Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-03T01:33:14.727Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Works Cited

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2019

Travis Dumsday
Affiliation:
Concordia University, Edmonton
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Works Cited

Ainsworth, Peter (2010) “What is Ontic Structural Realism?Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41, pp. 5057.Google Scholar
Alexander of Hales (1924) Summa Theologica, Part I (Quaracchi: Collegii s. Bonaventurae).Google Scholar
Alexander of Hales (1928) Summa Theologica, Part II (Quaracchi: Collegii s. Bonaventurae).Google Scholar
Allen, Keith (2011) “Revelation and the Nature of Colour”, Dialectica, 65, pp. 153176.Google Scholar
Allen, Keith (2015) “Colour Physicalism, Naive Realism, and the Argument from Structure”, Minds & Machines, 25, pp. 193212.Google Scholar
Aquinas (1920) Summa Theologica. Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Accessed online via www.newadvent.orgGoogle Scholar
Aquinas (1956) Summa Contra Gentiles: On the Truth of the Catholic Faith, Book 2: Creation, translated by James F. Anderson (New York, NY: Image Books)Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (1978) Nominalism and Realism: Universals and Scientific Realism, Volume 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (1980) “Identity Through Time”, in: Time and Cause: Essays in Honor of Richard Taylor, ed. van Inwagen, Peter (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 6778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David (1983) What is a Law of Nature? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (1989) Universals: An Opinionated Introduction (Boulder, CO: Westview Press).Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (1997) A World of States of Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (1999) “The Causal Theory of Properties: Properties According to Shoemaker, Ellis, and Others”, Philosophical Topics, 26, pp. 2537.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David (2005) “Four Disputes about Properties”, Synthese, 144, pp. 309320.Google Scholar
Arntzenius, Frank (2006) “Time Travel: Double Your Fun”, Philosophy Compass, 1, pp. 599616.Google Scholar
Ayers, Michael (1991) “Substance: Prolegomena to a Realist Theory of Identity”, Journal of Philosophy, 88, pp. 6990.Google Scholar
Baker, David (2005) “Spacetime Substantivalism and Einstein’s Cosmological Constant”, Philosophy of Science, 72, pp. 12991311.Google Scholar
Baker, David (2016) “Does String Theory Posit Extended Simples?Philosophers’ Imprint, 16, pp. 115.Google Scholar
Balashov, Yuri (2000) “Relativity and Persistence”, Philosophy of Science, 67 (supplement), pp. S549S562.Google Scholar
Balashov, Yuri (2002) “What is a Law of Nature? The Broken-Symmetry Story”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 40, pp. 459475.Google Scholar
Barker, Stephen (2013) “The Emperor’s New Metaphysics of Powers”, Mind, 122, pp. 605653.Google Scholar
Bartels, Andreas (2013) “Why Metrical Properties are not Powers”, Synthese, 190, pp. 20012013.Google Scholar
Bauer, William (2013) “Dispositional Essentialism and the Nature of Powerful Properties”, Disputatio, 5, pp. 119.Google Scholar
Beebee, Helen (2000) “The Non-Governing Conception of Laws of Nature”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 3, pp. 571595.Google Scholar
Beebee, Helen (2011) “Necessary Connections and the Problem of Induction”, Noûs, 45, pp. 504527.Google Scholar
Belot, Gordon (1999) “Rehabilitating Relationalism”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, pp. 3552.Google Scholar
Benovsky, Jiri (2009) “Presentism and Persistence”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 90, pp. 291309.Google Scholar
Bettoni, Efrem (1961) Duns Scotus: The Basic Principles of His Philosophy, translated by Bernardine Bonansea (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press).Google Scholar
Bigelow, John, Ellis, Brian, and Lierse, Caroline (1992) “The World as One of a Kind: Natural Necessity and the Laws of Nature”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, pp. 371388.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (2005) “The Ultimate Argument Against Armstrong’s Contingent Necessitation View of Laws”, Analysis, 65, pp. 147155.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (2006) “Potency and Modality”, Synthese, 149: 491508.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (2007) Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (2012) “Are Any Kinds Ontologically Fundamental?”, in: Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics, ed. Tahko, Tuomas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 94104.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander, Ellis, Brian, Mumford, Stephen, and Psillos, Stathis (2006) “Looking for Laws”, Metascience, 15, pp. 437469.Google Scholar
Black, Robert (2000) “Against Quidditism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, pp. 87104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobik, Joseph (1961) “St. Thomas on the Individuation of Bodily Substances”, in: Readings in the Philosophy of Nature, ed. Koren, Henry (Westminster, MD: The Newman Press), pp. 327340.Google Scholar
Bobik, Joseph (1965) Aquinas on Being and Essence: A Translation and Interpretation (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press).Google Scholar
Bobik, Joseph (1998) Aquinas on Matter and Form and the Elements: A Translation and Interpretation of the De Principiis Naturae and the De Mixtione Elementorum of St. Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press).Google Scholar
Borghini, Andrea, and Williams, Neil (2008) “A Dispositional Theory of Possibility”, dialectica, 62, pp. 2141.Google Scholar
Bostock, Simon (2003) “Are All Possible Laws Actual Laws?Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81, pp. 517533.Google Scholar
Bostock, Simon (2008) “A Defence of Pan-Dispositionalism”, Metaphysica, 9, pp. 139157.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Miller, Kristie (2006) “The Physics of Extended Simples”, Analysis, 66, pp. 222226.Google Scholar
Briceno, Sebastian, and Mumford, Stephen (2016) “Relations All the Way Down? Against Ontic Structural Realism”, in: The Metaphysics of Relations, eds. Marmodoro, Anna and Yates, David (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 198217.Google Scholar
Broackes, Justin (2006) “Substance”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106, pp. 131166.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1923) Scientific Thought (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1925) The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Brogaard, Berit (2000) “Presentist Four-Dimensionalism”, Monist, 83, pp. 341356.Google Scholar
