Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T09:19:34.428Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 July 2017

Andreas Losch
Affiliation:
Universität Bern, Switzerland
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Behe, M. (2007). The Edge of Evolution: The Search for the Limits of Darwinism, New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Bernard, C. (1878). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux végétaux, Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Cho, M. K., Magnus, D., Caplan, A. L., McGee, D. & The Ethics of Genomics Group (1999). Ethical considerations in synthesizing a minimal genome. Science, 286, 2087–90.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1996). River Out of Eden, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Delaporte, F. (1994 ). A Vital Rationalist: Selected Writings from Georges Canguilhem, New York: Zone.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. & O'Malley, M. A. (2007). Metagenomics and biological ontology. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci., 38, 834–46.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Editorial (2007) Meanings of ‘life’. Nature, 447, 1031–2.Google Scholar
Gibson, D. G. et al. (2010). Creation of a bacterial cell controlled by a chemically synthesized genome. Science, 329, 52–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gould, S. J. & Lewontin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc. R. Soc. London ser. B, 205, 581–98.Google Scholar
Jacob, F. (1973, 1993). Logic of Life: A Theory of Heredity, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Judson, H. F. (1979, 1996). The Eighth Day of Creation: Makers of the Revolution in Biology, Cold Spring Harbor: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.Google Scholar
Kahane, E. (1962). La vie n'existe pas, Paris: Editions rationalistes.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1790, 2002). The Critique of Judgment, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Lederberg, J. (1960). Exobiology: approach to life beyond the Earth. Science, 132, 393400.Google Scholar
Luria, S. E. & Delbrück, M. (1943). Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics, 28, 491511.Google Scholar
Maupertuis, P. L. M. de (1745, 1980). Vénus physique suivie de La lettre sur le progrès des sciences, Paris: Aubier Montaigne.Google Scholar
Monod, J. (1971). Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology, New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Morange, M. (2006). Ciliates as models…of what? J. Biosci., 31, 2730.Google Scholar
Morange, M. (2008). Life Explained, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Morange, M. (2015). Monod and the spirit of molecular biology. C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris Biol., 338, 380–4.Google Scholar
Normandin, S. & Wolfe, C. T. (2013). Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightment Life Science, 1800–2010, New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Oparin, A. I. (1938). The Origin of Life, New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Oyama, S. (2009). Compromising Positions: The Minding of Matter. In Barberousse, A., Morange, M. & Pradeu, T., eds., Mapping the Future of Biology: Evolving Concepts and Theories, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 2745.Google Scholar
Pichot, A. (1991). Histoire de la notion de vie, Paris: Gallimard, coll. Tel.Google Scholar
Porcar, M. & Pereto, J. (2014). Synthetic Biology: From iGEM to the Artificial Cell, Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Raoult, D. & Forterre, P. (2008). Redefining viruses: lessons from mimivirus. Nature Res. Microbiol., 6, 315–9.Google Scholar
Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is Life?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Taquet, P. (2006). Georges Cuvier: naissance d'un génie, Paris: Odile Jacob.Google Scholar
Varela, F., Maturana, H. & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. Biosystems, 5, 187–96.Google Scholar

References

Aristotle (2016). De anima, trans. Shields, C, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bedau, M. A. (2010). An Aristotelian account of minimal chemical life. Astrobiology, 10, 1011–21.Google Scholar
Bedau, M. A. & Cleland, C. E., eds. (2010). The Nature of Life. Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boden, M. A (1999). Is metabolism necessary? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(2), 231–48.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In Wilson, R. A, ed., Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 141–85.Google Scholar
