Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T01:44:20.002Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 October 2016

Christian Barry
Affiliation:
Australian National University, Canberra
Gerhard Øverland
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Responding to Global Poverty
Harm, Responsibility, and Agency
, pp. 244 - 255
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, M., ‘Causation and Responsibility in Tort and Affirmative Action’, Texas Law Review, 79, no. 3 (2001), 643702.Google Scholar
Alesina, A. and Dollar, D., ‘Who Gives Foreign Aid to Whom and Why?’, Journal of Economic Growth, 5, no. 1 (2002), 3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvi, E. and Senbeta, A., ‘Does Foreign Aid Reduce Poverty?’, Journal of International Development, 24, no. 8 (2012), 955–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
American Law Institute, Restatement (Second) of Tort, §§431–3, 1965.Google Scholar
Anderson, E., ‘Democracy, Public Policy, and Lay Assessments of Scientific Testimony’, Episteme, 8, no. 2 (2011), 144–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G.E.M., ‘War and Murder’ in Stein, W. (ed.), Nuclear Weapons: A Catholic Response (London: Burns & Oates, 1961), 4362.Google Scholar
Armstrong, C., ‘Defending the Duty of Assistance?’, Social Theory and Practice, 35, no. 3 (2009), 461–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arndt, C., Jones, S. and Tarp, F., ‘Assessing Foreign Aid’s Long Run Contribution to Growth and Development’, World Development, 69 (2015), 618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. J., ‘Moral Limits on the Demands of Beneficence?’ in Chatterjee, D. K. (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 3358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banerjee, A., Amsden, A. H., Bates, R. H. et al., Making Aid Work (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Banerjee, A. and Duflo, E., Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty (New York: Public Affairs, 2011).Google Scholar
Barry, C., ‘Applying the Contribution Principle’, Metaphilosophy, 36, no. 1–2 (2005), 210–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, C., ‘Understanding and Evaluating the Contribution Principle’, in Pogge, T. and Follesdal, A. (eds.), Real World Justice (Berlin: Springer, 2005), 103–38.Google Scholar
Barry, C. and Lawford-Smith, H., ‘Duties to Assist and the Appeal to Cost’, unpublished manuscript (2015).Google Scholar
Barry, C. and Øverland, G., ‘Responding to Global Poverty: Review Essay of Peter Singer, The Life You Can Save’, Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 6, no. 2 (2009), 239–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, C. and Øverland, G., ‘Why Remittances Should not be Taxed’, New York University Journal of International Law and Politics, 42, no. 4 (2010), 1181–208.Google Scholar
Barry, C. and Øverland, G., ‘ The Feasible Alternatives Thesis: Kicking away the Livelihoods of the Global Poor’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 11, no. 1 (2012), 97119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, C. and Øverland, G., ‘Are Trade Subsidies and Tariffs Killing the Global Poor?Social Research, 79, no. 4 (2012), 865–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, C. and Øverland, G., ‘How Much for the Child?’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, no. 1 (2013), 189204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barry, C. and Reddy, S. G., International Trade and Labor Standards: A Proposal for Linkage (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008).Google Scholar
Barry, C. and Wiens, D., ‘Benefiting from Wrongdoing and Sustaining Wrongful Harm’, Journal of Moral Philosophy (2014), 123.Google Scholar
Basu, K., ‘The New Empirical Development Economics: Remarks on its Philosophical Foundations’, Economic and Political Weekly, 40, no. 40 (2005), 4336–9.Google Scholar
Bauer, P., Dissent on Development (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976).Google Scholar
Beitz, C.R, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979).Google Scholar
Beitz, C.R, Political Equality: An Essay in Democratic Theory (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Bennett, J., The Act Itself (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Bhagwati, J., A Stream of Windows: Unsettling Reflections on Trade, Immigration, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Bird, G., ‘The IMF and Developing Countries: A Review of the Evidence and Policy Options’, International Organization, 50, no. 3 (1996), 477511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackstone, W., Commentaries on the Laws of England (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1765–69).Google Scholar
Blake, M., ‘Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30, no. 3 (2001), 257–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobba, M. and Powell, A., ‘Aid and Growth: Politics Matters’, Working Paper No. 601 (Washington, DC: Inter-American Development Bank, 2007).Google Scholar