Brower, Jeffrey (2014) Aquinas’s Ontology of the Material World: Change, Hylomorphism, and Material Objects (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler (2007) Foundations of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Byrne, Alex (1994) The Emergent Mind (Doctoral Dissertation, Princeton University).Google Scholar
Byrne, Alex, and Hilbert, David (2007) “Color Primitivism”, Erkenntnis, 66, pp. 73105.Google Scholar
Campbell, Keith (1990) Abstract Particulars (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1989) Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (2004) “No God, No Laws”, in: God and the Laws of Nature, eds. Moriggi, Stefano and Sindoni, Elio (Milan: Angelicum Mondo X), pp. 183190.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (2007) “What Makes a Capacity a Disposition?”, in: Dispositions and Causal Powers, eds. Kistler, Max and Gnassounou, Bruno (Aldershot: Ashgate), pp. 195205.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (2009) “Causal Laws, Policy Predictions, and the Need for Genuine Powers”, in: Dispositions and Causes, ed. Handfield, Toby (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 127157.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, Anjan (2003) “The Structuralist Conception of Objects”, Philosophy of Science, 70, pp. 867878.Google Scholar
Chakravartty, Anjan (2007) A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Chakravartty, Anjan (2012) “Ontological Priority: The Conceptual Basis of Non-eliminative, Ontic Structural Realism”, in: Structural Realism: Structure, Object, and Causality, eds. Landry, Elaine and Rickles, Dean (Dordrecht: Springer), pp. 187206.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David (2006) “Strong and Weak Emergence”, in: The Re-Emergence of Emergence, eds. Davies, Paul and Clayton, Philip (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Choi, Sungho (2005) “Do Categorical Ascriptions Entail Counterfactual Conditionals?Philosophical Quarterly, 55, pp. 495503.Google Scholar
Christensen, Jonas (2014) “Determinable Properties and Overdetermination of Causal Powers”, Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel, 42, pp. 695711.Google Scholar
Clarke, Randolph (2008) “Intrinsic Finks”, Philosophical Quarterly, 58, pp. 512518.Google Scholar
Clarke, William, and Norris, S. J. (2001) The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press).Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross (2016) “On Characterizing the Presentism/Eternalism and Actualism/Possibilism Debates”, Analytic Philosophy, 57, pp. 110140.Google Scholar
Coleman, Mary (2010) “Could there Be a Power World?American Philosophical Quarterly, 47, pp. 161170.Google Scholar
Connolly, Niall (2015) “Yes: Bare Particulars!Philosophical Studies, 172, pp. 13551370.Google Scholar
Corry, Richard (2009) “How is Scientific Analysis Possible?”, in: Dispositions and Causes, ed. Handfield, Toby (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 158188.Google Scholar
Cowling, Sam (2014) “Instantiation as Location”, Philosophical Studies, 167, pp. 667682.Google Scholar
Cowling, Sam (2017) Abstract Entities (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Creary, L. G. (1981) “Causal Explanation and the Reality of Natural Component Forces”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, pp. 148157.Google Scholar
Crisp, Thomas (2003) “Presentism”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, eds. Loux, Michael and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 211245.Google Scholar
Cross, Richard (1998) The Physics of Duns Scotus: The Scientific Context of a Theological Vision (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Cross, Troy (2005) “What is a Disposition?Synthese, 144, pp. 321341.Google Scholar
Daniels, Paul (2012) “Back to the Present: Defending Presentist Time Travel”, Disputatio, 4, pp. 469484.Google Scholar
Deasy, Daniel (2015) “The Moving Spotlight Theory”, Philosophical Studies, 172, pp. 20732089.Google Scholar
Demarest, Heather (2017) “Powerful Properties, Powerless Laws”, in: Causal Powers, ed. Jacobs, Jonathan (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 3854.Google Scholar
Denby, David (1999) “Determinable Nominalism”, Philosophical Studies, 102, pp. 297327.Google Scholar
Denby, David (2007) “A Note on Analysing Substancehood”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, pp. 473484.Google Scholar
Denkel, Arda (1996) Object and Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Denkel, Arda (1997) “On the Compresence of Tropes”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, pp. 599606.Google Scholar
Dieks, Dennis (2001) “Space–Time Relationism in Newtonian and Relativistic Physics”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 15, pp. 517.Google Scholar
Dieks, Dennis (2001a) “Space and Time in Particle and Field Physics”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32, pp. 217241.Google Scholar
Dipert, Randall (1997) “The Mathematical Structure of the World: The World as Graph”, Journal of Philosophy, 94, pp. 329358.Google Scholar
Donnelly, Maureen (2011) “Endurantist and Perdurantist Accounts of Persistence”, Philosophical Studies, 154, pp. 2751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorato, Mauro (2008) “Is Structural Spacetime Realism Relationism in Disguise? The Supererogatory Nature of the Substantivalism/Realism Debate”, in: The Ontology of Spacetime II, ed. Dieks, Dennis (Amsterdam: Elsevier), pp. 1737.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred (1977) “Laws of Nature”, Philosophy of Science, 44, pp. 248268.Google Scholar
Du Maurier, Daphne (1969) The House on the Strand (London: Victor Gollancz).Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2011) “Have the Laws of Nature Been Eliminated?”, in: Reading the Cosmos: Nature, Science and Wisdom, ed. Butera, Giuseppe (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press/American Maritain Association), pp. 111128.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2012) “An Argument for Hylomorphism or Theism (But Not Both)”, Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 86, pp. 245254.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2012a) “Dispositions, Primitive Activities, and Essentially Active Objects”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93, pp. 4364.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2013) “Laws of Nature Don’t Have Ceteris Paribus Clauses, They Are Ceteris Paribus Clauses”, Ratio, 26, pp. 134147.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2013a) “Using Natural-Kind Essentialism to Defend Dispositionalism”, Erkenntnis, 78, pp. 869880.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2014) “Nominalist Dispositionalism and a Cosmological Argument”, Philosophia Christi, 16, pp. 423432.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2015) “Atoms vs. Extended Simples: Towards a Dispositionalist Reconciliation”, Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel, 43, pp. 10231033.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2016) “Dispositionalism and Moral Nonnaturalism”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 50, pp. 97110.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2016a) “Lowe’s Unorthodox Dispositionalism”, Res Philosophica, 93, pp. 79101.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2016b) “Natural-Kind Essentialism, Substance Ontology, and the Unity Problem: Two Dispositionalist Solutions”, Dialectica, 70, pp. 609626.Google Scholar