Brun, G. (2015). Explication as a method of conceptual re-engineering. Erkenntnis. DOI: 10.1007/s10670–015–9791–5.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1962). Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd edn, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1963). Replies and systematic expositions. In Schilpp, P. A, ed., The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Chicago, Il: Open Court, pp. 8591013.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. & Chyba, C. (2002). Defining ‘life’. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 32(4), 387–93.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. & Chyba, C. (2007). Does ‘life’ have a definition?. In Woodruff, T., Sullivan, I. and Baross, J., eds., Planets and life: The emerging science of astrobiology, reprint in: Bedau, M. A and Cleland, C. E, eds., The Nature of Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, pp. 326–39.Google Scholar
Cleland, C. (2012). Life without definition. Synthese, 185, 125–44.Google Scholar
Diéguez, A. (2013). Life as a homeostatic property cluster. Biological Theory, 7, 180–6.Google Scholar
Fetzer, J. H., Shatz, D. and Schlesinger, G. N., eds. (1991). Definitions and Definability: Philosophical Perspectives, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality: The second Philosophical Perspectives lecture. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 116.Google Scholar
Gánti, T. (2003). The Principles of Life, ed. by Griesemer, J and Szathmary, E, reprint in: Bedau, M. A and Cleland, C. E, eds., The Nature of Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, pp. 102–12.Google Scholar
Gayon, J. (2010). Defining life: Synthesis and conclusions. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 40, 231–44.Google Scholar
Gupta, A. (2015). Definitions, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Zalta, Edward N, ed., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/definitions/.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739, 1978). Treatise of Human Nature, Selby-Bigge, L. A, ed., 2nd edn, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, G. F. (1994). Foreword. In Deamer, D. W and Fleischaker, G. R, eds., Origins of Life: The Central Concepts, Boston, MA: Jones & Bartlett, xixii.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1790, 2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Guyer, P and Matthews, E, Cambridge : Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1982). Genes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33, 337–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (1996). Life, “artificial life,” and scientific explanation, Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 225–44, reprint in Bedau, M. A and Cleland, C. E, eds., The Nature of Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, pp. 236–48.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals, Oxford : Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1690, 1894). An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding, Oxford : Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2012), Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life…and why you should do as well. Synthese, 185(1), 145–64.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. A. et al. (1929). Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung, Sozialismus und Logischer Empirismus, reprint in Hegselmann, R., ed., Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1979, 81101.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60, 2043, reprint in: From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953, 2046.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennock, R. T. (2012). Negotiating boundaries in the definition of life: Wittgensteinian and Darwinian insights on resolving conceptual border conflicts. Synthese, 185(1), 520.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In Putnam, H., Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 215–71.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. (1950). Definition, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J. & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34, 323–46.Google Scholar
Sagan, C. (1970). Life. In Encyclopædia Britannica, reprint in: Bedau, M. A and Cleland, C. E, eds., The Nature of Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010, pp. 303–6.Google Scholar