Bold, T., Kimenyi, M., Mwabu, G. et al., ‘Scaling Up What Works: Experimental Evidence on External Validity in Kenyan Education’, Working Paper No. 321 (Center for Global Development, 2013).Google Scholar
Boorse, C. and Sorenson, R., ‘Ducking Harm’, Journal of Philosophy, 85, no. 3 (1988), 115–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourguignon, F. and Sundberg, M., ‘Aid Effectiveness: Opening the Black Box’, American Economic Review, 97, no. 2 (2007), 316–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boxill, B., ‘A Lockean Argument for Black Reparations’, Journal of Ethics, 7, no. 1 (2003), 6391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, B., ‘Doing Away with Harm’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, no. 2 (2012), 390412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brock, G., Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Account (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J., Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2012).Google Scholar
Buchanan, A., ‘Social moral epistemology’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 19, no. 2 (2002), 126152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bunzl, M., ‘Causal Overdetermination’, Journal of Philosophy, 76, no. 3 (1979), 134–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butt, D., Rectifying International Injustice: Principles of Compensation and Restitution between Nations (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar
Caney, S., ‘Environmental Degradation, Reparations, and the Moral Significance of History’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 37, no. 3 (2006), 464–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N., ‘What Are Randomised Controlled Trials Good For?’, Philosophical Studies, 147, no. 1 (2010), 5970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. and Hardie, J., Evidence-Based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing It Better (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chand, R. P., Impact of Trade Liberalization and Related Reforms on India’s Agricultural Sector, Rural Food Security, Income and Poverty (Delhi: India Institute for Economic Growth, 2004).Google Scholar
Cohen, J., ‘Philosophy, Social Science, Global Poverty’, in Jaggar, A. (ed.), Thomas Pogge and his Critics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2010), 1845.Google Scholar
Cohen, J., The Probable and the Provable (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J., ‘Who Is Starving Whom?’, Theoria, 47, no. 2 (1981), 6581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collier, P. and Dollar, D., ‘Aid Allocation and Poverty Reduction’, European Economic Review, 46, no. 8 (2002), 1475–500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collier, P. and Hoeffler, A., ‘Greed and Grievance in Civil War’, Oxford Economic Papers, 56, no. 4 (2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M., Regan, H. M. and Ferson, S., ‘Is It a Crime to Belong to a Reference Class?’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, no. 2 (2001), 168–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cook, T. D. and Campbell, D. T., Quasi-Experimentation: Design & Analysis Issues for Field Settings (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1979).Google Scholar
Cornia, G. A., Jolly, G. A. R. and Stewart, F. (eds.), Adjustment with a Human Face: Protecting the Vulnerable and Promoting Growth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).Google Scholar
Cranor, C. F., Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and the Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullity, G., The Moral Demands of Affluence (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cullity, G., ‘Acts, Omissions, Emissions’, in Moss, J. (ed.), Climate Change and Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015).Google Scholar
De Waal, A., Famine Crimes: Politics and the Disaster Relief Industry in Africa (London: African Rights and the International African Institute, 1997).Google Scholar
Draper, K., ‘Rights and the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, no. 3 (2005), 253–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duff, R. A., Punishment, Communication, and Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Duflo, E., Glennerster, R. and Kremer, M., ‘Using Randomisation in Development Economics Research: A Toolkit’, Discussion Paper No.6059 (London, Centre for Economic Policy Research, 2007).Google Scholar
Easterly, W., The White Man’s Burden: Why the West’s Efforts to Aid the Rest Have Done So Much Ill and So Little Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Edwards, M. and Hulme, D., ‘NGO Performance and Accountability: Introduction and Overview’, in Edwards, M. and Fowler, A. (eds.), The Earthscan Reader on NGO Management (London: Earthscan, 2002).Google Scholar
