What Is Justified Belief?” in Pappas, George, ed., Justification and Knowledge (Boston, MA: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 125.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter, “Transferring Knowledge,” Noûs 34, 1 (2000): 131152.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter, “Can Testimony Generate Knowledge?Philosophica 78 (2006): 105127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, Peter, “Liberal Fundamentalism and Its Rivals” in Lackey, Jennifer and Sosa, Ernest, eds., The Epistemology of Testimony (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 93115.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter, “Epistemic Normativity and Social Norms,” in Henderson, David and Greco, John, eds., Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), pp. 247273.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter, “The Reliability of Testimony and Social Norms” (manuscript).Google Scholar
Greco, John, Putting Skeptics in Their Place: The Nature of Skeptical Arguments and Their Role in Philosophical Inquiry (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John, “Knowledge as Credit for True Belief,” in DePaul, Michael and Zagzebski, Linda, eds., Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 111134.Google Scholar
Greco, John, “The Nature of Ability and the Purpose of Knowledge,” Philosophical Issues 17 (2007): 5769.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John, “Friendly Theism” in Kraft, James and Basinger, David, eds., Religious Tolerance through Humility (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2008), pp. 5158.Google Scholar
Greco, John, “What’s Wrong with Contextualism?The Philosophical Quarterly 58, 232 (2008): 416436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John, “Religious Knowledge in the Context of Conflicting Testimony,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 82 (2009): 6176.Google Scholar
Greco, John, Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Greco, John, “Evidentialism and Knowledge,” in Dougherty, Trent, ed., Evidentialism and Its Discontents (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 167178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John, “Recent Work on Testimonial Knowledge,” American Philosophical Quarterly 49, 1 (2012): 1528.Google Scholar
Greco, John, “A (Different) Virtue Epistemology,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85, 1 (2012): 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John, “Episteme: Knowledge and Understanding,” in Timpe, Kevin and Boyd, Craig, eds., Virtues and Their Vices (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), pp. 285302.Google Scholar
Greco, John, “Testimonial Knowledge and the Flow of Information,” in Henderson, David and Greco, John, eds. Epistemic Evaluation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), pp. 274290.Google Scholar
Greco, John, “Intellectual Humility and Contemporary Epistemology: A Critique of Epistemic Individualism, Evidentialism, and Internalism,” in Alfano, Mark, Lynch, Michael, and Tanesini, Alessandra, eds., The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility (New York: Routledge, 2020).Google Scholar
Greco, John, and Turri, John, “Virtue Epistemology,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2015), available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/epistemology-virtue.Google Scholar
Green, Adam, “Reading the Mind of God (without Hebrew Lessons): Alston, Shared Attention, and Mystical Experience,” Religious Studies 45, 4 (2009): 455470.Google Scholar
Green, Adam, “Deficient Testimony is Deficient Teamwork,” Episteme 11, 2 (2014): 213227.Google Scholar
Green, Adam, The Social Contexts of Intellectual Virtue: Knowledge as a Team Achievement (New York: Routledge, 2017).Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R., “Is Understanding a Species of Knowledge?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57, 3 (2006): 515535.Google Scholar
Grimm, Stephen R., “Understanding,” in Berneker, Sven and Pritchard, Duncan, eds. The Routledge Companion to Epistemology (New York: Routledge, 2011), pp. 8494.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R.J., “Philosophy of Science,” in Barnes, Jonathan, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 109139.Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell, Trust and Trustworthiness (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2002).Google Scholar
Hardwig, John, “Epistemic Dependence,” Journal of Philosophy 82, 7 (1985): 335349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, John, “The Role of Trust in Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy 88, 12 (1991): 693708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, Paul L., and Koenig, Melissa A., “The Basis of Epistemic Trust: Reliable Testimony or Reliable Sources?Episteme 4, 3 (2007): 264284.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John, Knowledge and Lotteries (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Heller, Mark, “The Simple Solution to the Generality Problem,” Noûs 29, 4 (1995): 501515.Google Scholar
Henderson, David, “Motivated Contextualism,” Philosophical Studies 142, 1 (2009): 119131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henderson, David, and Graham, Peter, “Epistemic Norms and the ‘Epistemic Game’ They Regulate: The Basic Structured Epistemic Costs and Benefits,” American Philosophical Quarterly 54, 4 (2017): 367382.Google Scholar
Henderson, David, and Horgan, Terence, “What’s the Point?” in Henderson, David and Greco, John, eds., Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), pp. 87114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hess, John E., Interviewing and Interrogation for Law Enforcement, 2nd edition (New Providence, NJ: Matthew Bender and Company, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hick, John, Evil and the God of Love (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1966).Google Scholar
Hinchman, Edward, “Telling as Inviting to Trust,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70, 3 (2005): 562587.Google Scholar
Holton, Richard, “Deciding to Trust, Coming to Believe,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72, 1 (1994): 6376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence, and Tienson, John, “Connectionism and the Commitments of Folk Psychology,” Philosophical Perspectives 9 (1995): 127152.Google Scholar