Sagan, C. (1973). The Cosmic Connection: An Extraterrestrial Perspective, reprint in: Sagan, C., Carl Sagan's Cosmic Connection: An Extraterrestrial Perspective, produced by Agel, J, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Sagan, D. (2016). Life, In Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 2016. Web. 14 May. 2016, http://www.britannica.com/topic/life.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (2012). The dialectic of life. Synthese, 185, 103–24.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (1994). The Moral Problem, Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2003). Learning from Functionalism, prospects for strong artificial life. In: Langton, C. G, Taylor, C., Farmer, J. Doyne, and Rasmussen, S., eds., Artificial Life II, pp. 749765, reprint in: Bedau, M. A and Cleland, C. E, eds., The Nature of Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2010, pp. 225–35.Google Scholar
Sorensen, R. (2016). Vagueness, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), Zalta, Edward N, ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/vagueness/.Google Scholar
Toepfer, G. (2005). Der Begriff des Lebens. In Krohs, U. and Toepfer, G., eds., Philosophie der Biologie. Eine Einführung, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 157–74.Google Scholar
Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 58, 207–33.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations, trans. Anscombe, G. E. M, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar

References

Aguirre, A. (2007). Making predictions in a multiverse: conundrums, dangers, coincidences. In Carr, B., ed., Universe or Multiverse? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 367–86.Google Scholar
Albrecht, A. & Sorbo, L. (2004). Can the universe afford inflation? Physical Review D, 70(6), 063528.Google Scholar
Barrow, J. & Tipler, F. (1986). The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Behe, M. (1996). Darwin's Black Box. The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution, New York, NY: Free Press.Google Scholar
Bernal, J. D. (1965). Discussion of Peter T. Mora. The Folly of Probability. In Fox, S. W, ed., The Origins of Prebiological Systems and of Their Molecular Matrices, New York, London: Academic Press, pp. 52–6.Google Scholar
Boltzmann, L. (1897). Zu Hrn. Zermelos Abhandlung „Über die mechanische Erklärung irreversibler Vorgänge“. Annalen der Physik, 60, 392–8.Google Scholar
Bostrom, N. (2002). Anthropic Bias. Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bradley, W. L. (2004). Information, entropy, and the origin of life. In Dembski, W. M. and Ruse, M., eds., Debating Design, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 331–51.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1962). Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd edn, Chicago, Il: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carr, B., ed. (2007). Universe or Multiverse?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Carter, B. (1974). Large Number Coincidences and the Anthropic Principle in Cosmology, reprint in Leslie, J., ed., Physical Cosmology and Philosophy, New York, London: Prentice Hall, 1990, pp. 125–33.Google Scholar
Conway Morris, S. (2003). Life's Solution. Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Copernicus, N. (1543). On the Revolutions of Heavenly Spheres, trans. Wallis, C. G, Amherst: Prometheus, 1995.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1986). The Blind Watchmaker, London: Longman.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion, London: Bantam.Google Scholar
de Duve, C. (1991). Blueprint for a Cell, Burlington (N.C.): Neil Patterson Publishers.Google Scholar
de Simone, A., Guth, A. H., Linde, A. et al. (2010). Boltzmann brains and the scale-factor cutoff measure of the multiverse. Physical Review D, 82(6), 063520.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. (1972). Darwinian evolution and the problem of extraterrestrial life. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 15(2), 157–76.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (1986). A Primer on Determinism, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Eigen, M. (1992). Steps towards Life. A Perspective on Evolution, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, G. F. R. (2011). Does the multiverse really exist? Scientific American, 305, 3843.Google Scholar
Feinberg, G. & Shapiro, R. (1980). Life Beyond Earth. The Intelligent Earthling's Guide to Life in the Universe, New York, NY: William Morrow.Google Scholar