Eide, A., ‘The Right to Adequate Food as a Human Right: Final Report’, UN Doc E/CN.4/Sub.2/1987/23, United Nations (1987).Google Scholar
Enoch, D., ‘Intending, Foreseeing, and the State’, Legal Theory, 13, no. 2 (2007), 6999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D., Spectre, L. and Fisher, T., ‘Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 40, no. 3 (2012), 197224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, C., Cosmopolitan War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fair, D., ‘Causation and the Flow of Energy’, Erkenntnis, 14, no. 3 (1979), 219–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J., ‘The Expressive Function of Punishment’, in Feinberg, J. (ed.), Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 95118.Google Scholar
Feldman, H. L., ‘Science and Uncertainty in Mass Exposure Litigation’, Texas Law Review, 74, no. 1 (1995), 148.Google Scholar
Ferzan, K. K., ‘Justifying Self-Defense’, Law and Philosophy, 24, no. 6 (2005), 711–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyzioglu, T., Swaroop, V. and Zhu, M., ‘A Panel Data Analysis of the Fungibility of Foreign Aid’, World Bank Economic Review, 12, no. 1 (1998), 2958.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P., ‘Killing and Letting Die’, in Norcross, A. and Steinbock, B. (eds.), Killing and Letting Die (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994), 280–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H., ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’, Journal of Philosophy, 66, no. 23 (1969), 829–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frowe, H., ‘Threats, Bystanders and Obstructors’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, no. 1 (2008), 365–72.Google Scholar
Frowe, H., ‘Killing John to Save Mary: A Defence of the Moral Distinction between Killing and Letting Die’, in Campbell, J. K., O’Rourke, M. and Silverstein, H. S. (eds.), Topics in Contemporary Philosophy: Action, Ethics and Responsibility (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010), 4766.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geistfeld, M., ‘Scientific Uncertainty and Causation in Tort Law’, Vanderbilt Law Review, 54, no. 3 (2001), 1011–38.Google Scholar
Glover, J., Causing Death and Saving Lives (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977).Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I., ‘Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility Approach’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 16, no. 2 (1999), 201–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A.I., ‘Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, no. 1 (2001), 85110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R. E., ‘Erring on the Side of Kindness in Social Welfare Policy’, Policy Sciences, 18, no. 2 (1985), 141–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R.E., Protecting the Vulnerable: A Reanalysis of Our Social Responsibilities (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Goodin, R.E., ‘Exploiting a Situation and Exploiting a Person’, in Reeve, A. (ed.), Modern Theories of Exploitation (London: Sage, 1987), 166200.Google Scholar
Goodin, R.E., ‘Disgorging the Fruits of Historical Wrongdoing’, American Political Science Review, 107, no. 3 (2013), 478–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R. E. and Barry, C., ‘Benefiting from the Wrongdoing of Others’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31, no. 4 (2014), 363–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, F. and Mittone, L., ‘Experiments in Economics: External Validity and the Robustness of Phenomena’, Journal of Economic Methodology, 12, no. 4 (2005), 495515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A. and Smithson, M., ‘Rationality and Indeterminate Probabilities’, Synthese, 187, no. 1 (2012), 3348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, N., ‘Non-Locality on the Cheap? A New Problem for Counterfactual Analyses of Causation’, Noûs, 36, no. 2 (2002), 276–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, N., ‘Two Concepts of Causation’, in Collins, J., Hall, N. and Paul, L.A. (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004), 225–76.Google Scholar
Hanser, M., ‘Killing, Letting Die and Preventing People from Being Saved’, Utilitas, 11, no. 3 (1999), 277–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanser, M., ‘The Metaphysics of Harm’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, no. 2 (2008), 421–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, E., ‘Harming as Causing Harm’, in Roberts, M. A. and Wasserman, D. (eds.), Harming Future Persons (Dordrecht: Springer, 2009), 137–54.Google Scholar
