Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T11:57:07.235Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Historical considerations on brain and self

from Part I - The mind, brain, and education triad

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Fernando Vidal
Affiliation:
Max Plank Institute for the History of Science Berlin
Antonio M. Battro
Affiliation:
National Academy of Education, Argentina
Kurt W. Fischer
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Pierre J. Léna
Affiliation:
Université de Paris VII (Denis Diderot)
Get access

Summary

Overview

This chapter explores some historical developments concerning ideas about the connection between brain and self, and suggests that they constitute the background – and, indeed, the historical and intellectual conditions of possibility – for projects, such as the one that inspires this volume on the “educated brain,” aimed at integrating the neurosciences with (or into) traditional areas of the human sciences. Such integration can be conceived of in reductionistic terms (the area in question, e.g. education or psychoanalysis, is to be entirely reformed on the basis of neuroscientific knowledge, and to be made dependent on advancements in the neurosciences), or in more collaborative terms (the human sciences maintain their epistemic and methodological independence, but are to be enriched and partially modified by available neuroscientific information). If the neurosciences seem so crucial, it is ultimately because – beyond what is relevant for each area of application or cooperation – they show the extent to which the brain is a fundamental organ for the constitution of human personhood. The author suggests, however, that the significance which the neurosciences have gained is, at least in part, dependent on the belief that one's own brain is the only organ each of us needs in order to be himself or herself. Such a belief is obviously supported by neuroscientific findings, but did not originate in them; on the contrary, it precedes modern knowledge of the brain. This might sound counterintuitive, but if it is indeed the case, then history should help us understand the roots, as well as the implicit values and beliefs of contemporary enthusiasm about the consequences of the neurosciences for other disciplines.