Fry, I. (2000). The Emergence of Life. A Historical and Scientific Overview, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, M. (1986). WAP, SAP, PAP & FAP. New York Review of Books, 33 (8th May), 22–5.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1985). Mind and Supermind, reprint in Leslie, J., ed., Physical Cosmology and Philosophy, New York, London: Prentice Hall, 1990, pp. 181–8.Google Scholar
Greene, B. (2011). The Hidden Reality. Parallel Universes and the Deep Laws of the Cosmos, New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1987). The Inverse Gambler's Fallacy: The argument from design. The anthropic principle applied to Wheeler universes. Mind, 96(383), 331–40.Google Scholar
Hanson, R. (1998). Must Early Life Be Easy? The Rhythm of Major Evolutionary Transitions, (unpublished manuscript), http://mason.gmu.edu/~rhanson/hardstep.pdf.Google Scholar
Hart, M. H. (1982). Atmospheric Evolution, the Drake Equation, and DNA: Sparse Life in an Infinite Universe, reprint in Leslie, J., ed., Physical Cosmology and Philosophy, New York, London: Prentice Hall, 1990, pp. 256–66.Google Scholar
Hawking, S. W. & Ellis, G. F. R. (1973). The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hawking, S. W. & Israel, W. (1979). An introductory survey. In Hawking, S. W and Israel, W., eds., General Relativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Hoyle, F. & Wickramasinghe, C. (1981). Evolution from Space, London: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1779). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Irwin, L. N. & Schulze-Makuch, D. (2011). Cosmic Biology, New York, NY: Springer.Google Scholar
Jones, M. H. & Lambourne, R. J., eds. (2003). An Introduction to Galaxies and Cosmology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koonin, E. V. (2007). The cosmological model of eternal inflation and the transition from chance to biological evolution in the history of life. Biology Direct, 2(15).Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1980). Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Landsman, K. (2016). The fine tuning argument. Exploring the improbability of our existence. In Landsman, K and Wolde, E. van, eds., The Challenge of Chance. A Multidisciplinary Approach from Science and the Humanities, Heidelberg: Springer, 111–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leslie, J. (1988). No Inverse Gambler's Fallacy in Cosmology. Mind, 97 (386), 269–72.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. (1989). Universes, London, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. (1996). The End of the World, London, New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Leslie, J. (2001). Infinite Minds. A Philosophical Cosmology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, Penelope (2006). How Things Might Have Been. Individuals, Kinds, and Essential Properties, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Manson, N. A. (2003). Introduction. In Manson, N., ed., God and Design, London: Routledge, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Manson, N. A. & Thrush, M. (2003). Fine-tuning, multiple universes, and the “This Universe” objection. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 84, 6783.Google Scholar
Mash, R. (1993). Big numbers and induction in the case for extraterrestrial intelligence. Philosophy of Science, 60(2), 204–22.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1994). Does it pay to acquire high intelligence? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 37(3), 337–8.Google Scholar
Monod, J. (1971). Chance and Necessity. An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology, New York, NY: Vintage.Google Scholar
Narveson, J. (2003). God by design? In: Manson, N. A, ed., God and Design, London: Routledge, 88104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, D. (2006). Is our Universe Likely to Decay in 20 Billion Years? Web: http://arxiv.org/pdf/hep-th/0610079v2.pdf.Google Scholar
Paley, W. (1802). Natural Theology or Evidence of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity, Collected from the Appearances of Nature, reprint Eddy, M. D and Knight, D. eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.Google Scholar
Pascal, B. (1670). Pensées, trans. Trotter, W. F, New York, NY: E. P. Dutton, 1958.Google Scholar
Raup, D. M. (1985). ETI without intelligence. In Regis, E, ed., Extraterrestrials. Science and Alien Intelligence, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3142.Google Scholar
Rees, M. (1999). Just Six Numbers, London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson.Google Scholar
Sagan, C. (1995). The abundance of life bearing planets. Bioastronomy News, 7(4), 14.Google Scholar