Hart, H.L.A. and Honoré, T., Causation in the Law, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hassoun, N., Globalization and Global Justice: Shrinking Distance, Expanding Obligations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haydar, B., ‘Extreme Poverty and Global Responsibility’, Metaphilosophy, 36, no. 1–2 (2005), 240–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haydar, B., ‘Special Responsibility and the Appeal to Cost’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 17, no. 2 (2009), 129–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haydar, B. and Øverland, G., ‘The Normative Implications of Benefiting from Injustice’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31, no. 4 (2014), 349–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Headey, D. D., ‘Geopolitics and the Effect of Foreign Aid on Economic Growth: 1970–2001’, Journal of International Development, 20, no. 2 (2007), 161–80.Google Scholar
Hockett, R., ‘Three (Potential) Pillars of Transnational Economic Justice: The Bretton Woods Institutions as Guarantors of Global Equal Treatment and Market Completion’, Metaphilosophy, 36, no. 1–2 (2005), 93127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horton, K., ‘The Epistemic Question: Potential Solutions’, in Horton, K. and Roche, C. (eds.), Ethical Questions and International NGOs: An Exchange Between Philosophers and NGOs (Dordrecht: Springer, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hosein, A. O., ‘Doing, Allowing, and the State’, Law and Philosophy, 33, no. 2 (2014), 235–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, F., ‘Doing and Allowing Harm’ in Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2011), plato.stanford.edu/entries/doing-allowing/.Google Scholar
Jayasinghe, K. and Wickramasinghe, D., ‘Can NGOs Deliver Accountability? Predictions, Realities and Difficulties: The Case of Sri Lanka’, in Bhargava, H. and Kumar, D. (eds.), NGOs: Roles and Accountability: An Introduction (India: ICFAI University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Jackson, F., ‘Which Effects?’ in Dancy, J. (ed.), Reading Parfit (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 4253.Google Scholar
Jamieson, D., Reason in a Dark Time (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Juselius, K., Møller, N. F. and Tarp, F., ‘The Long-Run Impact of Foreign Aid in 36 African Countries: Insights from Multivariate Time Series Analysis’, Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 76, no. 2 (2014), 153–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S., The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S., ‘Do I Make a Difference?’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39, no. 2 (2011), 105–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F., Creation and Abortion (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F., Morality, Mortality, vol. II: Rights, Duties, and Status (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Kanbur, R., ‘Aid, Conditionality, and Debt in Africa’, in Tarp, F. (ed.), Foreign Aid and Development: Lessons Learnt and Directions for the Future (New York: Routledge, 2000), 318–28.Google Scholar
Kapur, D. and McHale, J., ‘Economic Effects of Emigration on Sending Countries’, in Rosenblum, M. R. and Tichenor, D. J. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Politics of International Migration (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 131–52.Google Scholar
Kaya, O., Kaya, I. and Gunter, L., ‘Foreign Aid and the Quest for Poverty Reduction: Is Aid to Agriculture Effective?’, Journal of Agricultural Economics, 64, no. 3 (2013), 583–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraay, A. and Dollar, D., ‘Growth Is Good for the Poor’, Policy Research Working Paper No. 2587 (Washington, DC: World Bank, 2001).Google Scholar
Kristoff, N., ‘Farm Subsidies that Kill’, New York Times, 5 July 2002, www.nytimes.com/2002/07/05/opinion/farm-subsidies-that-kill.html.Google Scholar
Kuper, A., ‘More than Charity: Cosmopolitan Alternatives to the “Singer Solution”’, Ethics and International Affairs, 16, no. 1 (2002), 107–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurjanska, M. and Risse, M., ‘Fairness in Trade II: Export Subsidies and the Fair Trade Movement’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 7, no. 1 (2008), 2956.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lane, M., ‘When the Experts Are Uncertain: Scientific Knowledge and the Ethics of Democratic Judgment’, Episteme, 11, no. 1 (2014), 97118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawford-Smith, H., ‘The Motivation Question: Arguments from Justice and from Humanity’, British Journal of Political Science, 42, no. 3 (2012), 661–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawford-Smith, H., ‘Benefiting from Failures to Address Climate Change’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31, no. 4 (2014), 392404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazar, S., ‘The Responsibility Dilemma for Killing in War: A Review Essay’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38, no. 2 (2010), 180213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D., ‘Causation as Influence’, Journal of Philosophy, 97, no. 4 (2000), 182–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lichtenberg, J., Distant Strangers: Ethics, Psychology, and Global Poverty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014).Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K., ‘Global Injustice and Redistributive Wars’, Law, Ethics and Philosophy, 1 (2013), 6586.Google Scholar