Dumsday, Travis (2017) “MaxCon Extended Simples and the Dispositionalist Ontology of Laws”, Synthese, 194, pp. 16271641.Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford (1994) “Laws, Natures, and Contingent Necessities”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, pp. 649667.Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford (1996) “Realism and Determinable Properties”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56, pp. 149159.Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford (2004) Real Natures and Familiar Objects (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford (2007) “Realism and the Problem of Infimae Species”, American Philosophical Quarterly 44, pp. 111127.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2001) Scientific Essentialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2002) The Philosophy of Nature: A Guide to the New Essentialism (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press).Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2009) The Metaphysics of Scientific Realism (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press).Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian, and Lierse, Caroline (1994) “Dispositional Essentialism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, pp. 2745.Google Scholar
Esfeld, Michael (2009) “The Modal Nature of Structures in Ontic Structural Realism”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23, pp. 179194.Google Scholar
Esfeld, Michael (2016) “The Reality of Relations: The Case from Quantum Physics”, in: The Metaphysics of Relations, eds. Marmodoro, Anna and Yates, David (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 218234.Google Scholar
Esfeld, Michael, and Lam, Vincent (2008) “Moderate Structural Realism About Space-Time”, Synthese, 160, pp. 2746.Google Scholar
Esfeld, Michael, and Lam, Vincent (2011) “Ontic Structural Realism as a Metaphysics of Objects”, in: Scientific Structuralism, eds. Bokulich, Alisa and Bokulich, Peter (Dordrecht: Springer), pp. 143159.Google Scholar
Esfeld, Michael, and Sachse, Christian (2011) Conservative Reductionism (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Everett, Anthony (2009) “Intrinsic Finks, Masks, and Mimics”, Erkenntnis, 71, pp. 191203.Google Scholar
Evnine, Simon (2016) Making Objects and Events: A Hylomorphic Theory of Artifacts, Actions, and Organisms (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Fales, Evan (1982) “Generic Universals”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60, pp. 2939.Google Scholar
Fales, Evan (1990) Causation and Universals (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Fales, Evan (1993) “Are Causal Laws Contingent?”, in: Ontology, Causality, and Mind: Essays in Honour of D.M. Armstrong, eds. Bacon, John, Campbell, Keith, and Reinhardt, Lloyd (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 121151.Google Scholar
Feser, Edward (2014) Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (Heusenstamm: Editiones Scholasticae).Google Scholar
Feser, Edward (2015) Neo-Scholastic Essays (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press).Google Scholar
Fine, Kit (1994) “Essence and Modality”, Philosophical Perspectives, 8, pp. 116.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit (1999) “Things and their Parts”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, pp. 6174.Google Scholar
Fisk, Milton (1973) Nature and Necessity: An Essay in Physical Ontology (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press).Google Scholar
Floridi, Luciano (2011) The Philosophy of Information (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Forrest, Peter (2004) “Grit or Gunk: Implications of the Banach-Tarski Paradox”, Monist, 87, pp. 351370.Google Scholar
Foster, John (2004) The Divine Lawmaker: Lectures on Induction, Laws of Nature, and the Existence of God (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Franklin, James (1986) “Are Dispositions Reducible to Categorical Properties?Philosophical Quarterly, 36, pp. 6264.Google Scholar
Franklin, James (2015) “Uninstantiated Properties and Semi-Platonist Aristotelianism”, Review of Metaphysics, 69, pp. 2545.Google Scholar
French, Steven (2006) “Structure as a Weapon of the Realist”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106, pp. 167185.Google Scholar
French, Steven (2010) “The Interdependence of Structure, Objects, and Dependence”, Synthese, 175, pp. 89109.Google Scholar
French, Steven, and Ladyman, James (2011) “In Defence of Ontic Structural Realism”, in: Scientific Structuralism, eds. Bokulich, Alisa and Bokulich, Peter (Dordrecht: Springer), pp. 2542.Google Scholar
French, Steven, and Redhead, Michael (1988) “Quantum Physics and the Identity of Indiscernibles”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39, pp. 233246.Google Scholar
Frigg, Roman, and Votsis, Ioannis (2011) “Everything You Ever Wanted to Know About Structural Realism but Were Afraid to Ask”, European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1, pp. 227276.Google Scholar
Funkhouser, Eric (2006) “The Determinable-Determinate Relation”, Noûs, 40, pp. 548569.Google Scholar
Funkhouser, Eric (2014) The Logical Structure of Kinds (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Gert, Joshua (2008) “What Colors Could Not Be: An Argument for Color Primitivism”, Journal of Philosophy, 105, pp. 128155.Google Scholar
Gibermam, Daniel (2012) “Against Zero-Dimensional Material Objects (and Other Bare Particulars)”, Philosophical Studies, 160, pp. 305321.Google Scholar
Gibermam, Daniel (2014) “Tropes in Space”, Philosophical Studies, 167, pp. 453472.Google Scholar
Gibson, Ian, and Pooley, Oliver (2006) “Relativistic Persistence”, Philosophical Perspectives, 20, pp. 157198.Google Scholar
Gilmore, Cody, Costa, Damiano, and Calosi, Claudio (2016) “Relativity and Three Four-Dimensionalisms”, Philosophy Compass, 11, pp. 102120.Google Scholar
Goddu, G. C. (2003) “Time Travel and Changing the Past: (Or How to Kill Yourself and Live to Tell the Tale)”, Ratio, 16, pp. 1632.Google Scholar
Goyette, John (2002) “Substantial Form and the Recovery of an Aristotelian Natural Science”, Thomist, 66, pp. 519533.Google Scholar
Greaves, Hilary (2011) “In Search of (Spacetime) Structuralism”, Philosophical Perspectives, 25, pp. 189204.Google Scholar
Grey, William (1999) “Troubles With Time Travel”, Philosophy, 74, pp. 5570.Google Scholar