Horgan, Terence, and Teinson, John, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Daniel, The Evidential Argument from Evil (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Daniel, and Moser, Paul K., “Introduction: The Hiddenness of God,” in Howard-Snyder, Daniel and Moser, Paul K., eds., Divine Hiddenness: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), pp. 123.Google Scholar
Hume, David, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd edition, Selby-Bigge, L.A., ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).Google Scholar
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edition, Selby-Bigge, L.A., ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).Google Scholar
Hyde, Krista, “A Virtue-Theoretic Account of the Epistemic Effects of Marginalization,” (PhD diss., Saint Louis University, 2017).Google Scholar
Johnson, Scott P., Amso, Dima and Slemmer, Jonathan A., “Development of Object Concepts in Infancy: Evidence for Early Learning in an Eye-Tracking Paradigm,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 100, 18 (2003): 1056810573.Google Scholar
Jones, Karen, “Trust as an Affective Attitude,” Ethics 107, 1 (1996): 425.Google Scholar
Kallestrup, Jesper and Pritchard, Duncan, “Robust Virtue Epistemology and Epistemic Anti-IndividualismPacific Philosophical Quarterly 93, 1 (2012): 84103.Google Scholar
Kelly, Thomas, “The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement,” in Hawthorne, John and Gendler, Tamar, eds., Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 166196.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip, “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World,” in Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley, eds., Scientific Explanation (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1989), pp. 410505.Google Scholar
Kornblith, Hilary, Inductive Inference and Its Natural Ground: An Essay in Naturalistic Epistemology (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Kutz, Christopher, “Acting Together,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61, 1 (2000): 131.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, “Testimonial Knowledge and Transmission,” Philosophical Quarterly 49, 197 (1999): 471490.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, “Knowing from Testimony,” Philosophy Compass 1, 5 (2006): 432448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, “Why We Don’t Deserve Credit for Everything We Know,” Synthese 158, 3 (2007): 345361.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source of Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, “Knowledge and Credit,” Philosophical Studies 142, 1 (2009): 2742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, Peter, Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd edition (New York: Routledge, 2004).Google Scholar
List, Christian, and Pettit, Philip, Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Mackie, J.L., “Evil and Omnipotence,” Mind 64, 254 (1955): 200212.Google Scholar
McGinn, Marie, Sense and Certainty: A Dissolution of Scepticism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989).Google Scholar
McLeod, Carolyn, “Trust,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 edition), available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/trust.Google Scholar
McMyler, Benjamin, Testimony, Trust, and Authority (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Medina, José, The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and the Social Imagination (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Seumas, Social Action: A Teleological Account (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Moore, G.E., “Proof of an External World,” Proceeding of the British Academy 25 (1939): 273300. Reprinted in G.E. Moore, Philosophical Papers (New York: Macmillan, 1959).Google Scholar
Moore, G.E.A Defense of Common Sense,” Philosophical Papers (New York: Macmillan, 1959).Google Scholar
Moran, Richard, “Getting Told and Being Believed,” in Lackey, Jennifer and Sosa, Ernest, eds., The Epistemology of Testimony (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 272306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard, The Exchange of Words: Speech, Testimony, and Intersubjectivity (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018).Google Scholar
Moser, Paul K., The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008).Google Scholar
Moser, Paul K., The Evidence for God: Religious Knowledge Reexamined (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, Understanding Wittgenstein’s on Certainty (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, “The Animal in Epistemology: Wittgenstein’s Enactivist Solution to the Problem of Regress,” in Coliva, Annalisa and Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle, eds., Hinge Epistemology (Leiden: Brill, 2016), pp. 2447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, “Virtus Normativa: Rational Choice Perspectives,” Ethics 100, 4 (1990): 725755.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, “The Reality of Group Agents,” in Mantzavinos, Chrysostomos, ed., Philosophy of the Social Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 6791.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, God, Freedom, and Evil (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1974).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, “Reason and Belief in God,” in Plantinga, Alvin and Wolterstorff, Nicholas, eds., Faith and Rationality (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 1693.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan, Epistemic Luck (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan, “Knowledge and Understanding,” in Haddock, Adrian, Millar, Alan, and Pritchard, Duncan, The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan, Epistemic Angst: Radical Scepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016).Google Scholar
Quinn, Philip L., and Meeker, Kevin, eds., The Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Reibsamen, Jonathan, “Social Epistemic Dependence: Trust, Testimony, and Social Intellectual Virtue,” (PhD diss., Saint Louis University, 2015).Google Scholar