Loriaux, S., ‘World Poverty and the Concept of Causal Responsibility’, South African Journal of Philosophy, 26, no. 3 (2007), 252–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maasland, A. and Van der Gaag, J., ‘World Bank Supported Adjustment Programs and Living Conditions’, in Corbo, V., Fischer, S. and Webb, S. (eds.), Adjustment Lending Revisited: Policies to Restore Growth (Washington, DC: World Bank, 1992), 4068.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L., Cement of the Universe, 2nd edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mattoo, A. and Subramanian, A., ‘The WTO and the Poorest Countries: The Stark Reality’, World Trade Review, 3, no. 3 (2004), 385407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. and Hollander, R. D. (eds.), Acceptable Evidence: Science and Values in Risk Management (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991).Google Scholar
McMahan, J., ‘Killing, Letting Die and Withdrawing Aid’, Ethics, 103, no. 2 (1993), 250–79.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McMahan, J., ‘Self-Defense and the Problem of the Innocent Attacker’, Ethics, 104, no. 2 (1994), 252–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J., ‘A Challenge to Common Sense Morality’, Ethics, 108, no. 2 (1998), 394418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J., ‘The Ethics of Killing in War’, Ethics, 114, no. 4 (2004), 693733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J., Killing in War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J., ‘The Basis of More Liability to Defensive Killing’, Philosophical Issues, 15, no. 1 (2009), 386405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, C., ‘Wrongful Beneficence: Exploitation and Third World Sweatshops’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 35, no. 3 (2004), 319–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D., ‘Distributing Responsibilities’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, no. 4 (2001), 453–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D., National Responsibility and Global Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D., ‘Taking up the Slack? Responsibility and Justice in Situations of Partial Compliance’, in Knight, C. and Stemplowska, Z. (eds.), Responsibility and Distributive Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 230–45.Google Scholar
Miller, R. W., ‘Moral Closeness and World Community’, in Chatterjee, D. K. (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 101–22.Google Scholar
Miller, R.W., ‘Beneficence, Duty and Distance’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 32, no. 4 (2004), 357–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R.W., Globalizing Justice: The Ethics of Poverty and Power (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minoiu, C. and Reddy, S. G., ‘Development Aid and Economic Growth: A Positive Long-run Relation,’ Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance, 50, no. 1 (2010), 2739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, M., ‘For What Must We Pay? Causation and Counterfactual Baselines’, San Diego Law Review, 40, no. 4 (2003), 1181–271.Google Scholar
Murphy, L. B., ‘The Demands of Beneficence’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22, no. 4 (1993), 267–92.Google Scholar
Murphy, L.B., Moral Demands in Non-Ideal Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T., ‘The Problem of Global Justice’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, no. 2 (2005), 113–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nefsky, J., ‘Consequentialism and the Problem of Collective Harm: A Reply to Kagan’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39, no. 4 (2012), 364–95.Google Scholar
New York Times, ‘Harvesting Poverty; The Long Reach of King Cotton’, 5 August 2003, www.nytimes.com/2003/08/05/opinion/harvesting-poverty-the-long-reach-of-king-cotton.html.Google Scholar
Nolt, J., ‘How Harmful Are the Average American’s Greenhouse Gas Emissions?’, Ethics, Policy and Environment, 14, no. 1 (2011), 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norberg, J., ‘American and European Protectionism Is Killing Poor Countries and Their People’, Cato Institute (2005), www.cato.org/publications/commentary/american-european-protectionism-is-killing-poor-countries-their-people.Google Scholar