Salisbury, F. B. (1969). Natural selection and the complexity of the gene. Nature, 224, 342–3.Google Scholar
Schopf, W., ed. (1992). Major Events in the History of Life, Boston, MA: Jones & Bartlett.Google Scholar
Shklovskii, I. S. & Sagan, C. (1966). Intelligent Life in the Universe, San Francisco, CA: Holden Day.Google Scholar
Smeenk, C. (2014). Predictability crisis in early universe cosmology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 46, 122–33.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution. The Logic Behind the Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Steinhardt, P. (2014). Big Bang blunder bursts the multiverse bubble. Nature, 510, 9.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (2003). The argument to God from fine-tuning reassessed. In Manson, N. A, ed., God and Design, London: Routledge, pp. 105–23.Google Scholar
Tegmark, M. (2014). Our Mathematical Universe, New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Tipler, F. J. (1985). Extraterrestrial intelligent beings do not exist. In Regis, Jr. E., ed., Extraterrestrials, Science and Alien Intelligence, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133–50.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (2015). Metaphysics, 4th edn, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Venn, J. (1888). The Logic of Chance, 3rd edn, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Vilenkin, A. (1996). Quantum cosmology and the constants of nature. In Sato, K., Suginohara, T. & Sugiyama, N., eds., The Cosmological Constant and the Evolution of the Universe, Tokyo: Universal Academy Press, pp. 161–8.Google Scholar
Vilenkin, A. (2006). Many Worlds in One. The Search for Other Universes, New York, NY: Hill and Wang.Google Scholar
Ward, P. & Brownlee, D. (2003). The Life and Death of Planet Earth, New York, NY: Henry Holt.Google Scholar
Webb, S. (2002). Where is Everybody? 50 Solutions to the Fermi Paradox and the Problem of Extraterrestrial Life, New York, NY: Copernicus.Google Scholar
Weidemann, C. (2010). Zufall, Gott oder Multiversum? Die Feinabstimmung der Naturkonstanten und die Erklärungsbedürftigkeit des Lebens in der modernen Kosmologie. In Nissing, H.-G., ed., Natur. Ein philosophischer Grundbegriff. Darmstadt: WBG, 181–96.Google Scholar
Weidemann, C. (2014a). Paralleluniversen, Gott und unser Platz im Kosmos. Das Feinabstimmungsproblem. Zur Debatte 2/2014, 35–6.Google Scholar
Weidemann, C. (2014b). Christian soteriology and extraterrestrial intelligence. Journal of the British Interplanetary Society, 67, 418–25.Google Scholar
Weidemann, C. (2016). Did Jesus die for Klingons too? In Levinson, P. & Waltemathe, M., eds., Touching the Face of the Cosmos: On the Intersection of Space Travel and Religion, New York, NY: Fordham University Press, pp. 119–29.Google Scholar
White, R. (2003). Fine-tuning and multiple universes. Nous, 34 (2000), 260–76, reprint (with a new postscript) in Manson, N. A., ed., God and Design, London: Routledge, pp. 229–50.Google Scholar
White, R. (2007). Does the origins of life research rest on a mistake? Nous, 41, 453–77.Google Scholar

References

Abe, Y. & Matsui, T. (1985). The formation of an impact-generated H2O atmosphere and its implications for the early thermal history of the Earth. Journal of Geophysical Research, 90, C545–60.Google Scholar
Arendt, H. (1963, 2007). The conquest of space and the stature of Man. New Atlantis, Fall issue, 4355 (http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/the-conquest-of-space-and-the-stature-of-man, last accessed August 15, 2015).Google Scholar
Barrow, J. D. & Tipler, F. J. (1986). The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baum, S. D. (2010). Is humanity doomed? Insights from astrobiology. Sustainability, 2, 591603.Google Scholar
Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life's tape. The Journal of Philosophy, 103, 336–62.Google Scholar
Benner, S. (2009). Life, the Universe…and the Scientific Method, Gainesville, FL: The FfAME Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. O. & Shostak, S. (2011). Life in the Universe, 3rd edn, San Francisco, CA: Benjamin Cummings.Google Scholar
Bromham, L. (2016). Testing hypotheses in macroevolution. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 55, 4759.Google Scholar
Bunzl, M. (2004). Counterfactual history: a user's guide. American Historical Review, 109, 845–58.Google Scholar
Chela-Flores, J. (2003): Testing evolutionary convergence on Europa. International Journal of Astrobiology, 2, 307–12.Google Scholar
Chopra, A. & Lineweaver, C. H. (2016). The case for a Gaian Bottleneck: the biology of habitability. Astrobiology, 16, 722.Google Scholar