Groff, Ruth, and Greco, John (eds.) (2013) Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Hales, Steven, and Johnson, Timothy (2003) “Endurantism, Perdurantism, and Special Relativity”, Philosophical Quarterly, 53, pp. 524539.Google Scholar
Hall, Thomas (2014) “In Defense of the Compossibility of Presentism and Time Travel”, Logos & Episteme, 5, pp. 141159.Google Scholar
Handfield, Toby (2005) “Armstrong and the Modal Inversion of Dispositions”, Philosophical Quarterly, 55, pp. 452461.Google Scholar
Handfield, Toby (2005a) “Lange on essentialism, counterfactuals, and explanation”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83, pp. 8185.Google Scholar
Handfield, Toby (2008) “Unfinkable Dispositions”, Synthese, 160, pp. 297308.Google Scholar
Harré, Rom, and Madden, E. H. (1975) Causal Powers: A Theory of Natural Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Haslanger, Sally (2003) “Persistence Through Time”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, eds. Loux, Michael and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 315354.Google Scholar
Hawley, Katherine (2001) How Things Persist (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Hawley, Katherine, and Bird, Alexander (2011) “What Are Natural Kinds?Philosophical Perspectives 25, pp. 205221.Google Scholar
Heil, John (2003) From an Ontological Point of View (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Heil, John (2005) “Dispositions”, Synthese, 144, pp. 343356.Google Scholar
Heil, John (2012) The Universe As We Find It (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Heil, John (2017) “Real Modalities”, in: Causal Powers, ed. Jacobs, Jonathan (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 90104.Google Scholar
Heller, Mark (1990) The Ontology of Physical Objects: Four-Dimensional Hunks of Matter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)Google Scholar
Hoefer, Carl (1996) “The Metaphysics of Space–Time Substantivalism”, Journal of Philosophy, 93, pp. 527.Google Scholar
Hoefer, Carl (1998) “Absolute Versus Relational Space-Time: For Better or Worse, the Debate Goes On”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, pp. 451467.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua (2012) “Neo-Aristotelianism and Substance”, in: Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics, ed. Tahko, Tuomas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 140155.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary (2003) “Platonistic Theories of Universals”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, eds. Loux, Michael andZimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 4674.Google Scholar
Holden, Thomas (2004) The Architecture of Matter: Galileo to Kant (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Hudson, Hud (2014) The Fall and Hypertime (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Huggett, Nick (2006) “The Regularity Account of Relational Spacetime”, Mind, 115, pp. 4173.Google Scholar
Hughes, Christopher, and Adams, Robert (1992) “Miracles, Laws of Nature and Causation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 66, pp. 179224.Google Scholar
Humphreys, P. (1997) “How Properties Emerge”, Philosophy of Science, 64, pp. 117.Google Scholar
Humphreys, P. (1997a) “Emergence, Not Supervenience”, Philosophy of Science, 64 (supplement), pp. S337S345.Google Scholar
Huntelmann, Rafael, and Hattler, Johannes (eds.) (2014) New Scholasticism Meets Analytic Philosophy (Heusenstamm: Editiones Scholasticae).Google Scholar
Ingthorsson, R. D. (2013) “Properties: Qualities, Powers, or Both?Dialectica, 67, pp. 5580.Google Scholar
Isaacs, A. (ed.) (2000) Oxford Dictionary of Physics, 4th edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Jacobs, Jonathan (2010) “A Powers Theory of Modality: Or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Reject Possible Worlds”, Philosophical Studies, 151, pp. 227248.Google Scholar
Jacobs, Jonathan (2011) “Powerful Qualities, Not Pure Powers”, Monist, 94, pp. 81102.Google Scholar
Jaeger, Andrew (2014) “Back to the Primitive: From Substantial Capacities to Prime Matter”, American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 88, pp. 381395.Google Scholar
Jaeger, Lydia (1999) Croire et connaître: Einstein, Polanyi et les lois de la nature (Paris: Institut Biblique de Nogent).Google Scholar
Jantzen, Benjamin (2011) “No Two Entities Without Identity”, Synthese, 181, pp. 433450.Google Scholar
Jaworski, William (2016) Structure and the Metaphysics of Mind: How Hylomorphism Solves the Mind–Body Problem (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Johansson, Ingvar (2000) “Determinables as Universals”, Monist, 83, pp. 101121.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark (2006) “Hylomorphism”, Journal of Philosophy, 103, pp. 652698.Google Scholar
Kantorovich, Aharon (2003) “The Priority of Internal Symmetries in Particle Physics”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, pp. 651675.Google Scholar
Kantorovich, Aharon (2009) “Ontic Structuralism and the Symmetries of Particle Physics”, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 40, pp. 7384.Google Scholar
Katzav, Joel (2005) “On What Powers Cannot Do”, Dialectica, 59, pp. 331345.Google Scholar
Kedar, Yael, and Hon, Giora (2017) “‘Natures’ and ‘Laws’: The Making of the Concept of Law of Nature Robert Grosseteste (1168–1253) and Roger Bacon (1214/1220–1292)”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 61, pp. 2131.Google Scholar
Keinänen, Markku (2011) “Tropes – The Basic Constituents of Powerful Particulars?Dialectica, 65, pp. 419450.Google Scholar
Keller, Simon, and Nelson, Michael (2001) “Presentists Should Believe in Time Travel”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79, pp. 333345.Google Scholar
Khalidi, Muhammad Ali (2011) “The Pitfalls of Microphysical Realism”, Philosophy of Science, 78, pp. 11561164.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (2006) “Emergence: Core Ideas and Issues”, Synthese, 151, pp. 547559.Google Scholar
Kistler, Max (2012) “Powerful Properties and the Causal Basis of Dispositions”, in: Properties, Powers, and Structures: Issues in the Metaphysics of Realism, eds. Bird, Alexander, Ellis, Brian, and Sankey, Howard (New York, NY: Routledge), pp. 119137.Google Scholar
Koons, Robert, and Pickavance, Timothy (2015) Metaphysics: The Fundamentals (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell).Google Scholar
Koslicki, Kathrin (2008) The Structure of Objects (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kronen, John (1994) “The Substantial Unity of Material Substances According to John Poinsot”, Thomist 58, pp. 599615.Google Scholar
Kuhlmann, Meinard (2012) “Quantum Field Theory”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/quantum-field-theory/Google Scholar
Kutach, Douglas (2003) “Time Travel and Consistency Constraints”, Philosophy of Science, 70, pp. 10981113.Google Scholar