Nunn, N. and Qian, N., ‘U.S. Food Aid and Civil Conflict’, American Economic Review, 104, no. 6 (2014), 1630–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Otsuka, M., ‘Killing the Innocent in Self-Defense’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23, no. 1 (1994), 7494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Øverland, G., ‘Contractual Killing’, Ethics, 115 (2005), 692720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Øverland, G., ‘The Right to Do Wrong’, Law and Philosophy, 26, no. 4 (2007), 377404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Øverland, G., ‘Forced Assistance’, Law and Philosophy, 28, no. 2 (2009), 203–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Øverland, G., ‘Global Poverty and an Extraordinary Humanitarian Intervention’, in Brooks, T. (ed.), New Waves in Global Justice (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014), 2947.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Øverland, G., ‘Moral Obstacles: An Alternative to the Doctrine of Double Effect’, Ethics, 124, no. 3 (2014), 481506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oxfam, Rigged Rules and Double Standards: Trade, Globalisation and the Fight against Poverty (Oxford: Oxfam Publishing, 2002).Google Scholar
Parfit, D., Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).Google Scholar
Patten, A., ‘Should We Stop Thinking about Poverty in Terms of Helping the Poor?’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19, no. 1 (2005), 1927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Three Problems with Contractarian-Consequentialist Ways of Assessing Social Institutions’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 12, no. 2 (1995), 241–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘The Categorical Imperative’, in Guyer, P. (ed.), Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998), 189213.Google Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Eradicating Systemic Poverty: Brief for a Global Resources Dividend’, Journal of Human Development, 2, no. 1 (2001), 5977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘“Assisting” the Global Poor’, in Chatterjee, D. K. (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 260–88.Google Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Historical Wrongs: The Two Other Domains’, in Meyer, L. H. (ed.), Justice in Time: Responding to Historical Injustice (Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 2004), 117–34.Google Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Real World Justice’, Journal of Ethics, 9 (2005), 2953.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Severe Poverty as a Violation of Negative Duties’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19, no. 1 (2005), 5583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W. (ed.), Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., ‘Severe Poverty as a Human Rights Violation’, in Pogge, T. (ed.), Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 1153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, T.W., World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms, 2nd edn. (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2008).Google Scholar
Pogge, T.W., Politics as Usual: What Lies Behind the Pro-Poor Rhetoric (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Quinn, W. S., ‘Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing’, Philosophical Review, 98, no. 3 (1989), 287312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quong, J., ‘Killing in Self-Defense’, Ethics, 119, no. 3 (2009), 507–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rajan, R., ‘Aid and Growth: The Policy Challenge’, Finance and Development, 42, no. 4 (2005).Google Scholar
Rajan, R. and Subramanian, A., ‘What Undermines Aid’s Impact on Growth?’, NBER Working Paper No. 11657 (Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research, 2005), 54.Google Scholar
Rajan, R. and Subramanian, A., ‘Does Aid Affect Governance?’, American Economic Review, 97, no. 2 (2007), 322–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ratha, D., ‘Dollars Without Borders: Can the Global Flow of Remittances Survive the Crisis?’, Foreign Affairs, 16 October (2009), www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/65448/dilip-ratha/dollars-without-borders.Google Scholar
Reddy, S. G., ‘Randomise This! On Poor Economics’, Review of Agrarian Studies, 2, no. 2 (2012), 6073.Google Scholar
Reitberger, M., ‘Poverty, Negative Duties and the Global Institutional Order’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 7, no. 4 (2008), 379402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rickless, S. C., ‘The Moral Status of Enabling Harm’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92, no. 1 (2011), 6686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riddell, R.C., Does Foreign Aid Really Work? (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Ripstein, A., Equality, Responsibility, and the Law (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Ripstein, A., ‘Philosophy of Tort Law’, in Coleman, J. L. and Shapiro, S. J. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 656–86.Google Scholar