Chyba, C. F. & Hand, K. (2005). Astrobiology: the study of the living universe. Annual Review of Astronomy and Astrophysics, 43, 3174.Google Scholar
Ćirković, M. M. (2005). ‘Permanence' – an adaptationist solution to Fermi's Paradox?. Journal of the British Interplanetary Society, 58, 6270.Google Scholar
Ćirković, M. M. (2012). The Astrobiological Landscape: Philosophical Foundations of the Study of Cosmic Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Conway Morris, S. (2003a). Life's Solution: Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Conway Morris, S. (2003b). The navigation of biological hyperspace. International Journal of Astrobiology, 2, 149–52.Google Scholar
Conway Morris, S. (2011). Predicting what extra-terrestrials will be like: and preparing for the worst. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 369, 555–71.Google Scholar
Darling, D. (2001). Life Everywhere: The Maverick Science of Astrobiology, New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, London: Murray.Google Scholar
Davies, C. W. (2003). Does life's rapid appearance imply a Martian origin? Astrobiology, 3, 673–9.Google Scholar
Des Marais, D. J. & Walter, M. R. (1999). Astrobiology: exploring the origins, evolution, and distribution of life in the Universe. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 30, 397420.Google Scholar
Des Marais, D. J. et al. (2008). The NASA Astrobiology Roadmap. Astrobiology, 8, 715–30.Google Scholar
Dick, S. J. (1996). The Biological Universe: The Twentieth-Century Extraterrestrial Life Debate and the Limits of Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Drake, M. J. (2005). Origin of water in the terrestrial planets. Meteoritics & Planetary Science, 40, 519–27.Google Scholar
Edwards, H. G. M. (2004). Raman spectroscopic protocol for the molecular recognition of key biomarkers in astrobiological exploration. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34, 311.Google Scholar
Erwin, D. H. (2015). Was the Ediacaran–Cambrian radiation a unique evolutionary event? Paleobiology, 41, 115.Google Scholar
Falcon, A. (2005). Aristotle and the Science of Nature: Unity without Uniformity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Farrer, J. (2010). Smart dust: Sci-fi applications enabled by synthetic fiber and textiles technology. Textile, 8, 342–7.Google Scholar
Ferguson, N. (1999). Virtual History: Alternatives and Counterfactuals, New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Fergusson, J., Oliver, C. & Walter, M. R. (2012). Astrobiology outreach and the nature of science: the role of creativity. Astrobiology, 12, 1143–53.Google Scholar
Frayn, M. (2006). The Human Touch: Our Part in the Creation of a Universe, London: Faber and Faber.Google Scholar
Garber, S. J. (1999). Searching for good science: The cancellation of NASA's SETI program. JBIS, 52, 312.Google Scholar
Gale, J. (2009). Astrobiology of Earth: The Emergence, Evolution, and Future of Life on a Planet in Turmoil, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gest, H. (2006). The “Astrobiology” fantasy of NASA, unpublished manuscript (available at http://www.bio.indiana.edu/about/history/biographies/gest_pdfs/astrobiology.pdf, last accessed January 15, 2016).Google Scholar
Gest, H. (2011). On the origin, evolution, and demise of an oxymoron: ‘astrobiology’, unpublished manuscript (available at https://scholarworks.iu.edu/dspace/handle/2022/13376, last accessed January 15, 2016).Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1987). The Flamingo's Smile: Reflections in Natural History, New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History, New York, NY: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1996). Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin, New York, NY: Three Rivers Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Grinspoon, D. (2003). Lonely Planets: The Natural Philosophy of Alien Life, New York, NY: HarperCollins.Google Scholar
Hausheer, R. (2003). Enlightening the Enlightenment. In Mali, J. and Wokler, R., eds., Isaiah Berlin's Counter-Enlightenment, Philadelphia, PA: American Philosophical Society, pp. 3350.Google Scholar
Heffernan, W. C. (1978). The singularity of our inhabited world: William Whewell and A. R. Wallace in dissent. Journal of the History of Ideas, 39, 81100.Google Scholar
Horneck, G. & Rettberg, P., eds. (2007). Complete Course in Astrobiology, Weinheim: Wiley-VCH.Google Scholar
Horner, J. & Jones, B. W. (2008). Jupiter – friend or foe? I: The asteroids. International Journal of Astrobiology, 7, 251–61.Google Scholar