LaBossiere, Michael (1994) “Substances and Substrata”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, pp. 360370.Google Scholar
Ladyman, James (1998) “What is Structural Realism?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, pp. 409424.Google Scholar
Ladyman, James (2016) “Structural Realism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/structural-realism/Google Scholar
Ladyman, James (2016a) “The Foundations of Structuralism and the Metaphysics of Relations”, in: The Metaphysics of Relations, eds. Marmodoro, Anna and Yates, David (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 177197.Google Scholar
Ladyman, James, and Ross, Don (with David Spurrett and John Collier) (2007) Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lam, Vincent (2014) “Entities Without Intrinsic Physical Identity”, Erkenntnis, 79, pp. 11571171.Google Scholar
Lam, Vincent, and Wuthrich, Christian (2015) “No Categorial Support for Radical Ontic Structural Realism”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, pp. 605634.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2004) “A Note on Scientific Essentialism, Laws of Nature, and Counterfactual Conditionals”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, pp. 227241.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2006) “Farewell to Laws of Nature?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37, pp. 361369.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2009) “Why Do the Laws Explain Why?”, in: Dispositions and Causes, ed. Handfield, Toby (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 286321.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2009a) Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Latham, Noa (2011) “Are Fundamental Laws Necessary or Contingent?”, in: Carving Nature at its Joints: Natural Kinds in Metaphysics and Science, eds. Campbell, Joseph K., O’Rourke, Michael, and Slater, Matthew (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 97112.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1981) “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science, 48, pp. 1949.Google Scholar
Laudisa, Federico (2015) “Laws Are Not Descriptions”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29, pp. 251270.Google Scholar
Le Bihan, Baptiste (2016) “Super-Relationism: Combining Eliminativism About Objects and Relationism About Spacetime”, Philosophical Studies, 173, pp. 21512172.Google Scholar
Lehoux, Daryn (2006) “Laws of Nature and Natural Laws”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37, pp. 527549.Google Scholar
Legg, Cathy (1999) “Real Laws in Peirce’s ‘Pragmaticism’ (Or: How Scholastic Realism Met the Scientific Method)”, in: Causation and the Laws of Nature, ed. Sankey, Howard (Dordrecht: Kluwer), pp. 125142.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1976) “The Paradoxes of Time Travel”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 13, pp. 145152.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1983) “Survival and Identity”, in: Philosophical Papers Volume I (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Lewis, David (2009) “Ramseyan Humility”, in Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, eds. Braddon-Mitchell, David and Nola, Robert (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 203222.Google Scholar
Lewis, Peter (2006) “GRW: A Case Study in Quantum Ontology”, Philosophy Compass, 1, pp. 224244.Google Scholar
Loux, Michael (1974) “Kinds and the Dilemma of Individuation”, Review of Metaphysics, 27, pp. 773784.Google Scholar
Loux, Michael (1978) Substance and Attribute: A Study in Ontology (Dordrecht: Reidel).Google Scholar
Loux, Michael (2002) Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction, 2nd edition (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Loux, Michael (2006) “Aristotle’s Constituent Ontology”, in: Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume II, ed. Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 207250.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1994) “Primitive Substances”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, pp. 531552.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1995) “The Metaphysics of Abstract Objects”, Journal of Philosophy, 92, pp. 509524.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (1998) “Form Without Matter”, Ratio, 11, pp. 214234.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2000) “Locke, Martin, and Substance”, Philosophical Quarterly, 50, pp. 499514.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2001) “Dispositions and Laws”, Metaphysica, 2, pp. 523.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2005) “Vagueness and Endurance”, Analysis, 65, pp. 104112.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2006) The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2012) “A Neo-Aristotelian Substance Ontology: Neither Relational Nor Constituent”, in: Contemporary Aristotelian Metaphysics, ed. Tahko, Tuomas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 229248.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2013) “Neo-Aristotelian Metaphysics: A Brief Exposition and Defense”, in: Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, ed. Feser, Edward (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan), pp. 196205.Google Scholar
Macdonald, Cynthia (2005) Varieties of Things: Foundations of Contemporary Metaphysics (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter (2004) “Activities and Causation: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Mechanisms”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, pp. 2739.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1977) “Dispositions, Grounds and Causes”, Synthese, 34, pp. 361369.Google Scholar
Madden, James (2013) Mind, Matter, and Nature: A Thomistic Proposal for the Philosophy of Mind (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press).Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned (1998) “Simples”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, pp. 213226.Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned (2004) “Simples, Stuff, and Simple People”, Monist, 87, pp. 405428.Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned (2015) “The Right Stuff”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93, pp. 665687.Google Scholar
Marmodoro, Anna (2013) “Aristotelian Hylomorphism Without Reconditioning”, Philosophical Inquiry, 36, pp. 522.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (1980) “Substance Substantiated”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, pp. 310.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (1997) “On the Need for Properties: The Road to Pythagoreanism and Back”, Synthese, 112, pp. 193231.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B., and Heil, John (1999) “The Ontological Turn”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, pp. 3460.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Timothy (1993) “Buckets of Water and Waves of Space: Why Spacetime is Probably a Substance”, Philosophy of Science, 60, pp. 183203.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Timothy (2007) The Metaphysics Within Physics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