Risse, M., ‘Do We Owe the Global Poor Assistance or Rectification?’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19, no. 1 (2005), 918.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Risse, M., ‘How Does the Global Order Harm the Poor?’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, no. 4 (2005), 347–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, D., War and Self-Defense (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodrik, D., ‘The New Development Economics: We Shall Experiment, but How Shall We Learn?’, Faculty Research Working Paper Series, RWP08-055 (Cambridge, MA: John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, 2008).Google Scholar
Sachs, J. D., The End of Poverty: Economic Possibilities of Our Time (New York: Penguin, 2005).Google Scholar
Satz, D., ‘What Do We Owe the Global Poor?’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19, no. 1 (2005), 4754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M., What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Schaffer, J., ‘Overdetermining Causes’, Philosophical Studies, 114, no. 1–2 (2003), 2345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiff, M. and Valdes, A., The Plundering of Agriculture in Developing Countries (Washington, DC: World Bank, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidtz, D., ‘Islands in a Sea of Obligation: Limits of the Duty to Rescue’, Law and Philosophy, 19, no. 6 (2000), 683705.Google Scholar
Schroeder, S. A., ‘Imperfect Duties, Group Obligations, and Beneficence’, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 11, no. 5 (2013), 557–84.Google Scholar
Shiffrin, S., ‘Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm’, Legal Theory, 5, no. 2 (1999), 117–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shue, H., Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Shue, H., ‘Subsistence Emissions and Luxury Emissions’, Law and Policy, 15, no. 1 (1993), 3959.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P., ‘Famine, Affluence and Morality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1, no. 3 (1972), 229–43.Google Scholar
Singer, P., ‘Utilitarianism and Vegetarianism’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9, no. 4 (1980), 325–37.Google Scholar
Singer, P., Practical Ethics, 2nd edn. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Singer, P., ‘Poverty, Facts, and Political Philosophies: Response to “More Than Charity”’, Ethics and International Affairs, 16, no.1 (2002), 121–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P., One World: The Ethics of Globalisation (Melbourne: Text Publishing, 2004).Google Scholar
Singer, P., The Life You Can Save: Acting Now to End World Poverty (Melbourne: Text Publishing, 2009).Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W., ‘“It’s Not My Fault”: Global Warming and Individual Moral Obligations’, in Sinnott-Armstrong, W. and Howarth, R. B. (eds.), Perspectives on Climate Change: Science, Economics, Politics, Ethics (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2005), 293315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smillie, I., The Alms Bazaar: Altruism Under Fire: Non-Profit Organizations and International Development (London: International Development Research Centre, 1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. and Jackson, F., ‘Absolutist Moral Theories and Uncertainty’, Journal of Philosophy, 103, no. 6 (2006), 267–83.Google Scholar
Stapleton, J., ‘Choosing What We Mean by “Causation” in Law’, Missouri Law Review, 73, no. 2 (2008), 433–80.Google Scholar
Statman, D., ‘On the Success Condition for Legitimate Self-Defense’, Ethics, 118, no. 4 (2008), 659–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Summers, L. and Pritchett, L. H., ‘The Structural-Adjustment Debate’, American Economic Review, 83, no. 2 (1993), 383–9.Google Scholar
Tadros, V., Criminal Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tadros, V., The Ends of Harm (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Terry, F., Condemned to Repeat? The Paradox of Humanitarian Action (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J., ‘Self-Defense’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 20, no. 4 (1991), 283310.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J., ‘Critical Study: Jonathan Bennett, The Act Itself’, Noûs, 30, no. 4 (1996), 545–57.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J., ‘More on the Metaphysics of Harm’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, no. 2 (2011), 436–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomlin, P., ‘Extending the Golden Thread? Criminalisation and the Presumption of Innocence’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 21, no. 1 (2013), 4466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuck, R., Free Riding (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, P., Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