Reid, Thomas, Philosophical Works, Bracken, H.M., ed., 2 volumes (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1983).Google Scholar
Rezendes, Michael, Caroll, Matt, and Pfeiffer, Sacha, “Clergy Sex Abuse Crisis,” The Boston Globe (January 6, 2002), available at www.bostonglobe.com/metro/specials/clergy.Google Scholar
Riggs, Wayne, “Reliability and the Value of Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64, 1 (2002): 7996.Google Scholar
Riggs, Wayne, “Understanding ‘Virtue’ and the Virtue of Understanding,” in DePaul, M. and Zagzebski, L., eds. Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 203226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riggs, Wayne, “Why Epistemologists Are so Down on Their Luck,” Synthese 158, 3 (2007): 329344.Google Scholar
Riggs, Wayne, “Two Problems of Easy Credit,” Synthese 169, 1 (2009): 201216.Google Scholar
Ross, Angus, “Why Do We Believe What We Are Told?Ratio 69, 1 (1986): 6988.Google Scholar
Roth, Abraham Sesshu, “Shared Agency,” in Zalta, Edward N., ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2011), available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/shared-agency.Google Scholar
Rowe, William L., “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16, 4 (1979): 355–341.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard, “Induction and Natural Kinds,” Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 1, 2 (1997): 239254.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J.L., Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J.L., “The Hiddenness Problem and the Problem of Evil,” Faith and Philosophy 27, 1 (2010): 4560.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, J.L., “Divine Hiddenness and Human Philosophy,” in Green, Adam and Stump, Eleonore, eds., Hidden Divinity and Religious Belief: New Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 1332.Google Scholar
Schmid, Hans Bernhard, “Trying to Act Together: The Structure and Role of Trust in Joint Action,” in Kobow, B., Schmid, H.B, and Schmitz, M., eds., The Background of Institutional Reality (Dordrecht: Springer, 2013), pp. 3755.Google Scholar
Searle, John, “Collective Intentions and Actions,” in Cohen, Philip R., Morgan, Jerry, and Pollack, Martha, eds., Intentions in Communication (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 401415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simion, Mona, “No Epistemic Norm for Action,” American Philosophical Quarterly 55, 3 (2018): 231238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest, “How to Defeat Opposition to Moore,” Philosophical Perspectives 13 (1999): 141153.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest, Knowing Full Well (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest, Judgment and Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).Google Scholar
Spelke, E.S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., and Jacobson, K., “Origins of Knowledge,” Psychological Review 99, 4 (1992): 605632.Google Scholar
Sripada, Chandra, and Stich, Stephen, “A Framework for the Psychology of Norms,” in Carruthers, Peter, Laurence, Stephen, and Stich, Stephen P., eds., The Innate Mind, vol. 2: Culture and Cognition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 237256.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason, Knowledge and Practical Interests (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore, Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Tollefsen, Deborah, Groups as Agents (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2015).Google Scholar
van Cleve, James, “Reliability, Justification, and the Problem of Induction,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9, 1 (1984): 555567.Google Scholar
Welbourne, Michael, “The Transmission of Knowledge,” Philosophical Quarterly 29, 114 (1979): 19.Google Scholar
Welbourne, Michael, “The Community of Knowledge,” Philosophical Quarterly 31, 125 (1981): 302314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welbourne, Michael, The Community of Knowledge (Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
White, Roger, “You Just Believe that Because…,” Philosophical Perspectives 24 (2010): 573615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Deciding to Believe,” in Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 136151.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy, Knowledge and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, On Certainty, Anscombe, G.E.M. and von Wright, Go Ho, eds., Paul, Denis and Anscombe, G.E.M., transl. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1969).Google Scholar
Woodward, James, Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Wright, Stephan, “In Defence of Transmission,” Episteme 12, 1 (2015): 1328.Google Scholar
Wykstra, Stephen, “Toward a Sensible Evidentialism: On the Notion of ‘Needing Evidence’,” in Rowe, William and Wainwright, William, eds., Readings in the Philosophy of Religion, 2nd edition (San Diego, CA: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich: 1989), pp. 426437.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda, Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda, “What Is Knowledge?” in Greco, John and Sosa, Ernest, eds., The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999), pp. 92116.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda, “Recovering Understanding,” in Steup, Matthias, ed., Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 235251.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda, Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • John Greco, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: The Transmission of Knowledge
  • Online publication: 21 August 2020
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108560818.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • John Greco, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: The Transmission of Knowledge
  • Online publication: 21 August 2020
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108560818.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • John Greco, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: The Transmission of Knowledge
  • Online publication: 21 August 2020
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108560818.012
Available formats
×