Horner, J. & Jones, B. W. (2009). Jupiter – friend or foe? II: The Centaurs. International Journal of Astrobiology, 8, 7580.Google Scholar
Kundera, M. (2007). The Curtain: An Essay in Seven Parts, London: Faber and Faber.Google Scholar
Lem, S. (1964, 1973). The Invincible, London: Sidgwick and Jackson.Google Scholar
Lem, S. (1974, 1977). Summa Technologiae, Belgrade: Nolit.Google Scholar
Lin, H. W., Gonzalez Abad, G. & Loeb, A. (2014). Detecting industrial pollution in the atmospheres of Earth-like exoplanets. The Astrophysical Journal Letters, 792, L7.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1993). The search for intelligence. Science, 259, 1522–3.Google Scholar
Midgley, M. (1985). Evolution as a Religion: Strange Hopes and Stranger Fears, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Okasha, S. (2006). The levels of selection debate: Philosophical Issues. Philosophy Compass, 1, 112.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2010). Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1974). Darwinism as a metaphysical rpsearch Programme. In Schilpp, P. A., ed., The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Vol. I, La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 133–43.Google Scholar
Raup, D. M. (1992). Nonconscious intelligence in the Universe. Acta Astronautica, 26, 257–61.Google Scholar
Rhodes, R. (1986). The Making of the Atomic Bomb, New York, NY: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Rinaldi, A. (2007). Space life holds its breath. Pressured by scepticism, budget cuts and the need to prove itself, astrobiology is coming to a crossroads. EMBO Reports, 8, 436–40.Google Scholar
Rosen, B. P., Ajees, A. A. & McDermott, T. R. (2011). Life and death with arsenic. BioEssays, 33, 350–7.Google Scholar
Rospars, J.-P. (2011). Terrestrial biological evolution and its implication for SETI. Acta Astronautica, 67, 1361–5.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1977). Karl Popper's philosophy of biology. Philosophy of Science, 44, 638–61.Google Scholar
Schellnhuber, H. J. (1999). ’Earth system’ analysis and the second Copernican revolution. Nature, 402, C1923.Google Scholar
Schroeder, K. (2002). Permanence, New York, NY: Tor Books.Google Scholar
Simpson, G. G. (1964). The nonprevalence of humanoids. Science, 143, 769–75.Google Scholar
Sleep, N. H., Zahnle, K. & Neuhoff, P. S. (2001). Initiation of clement surface conditions on the earliest Earth. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98, 3666–72.Google Scholar
Swirski, P. (2000). Between Literature and Science: Poe, Lem, and Explorations in Aesthetics, Cognitive Science, and Literary Knowledge, Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press.Google Scholar
Swirski, P., ed. (2006). The Art and Science of Stanislaw Lem, Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press.Google Scholar
Turner, D. D. (2011). Gould's replay revisited. Biology and Philosophy, 26, 6579.Google Scholar
Wallace, A. R. (1903). Man's Place in the Universe; A Study of the Results of Scientific Research in Relation to the Unity or Plurality of Worlds, London: Chapman & Hall.Google Scholar
Ward, P. D. & Brownlee, D. (2000). Rare Earth: Why Complex Life Is Uncommon in the Universe, New York, NY: Springer.Google Scholar
Wells, H. G. (1914). The World Set Free: A Story of Mankind, London: Macmillan & Co.Google Scholar

References

Baars, B. (2008). The Global Workspace Theory of Consciousness. In Velmans, M. and Schneider, S., eds., The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, Boston, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 236–47.Google Scholar
Bennett, J.O. & Shostak, S. (2011). Life in the Universe, San Francisco, CA: Pearson.Google Scholar
Bostrom, N. (2014). Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bostrom, N. & Ćirković, M. (2008). Global Catastrophic Risks, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bradbury, R., Ćirković, M. & Dvorsky, G. (2011). Dysonian approach to SETI: A fruitful middle ground? Journal of the British Interplanetary Society, 64, 156–65.Google Scholar
Brin, D. (2015). Shall We Shout into the Cosmos? Web: http://www.davidbrin.com/setisearch.html Accessed: July 1, 2016.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (1996). Absent qualia, fading qualia, dancing qualia. In: The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ćirković, M. & Bradbury, R. (2006). Galactic gradients, postbiological evolution and the apparent failure of SETI. New Astronomy, 11, 628–39.Google Scholar