McCall, Storrs (1994) A Model of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kris (2007) “Extended Simples”, Philosophical Studies, 133, pp. 131141.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kris (2009) “Extended Simples and Qualitative Heterogeneity”, Philosophical Quarterly, 59, pp. 325331.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kris (2010) “A Return to the Analogy of Being”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, pp. 688717.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kris (2010a) “Being and Almost Nothingness”, Noûs, 44, pp. 628649.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kris (2013) “Degrees of Being”, Philosophers’ Imprint, 13, pp. 119.Google Scholar
McKenzie, Kerry (2014) “Priority and Particle Physics: Ontic Structural Realism as a Fundamentality Thesis”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, pp. 353380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merricks, Trenton (1995) “On the Incompatibility of Enduring and Perduring Entities”, Mind, 104, pp. 523531.Google Scholar
Miller, Elizabeth (2015) “Humean Scientific Explanation”, Philosophical Studies, 172, pp. 13111332.Google Scholar
Miller, Kristie (2009) “Ought a Four-Dimensionalist to Believe in Temporal Parts?Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39, pp. 619646.Google Scholar
Molnar, George (2003) Powers: A Study in Metaphysics, ed. Mumford, Stephen (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. (1998) “Theories of Individuation: A Reconsideration of Bare Particulars”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, pp. 251263.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. (2000) “Naturalism and the Ontological Status of Properties”, in: Naturalism: A Critical Analysis, eds. Craig, William Lane and Moreland, J. P. (New York, NY: Routledge), pp. 67109.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. (2001) Universals (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press).Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. (2013) “Exemplification and Constituent Realism: A Clarification and Defense”, Axiomathes, 23, pp. 247259.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P., and Pickavance, Timothy (2003) “Bare Particulars and Individuation: A Reply to Mertz”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81, pp. 113.Google Scholar
Morganti, Matteo (2004) “On the Preferability of Epistemic Structural Realism”, Synthese, 142, pp. 81107.Google Scholar
Morganti, Matteo (2011) “Is There a Compelling Argument for Ontic Structural Realism?Philosophy of Science, 78, pp. 11651176.Google Scholar
Morganti, Matteo (2011a) “Substrata and Properties: From Bare Particulars to Supersubstantivalism?Metaphysica, 12, pp. 183195.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen (1998) Dispositions (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen (2004) Laws in Nature (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen (2006) “The Ungrounded Argument”, Synthese, 149, pp. 471489.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen (2007) “Powers, Dispositions, Properties: Or a Causal Realist Manifesto”, in: Revitalizing Causality: Realism About Causality in Philosophy and Social Science, ed. Groff, Ruth (New York, NY: Routledge), pp. 139151.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen (2009) “Powers and Persistence”, in: Unity and Time in Metaphysics, eds. Honnefelder, Ludger, Runggaldier, Edmund, and Schlick, Benedikt (Berlin: De Gruyter), pp. 223236.Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen, and Anjum, Rani Lill (2011) Getting Causes from Powers (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Mumford, Stephen, Anjum, Rani Lill, and Lie, Svein Anders Noer (2013) “Dispositions and Ethics”, in: Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism, eds. Groff, Ruth and Greco, John (New York, NY: Routledge), pp. 231247.Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin (2012) “Infinite Decomposability and the Mind-Body Problem”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 49, pp. 357367.Google Scholar
Nerlich, Graham (2003) “Space-Time Substantivalism”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, eds. Loux, Michael and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 281314.Google Scholar
Newman, Andrew (2013) “On the Constitution of Solid Objects Out of Atoms”, Monist, 96, pp. 149171.Google Scholar
Ney, Alyssa (2010) “Are There Fundamental Intrinsic Properties?”, in: New Waves in Metaphysics, ed. Hazlett, Allan (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan), pp. 219239.Google Scholar
Novak, Lukas, Novotny, Daniel, Sousedik, Prokop, and Svoboda, David (eds.) (2013) Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic (Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag).Google Scholar
Novotny, Daniel, and Novak, Lukas (eds.) (2014) Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Oakes, M. Gregory (2004) “Perdurance and Causal Realism”, Erkenntnis, 60, pp. 205227.Google Scholar
O’Conaill, Donnchadh (2014) “Ontic Structural Realism and Concrete Objects”, Philosophical Quarterly, 64, pp. 284300.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Timothy (1994) “Emergent Properties”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 31, pp. 91104.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Timothy (2006) “Emergent Properties”, in: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward, N. Zalta (ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2006/entries/properties-emergent/Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (1996) “Coincidence Under a Sortal”, Philosophical Review, 105, pp. 145171.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (2002) “Hylomorphism and Individuation”, in: Mind, Metaphysics, and Value in the Thomistic and Analytic Traditions, ed. Haldane, John (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press), pp. 125142.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (2004) “Temporal Parts and the Possibility of Change”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, pp. 686708.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (2005) “Hylemorphic Dualism”, Social Philosophy & Policy, pp. 7099.Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (2007) Real Essentialism (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Oderberg, David (2011) “Essence and Properties”, Erkenntnis, 75, pp. 85111.Google Scholar
Okasha, Samir (2002) Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
O’Leary-Hawthorne, John, and Cover, Jan (1998) “A World of Universals”, Philosophical Studies, 91, pp. 205219.Google Scholar