United Nations Children’s Fund, The State of the World’s Children 2014 in Numbers: Every Child Counts: Revealing Disparities, Advancing Children’s Rights (2014).Google Scholar
United Nations Children’s Fund, Levels and Trends in Child Mortality: Report 2014 (2014).Google Scholar
Valdman, M., ‘Exploitation and Injustice’, Social Theory and Practice, 34, no. 4 (2008), 551–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valdman, M., ‘A Theory of Wrongful Exploitation’, Philosopher’s Imprint, 9, no. 6 (2009), 114.Google Scholar
Valentini, L., ‘Just War and Global Distributive Justice’, in Held, D. and Maffettone, P. (eds.), International Political Theory Today (Cambridge: Polity Press, forthcoming).Google Scholar
Vihvelin, K. and Tomkow, T., ‘The Dif’, Journal of Philosophy, 102, no. 4 (2005), 183205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J., ‘Superseding Historical Injustice’, Ethics, 103, no. 1 (1992), 428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J., ‘Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss’ in Owen, D. (ed.), Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 387408.Google Scholar
Watkins, K. and Fowler, P., Rigged Rules and Double Standards: Trade, Globalisation and the Fight against Poverty (Oxford: Oxfam Publishing, 2002).Google Scholar
Wenar, L., ‘What We Owe to Distant Others’, Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 2, no. 3 (2003), 283304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenar, L., ‘Accountability in International Development Aid’, Ethics and International Affairs, 19, no. 1 (2006), 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenar, L., ‘Realistic Reform of International Trade in Resources’, in Jaggar, A. M. (ed.), Thomas Pogge and His Critics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2010), 123–50.Google Scholar
Wenar, L., ‘Poverty Is No Pond: Challenges for the Affluent’, in Illingworth, P., Pogge, T. and Wenar, L. (eds.), Giving Well: The Ethics of Philanthropy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 104–32.Google Scholar
Wenar, L., Blood Oil (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).Google Scholar
Wertheimer, A., Exploitation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woollard, F., ‘Doing and Allowing, Threats and Sequences’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89, no. 2 (2008), 261–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woollard, F., ‘The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing I: Analysis of the Doing/Allowing Distinction’, Philosophy Compass, 7, no. 7 (2012), 448–58.Google Scholar
Woollard, F., ‘The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing II: The Moral Relevance of the Doing/Allowing Distinction’, Philosophy Compass, 7, no. 7 (2012), 459–69.Google Scholar
World Bank, Global Economic Prospects 2006: Economic Implications of Remittances and Migration (2006), ch. 5.Google Scholar
World Bank, World Development Indicators: Population Dynamics (2015), http://wdi.worldbank.org/table/2.1.Google Scholar
World Health Organisation, The World Health Report 2004: Changing History (2004).Google Scholar
Wright, R., ‘Causation in Tort Law’, California Law Review, 73, no. 6 (1985), 17881813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, R., ‘Standards of Care in Negligence Law’, in Owen, D. (ed.), Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 249–75.Google Scholar
Ypi, L., Goodin, R.E. and Barry, C., ‘Associative Duties, Global Justice, and the Colonies’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37, no. 2 (2009), 103–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zohar, N., ‘Collective War and Individualistic Ethics: Against the Conscription of “Self-Defense”’, Political Theory, 21, no. 4 (1993), 606–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zwolinski, M., ‘Sweatshops, Choice, and Exploitation’, Business Ethics Quarterly, 17, no. 4 (2007), 689727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Christian Barry, Australian National University, Canberra, Gerhard Øverland, Universitetet i Oslo
  • Book: Responding to Global Poverty
  • Online publication: 13 October 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139381758.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Christian Barry, Australian National University, Canberra, Gerhard Øverland, Universitetet i Oslo
  • Book: Responding to Global Poverty
  • Online publication: 13 October 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139381758.013
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Christian Barry, Australian National University, Canberra, Gerhard Øverland, Universitetet i Oslo
  • Book: Responding to Global Poverty
  • Online publication: 13 October 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139381758.013
Available formats
×