Clarke, A. (1962). Profiles of the Future: An Inquiry into the Limits of the Possible, New York, NY: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Consolmagno, G. & Mueller, P. (2014) Would You Baptize an Extraterrestrial?:…and Other Questions from the Astronomers' In-box at the Vatican Observatory, New York, NY: Penguin Random House.Google Scholar
Davies, P. (2010). The Eerie Science: Renewing Our Search for Alien Intelligence, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Dick, S. (2013). Bringing culture to cosmos: the postbiological universe. In Dick, S. J., and Lupisella, M. eds., Cosmos and Culture: Cultural Evolution in a Cosmic Context, Washington, DC: NASA, Web: http://history.nasa.gov/SP-4802.pdf.Google Scholar
Falk, D. (2015). Is This Thing On?: The fierce debate over whether we should try to contact extraterrestrial life or wait for aliens to contact us. Slate. Web: http://www.slate.com/articles/technology/future_tense/2015/03/active_seti_should_we_reach_out_to_extraterrestrial_life_or_are_aliens_dangerous.html. Accessed: July 1, 2016.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1978). The Language of Thought, Boston, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hawkins, J. & Blakeslee, S. (2004). On Intelligence: How a New Understanding of the Brain will Lead to the Creation of Truly Intelligent Machine, NewYork, NY: Times Books.Google Scholar
Holley, P. (2015). Bill Gates on dangers of artificial intelligence: ‘I don't understand why some people are not concerned’. The Washington Post. Web: http://wpo.st/45n42 Accessed: July 1, 2016.Google Scholar
Kurzweil, R. (2005). The Singularity is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology, New York, NY: Viking.Google Scholar
Miller, R. (1956). “The magical number seven, plus or minus two: some limits on our capacity for processing information”. The Psychological Review, 63, 8197.Google Scholar
Müller, V. C. & Bostrom, N. (2016), “Future progress in artificial intelligence: A survey of expert opinion,” in Müller, Vincent C, ed., Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence, Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. (2004). Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and their Perceptual Basis, Boston, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. (2009). Science Fiction and Philosophy: From Time Travel to Superintelligence, New York, NY: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. (2011a). Mindscan: transcending and enhancing the brain. In Giordano, J., ed., Neuroscience and Neuroethics: Issues At the Intersection of Mind, Meanings and Morality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. (2011b). The Language of Thought: a New Philosophical Direction, Boston, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. (2014). The philosophy of ‘her.’ The New York Times, March 2.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. (2015). Alien minds. In Dick, S., ed., The Impact of Discovering Life beyond Earth, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schneider, S. & Mandik, P. (2016). “How philosophy of mind can shape the future,” Kind, Amy, ed., Philosophy of Mind in the Twentieth and Twenty-first Centuries, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Seung, S. (2012). Connectome: How the Brain's Wiring Makes Us Who We Are, Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Shostak, S. (2009). Confessions of an Alien Hunter, New York, NY: National Geographic.Google Scholar
Shostak, S. (2015). Should we keep a low profile in space? The New York Times. Web: http://nyti.ms/1yknLSqAccessed: July 1, 2016.Google Scholar
Wallach, W. & Allen, C. (2008). Moral Machines, Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
Yudkowsky, E. (2008). Artificial intelligence as a positive and negative factor in global risk. In Bostrom, N and Ćirković, M. M, eds., Global Catastrophic Risks, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 308–45.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Philosophy
  • Edited by Andreas Losch, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: What is Life? On Earth and Beyond
  • Online publication: 08 July 2017
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Philosophy
  • Edited by Andreas Losch, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: What is Life? On Earth and Beyond
  • Online publication: 08 July 2017
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Philosophy
  • Edited by Andreas Losch, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: What is Life? On Earth and Beyond
  • Online publication: 08 July 2017
Available formats
×