Paoletti, Michele (2016) “Who’s Afraid of Non-Existent Manifestations?”, in: Metaphysics and Scientific Realism: Essays in Honour of David Malet Armstrong, ed. Calemi, Francesco (Berlin: De Gruyter), pp. 193206.Google Scholar
Paoletti, Michele (2016a) “How Powers Emerge from Relations”, Axiomathes, 26, pp. 187204.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh (2000) “Must a Four Dimensionalist Believe in Temporal Parts?Monist, 83, pp. 399418.Google Scholar
Pashby, Thomas (2013) “Do Quantum Objects Have Temporal Parts?Philosophy of Science, 80, pp. 11371147.Google Scholar
Pasnau, Robert (2011) Metaphysical Themes: 1274–1671 (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Paterson, Craig, and Pugh, Matthew (eds.) (2006) Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue (Aldershot: Ashgate).Google Scholar
Paul, Laurie (2002) “Logical Parts”, Noûs, 36, pp. 578596.Google Scholar
Pawl, Timothy (2017) “Nine Problems (And Even More Solutions) for Powers Accounts of Possibility”, in: Causal Powers, ed. Jacobs, Jonathan (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 105124.Google Scholar
Persson, Johannes (2010) “Activity-Based Accounts of Mechanism and the Threat of Polygenic Effects”, Erkenntnis, 72, pp. 135149.Google Scholar
Peterson, John (1996) “Law and Thomistic Exemplarism”, Thomist, 60, pp. 81108.Google Scholar
Pickavance, T. (2009) “In Defence of ‘Partially Clad’ Bare Particulars”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87, pp. 155158.Google Scholar
Pickavance, T. (2014) “Bare Particulars and Exemplification”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 51, pp. 95108.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (1999) Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (2006) “What Do Powers Do When They Are Not Manifested?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72, pp. 137156.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (2009) Knowing the Structure of Nature: Essays on Realism and Explanation (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan).Google Scholar
Poincaré, Henri (1905) Science and Hypothesis, reprint edition from 1952 (New York, NY: Dover).Google Scholar
Pooley, Oliver (2013) “Substantivalist and Relationalist Approaches to Spacetime”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics, ed. Batterman, Robert (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 522586.Google Scholar
Pruss, Alexander (2011) Actuality, Possibility, and Worlds (London: Continuum).Google Scholar
Pruss, Alexander (2013) “Aristotelian Forms and Laws of Nature”, Analiza i Egzystencja, 24, pp. 115132.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1966) The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1974) Roots of Reference (La Salle, IL: Open Court).Google Scholar
Rea, Michael (2003) “Four-Dimensionalism”, in: The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, eds. Loux, Michael and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 246280.Google Scholar
Reck, Erich, and Price, Michael (2000) “Structures and Structuralism in Contemporary Philosophy of Mathematics”, Synthese, 125, pp. 341383.Google Scholar
Robb, David (2005) “Qualitative Unity and the Bundle Theory”, Monist, 88, pp. 466492.Google Scholar
Ruby, Jane (1986) “The Origins of Scientific ‘Law’”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 47, pp. 341359.Google Scholar
Ruse, Michael (2001) Can a Darwinian Be a Christian? The Relationship Between Science and Religion (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1915/1951) “The Ultimate Constituents of Matter”, in: Mysticism and Logic (New Jersey: Barnes and Noble), pp. 94107.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan (2003) “Is There a Fundamental Level?Noûs, 37, pp. 498517.Google Scholar
Schneider, Susan (2007) “What is the Significance of the Intuition that Laws of Nature Govern?Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, pp. 307324.Google Scholar
Schnieder, Benjamin (2006) “A Certain Kind of Trinity: Dependence, Substance, Explanation”, Philosophical Studies, 129, pp. 393419.Google Scholar
Schrenk, Markus (2017) Metaphysics of Science: A Systematic and Historical Introduction (New York, NY: Routledge).Google Scholar
Schroer, Robert (2010) “Is There More Than One Categorical Property?Philosophical Quarterly, 60, pp. 831850.Google Scholar
Schumm, Bruce (2004) Deep Down Things: The Breathtaking Beauty of Particle Physics (Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press).Google Scholar
Scotus (1975) God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions, translated by Felix Alluntis and Allan Wolter (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Shiver, Anthony (2014) “Mereological Bundle Theory and the Identity of Indiscernibles”, Synthese, 191, pp. 901913.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney (1980) “Causality and Properties”, in: Time and Cause, ed. Inwagen, Peter van (Dordrecht: Reidel); reprinted in (1999) Metaphysics: An Anthology, eds. Kim, Jaegwon and Sosa, Ernest (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 253268.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney (1998) “Causal and metaphysical necessity”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, pp. 5977.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore (1993) “Van Inwagen and the Possibility of Gunk”, Analysis, 53, pp. 285289.Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore (2001) Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Sider, Theodore (2006) “Bare Particulars”, Philosophical Perspectives, 20, pp. 387397.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter (1994) “Particulars in Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories of Substance”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, pp. 553575.Google Scholar
Simons, Peter (2004) “Extended Simples: A Third Way Between Atoms and Gunk”, Monist, 87, pp. 371384.Google Scholar
Skow, Bradford (2007) “Are Shapes Intrinsic?Philosophical Studies, 133, pp. 111130.Google Scholar
Smart, Benjamin (2013) “Is the Humean Defeated by Induction?Philosophical Studies, 162, pp. 319332.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (2008) “The Tenseless Theory of Time”, in: Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, eds. Sider, Ted, Hawthorne, John, and Zimmerman, Dean (London: Blackwell), pp. 226238.Google Scholar
Stachel, John (2006) “Structure, Individuality, and Quantum Gravity”, in: Structural Foundations of Quantum Gravity, eds. Rickles, Dean, French, Steven, and Saatsi, Juha (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 5382.Google Scholar
Stanford, P. Kyle (2006) Exceeding Our Grasp: Science, History, and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Strawson, Galen (2008) “The Identity of the Categorical and the Dispositional”, Analysis, 68, pp. 271282.Google Scholar
Suárez, Francisco (1994) Metaphysical Disputations 17, 18, and 10, translated by Alfred Freddoso (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).Google Scholar
Suárez, Mauricio (2007) “Quantum Propensities”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38, pp. 418438.Google Scholar
Swoyer, Chris (1982) “The Nature of Natural Laws”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60, pp. 203223.Google Scholar
Tabaczek, Mariusz (2013) “The Metaphysics of Downward Causation: Rediscovering the Formal Cause”, Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science, 48, pp. 380404.Google Scholar
Taylor, Elanor (2015) “An Explication of Emergence”, Philosophical Studies, 172, pp. 653669.Google Scholar
Tegmark, Max (2007) “The Mathematical Universe”, Foundations of Physics, 38, pp. 101150.Google Scholar
Thompson, I. J. (1988) “Real Dispositions in the Physical World”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39, pp. 6779.Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick (2008) “Emergent Substance”, Philosophical Studies, 141, pp. 281297.Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick (2010) “On Substance”, American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 84, pp. 2548.Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick (2011) “Hylemorphic Animalism”, Philosophical Studies, 155, pp. 6581.Google Scholar
Toner, Patrick (2012) “On Aristotelianism and Structure as Parts”, Ratio, 31, pp. 148161.Google Scholar
Tooley, Michael (1977) “The Nature of Laws”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 74, pp. 667698.Google Scholar
Tugby, Matthew (2013) “Platonic Dispositionalism”, Mind, 122, pp. 4514800.Google Scholar
Tugby, Matthew (2016) “Universals, Laws, and Governance”, Philosophical Studies, 173, pp. 11471163.Google Scholar
Tweedale, Martin (1984) “Armstrong on Determinable and Substantival Universals”, in: D. M. Armstrong, ed. Bogdan, R. J. (Dordrecht: Reidel), pp. 171189.Google Scholar
Vallicella, William (2000) “Three Conceptions of States of Affairs”, Noûs, 34, pp. 237259.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, Bas (1980) The Scientific Image (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, Peter (1981) “The Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, pp. 123137.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, Peter (2011) “Relational Vs. Constituent Ontologies”, Philosophical Perspectives, 25, pp. 389405.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, Peter (2016) “In Defense of Transcendent Universals”, in: Metaphysics and Scientific Realism: Essays in Honour of David Malet Armstrong, ed. Calemi, Francesco (Berlin: De Gruyter), pp. 5170.Google Scholar
Vetter, Barbara (2013) “Multi-Track Dispositions”, Philosophical Quarterly, 63, pp. 330352.Google Scholar
Vetter, Barbara (2015) Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Wahlberg, Tobias Hannsson (2009) “4-D Objects and Disposition Ascriptions”, Philosophical Papers, 38, pp. 3572.Google Scholar
Wahlberg, Tobias Hannsson (2017) “Meso-Level Objects, Powers, and Simultaneous Causation”, Metaphysica, 18, pp. 107125.Google Scholar
Wasserman, Ryan (2016) “Theories of Persistence”, Philosophical Studies, 173, pp. 243250.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2016) “The Rise and Fall of Laws of Nature”, in: Rethinking Order: After the Laws of Nature, eds. Cartwright, Nancy and Ward, Keith (London: Bloomsbury), pp. 724.Google Scholar
Whittle, Ann (2009) “Causal Nominalism”, in: Dispositions and Causes, ed. Handfield, Toby (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 242285.Google Scholar
Whittle, Ann (2016) “A Defense of Substance Causation”, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2, pp. 120.Google Scholar
Wiggins, David (2001) Sameness and Substance Renewed (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Wildman, Nathan (2015) “Load Bare-ing Particulars”, Philosophical Studies, 172, pp. 14191434.Google Scholar
Williams, Neil (2011) “Putting Powers Back on Multi-Track”, Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel, 39, pp. 581595.Google Scholar
Williams, Neil (2017) “Powerful Perdurance: Linking Parts with Powers”, in: Causal Powers, ed. Jacobs, Jonathan (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 139164.Google Scholar
Williams, Neil (Forthcoming) The Powers Metaphysic (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica (2011) “Non-Reductive Realization and the Powers-Based Subset Strategy”, Monist, 94, pp. 121154.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica (2012) “Fundamental Determinables”, Philosophers’ Imprint, 12, pp. 117.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica (2013) “A Determinable-Based Account of Metaphysical Indeterminacy”, Inquiry, 56, pp. 359385.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica (2015) “Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong”, in: Metaphysics in Contemporary Physics: Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, Vol. 104, eds. Bigaj, Tomasz and Wuthrich, Christian (Amsterdam: Brill), pp. 345402.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas (1970) “Bergmann’s Constituent Ontology”, Noûs, 4, pp. 109134.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas (1991) “Divine Simplicity”, Philosophical Perspectives, 5, pp. 531552.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (1992) “Realism About Laws”, Erkenntnis, 36, pp. 181218.Google Scholar
Worrall, John (1989) “Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?Dialectica, 43, pp. 99124.Google Scholar
Young, J. Z. (1971) An Introduction to the Study of Man (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Yudell, Zanja (2011) “Structuralism and the New Way of Worlds: A Sellarsian Argument for Necessitarianism About Laws”, Philosophy of Science, 78, pp. 678695.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Dean (1996) “Indivisible Parts and Extended Objects: Some Philosophical Episodes from Topology’s Prehistory”, Monist, 79, pp. 148181.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Dean (1996a) “Could Extended Objects be Made Out of Simple Parts? An Argument for ‘Atomless Gunk’Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51, pp. 129.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Works Cited
  • Travis Dumsday, Concordia University, Edmonton
  • Book: Dispositionalism and the Metaphysics of Science
  • Online publication: 21 January 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647502.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Works Cited
  • Travis Dumsday, Concordia University, Edmonton
  • Book: Dispositionalism and the Metaphysics of Science
  • Online publication: 21 January 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647502.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Works Cited
  • Travis Dumsday, Concordia University, Edmonton
  • Book: Dispositionalism and the Metaphysics of Science
  • Online publication: 21 January 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647502.011
Available formats
×