The Editors

Type
Chapter
Information
The Educated Brain
Essays in Neuroeducation
, pp. 20 - 42
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andrieu, B. (2002). La nouvelle philosophie du corps (The New Philosophy of the Body). Ramonville: Éditions érès.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blank, R. H. (1999). Brain Policy: How the New Neuroscience Will Change Our Lives and Our Politics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Brazier, M. A. B. (1988). A History of Neurophysiology in the Nineteenth Century. New York: Raven Press.Google Scholar
Breidbach, O. (1997a). Die Materialisierung des Ichs. Zur Geschichte der Hirnforschung im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert (The Materialization of the Self. On the History of Brain Research in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Century). Frankfurt, Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Breidbach, O.(1997b). Einleitung: Neuronale Ästhetik – Skizze eines Programms (Introduction: Neuronal Esthetics. Sketch of A Program). In Breidbach, O. (ed.), Natur des Ästhetik – Ästhetik der Natur (Nature of Esthetics – Esthetics of Nature) (Vienna / New York, Springer).Google Scholar
Bruer, J. T. (1997). Education and the brain: a bridge too far. Educational Researcher, 26, 4–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruer, J. T.(1999). In search of … brain-based education. Phi Delta Kappan, www.pdkintl.org/kappan/kbru9905.htm.
Bynum, C. W. (1995). Why all the fuss about the body? A Medievalist's perspective. Critical Inquiry, 22, 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camerer, C., Loewenstein, G., and Prelec, D. (2003). Neuroeconomics: How neuroscience can inform economics, http://sds.hss.cmu.edu/faculty/Loewenstein/downloads/neurojep.pdf.
Changeux, J. P. (1983/1997). Neuronal Man. The Biology of Mind, trans Laurence Garey. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Changeux, J.-P. (2000). La révolution des neurosciences (The Neurosciences Revolution) [an interview]. Label France, n° 38, www.france.diplomatie.fr/label_france/FRANCE/DOSSIER/2000/09neuro.html.
Clarke, E. and Dewhurst, K. (1972). An Illustrated History of Brain Function. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, E. and O'Malley, C. D. (1968). The Human Brain and Spinal Cord. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, E. and Jacyna, L. S. (1987). Nineteenth-Century Origins of Neuroscientific Concepts. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Corsi, P. (ed.) (1990). La fabrique de la pensée. La découverte du cerveau de l'art de la mémoire aux neurosciences (The Fabric of Thought. The Discovery of the Brain from the Art of Memory to the Neurosciences). Milan, Electa.Google Scholar
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. The Scientific Search for the Soul. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
Dahl, R. (1960/1979). William and Mary. In Dahl, Roald, Tales of the Unexpected. Harmondsworth, Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Daston, L. and Vidal, F. (eds.) (2004). The Moral Authority of Nature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dumit, J. (1997). A digital image of the category of the person. PET scanning and objective self-fashioning. In Downey, G. L. and Dumit, J. (eds.), Cyborgs & Citadels. Anthropological Interventions in Emerging Sciences and Technologies. Santa Fe, New Mexico: School of American Research Press.Google Scholar
Dumit, J.(2003). Is It Me or My Brain? Depression and Neuroscientific Facts. Journal of Medical Humanities, 24(1/2), 35–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dumit, J.(2004). Picturing Personhood. Brain Scans and Biomedical Identity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Eickmeier, J. (1004). Make your brain feel younger. www.prevention.com/article/0,5778,s1-5-91-276-2889-1,00.html
Featherstone, M. (ed.) (2000). Body Modification. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Ferret, S. (1993). Le philosophe et son scalpel. Le problème de l'identité personnelle (The Philosopher and His Scalpel. The Problem of Personal Identity). Paris: Editions de Minuit.Google Scholar
Finger, S. (1994). Origins of Neuroscience. A History of Explorations into Brain Function. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Garland, B., (ed.) (2004). Neuroscience and the Law. Brain, Mind, and the Scales of Justice, New York: Dana Press.Google Scholar
Glimcher, P. (2003). Decisions, Uncertainty, and the Brain. The Science of Neuroeconomics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hagner, M. (1997). Homo cerebralis. Der Wandel vom Seelenorgan zum Gehirn (Homo Cerebralis. The Transformation of the Organ of the Soul into the Brain). Berlin: Berlin Verlag.Google Scholar
Hagner, M. and Borck, C. (2001). Mindful practices: on the neurosciences in the twentieth centuy. Science in Context, 14(4), 507–510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagner, M. (2004). Geniale Gehirne. Zur Geschichte der Elitenhirnforschung. Berlin: Wallstein.Google Scholar
Harvey, R. (1975). The Inward Wits. Psychological Theory in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. London: Warburg Institute.Google Scholar
Jaroff, L. (1989). The gene hunt. Time Magazine, 20 March, 62–67.
Kaplan-Solms, K. and Solms, M. (2002). Clinical Studies in Neuro-Psychoanalysis: Introduction to a Depth Neuropsychology. New York: Karnac Books (2nd edn.).Google Scholar
Kemp, S. (1990). Medieval Psychology. New York: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Keenan, J. F. (1994). Christian perspectives on the human body. Theological Studies, 55, 330–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kessler, E. (1990). The intellective soul. In Schmitt et al. (1990).
Kleeberg, B. (2004). Vor der Sprache. Naturalistischer Konzepte objektiver Wahrnehmung (Before Speech. Naturalistic Concepts of Objective Perception). In Crivellari, F., Kirchmann, K., Sandl, M., and Schlögl, R. (eds.), Die Medien der Geschichte. Historizität und Medialität in interdisziplinärer Perspektive (The Media of History. Historicity and Mediality in Interdisciplinary Perspectives). Konstanz: UVK Verlagsgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Breton, D. (2002). Signes d'identité. Tatouages, piercings et autres marques corporelles (Signs of Identity. Tatoos, Piercings, and Other Body Markings). Paris: Métailié.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1694/1988). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch, Peter H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Marcus, S. J. (ed.) (2004). Neuroethics. Mapping the Field. New York: Dana Press.Google Scholar
McCabe, K. (2003). Neuroeconomics. In Nadel, L., ed., Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. London: Nature Publishing Group, vol. 3.Google Scholar
Michael, E. (2000). Renaissance theories of body, soul, and mind. In Wright, J. P. and Potter, P. (eds.), Psyche and Soma. Physicians and Metaphysicians on the Mind-Body Problem from Antiquity to Enlightenment. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Neuburger, M. (1897/1981). The Historical Development of Experimental Brain and Spinal Cord Physiology Before Flourens, annotated and translated by Edwin Clarke. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Newberg, A., D'Aquili, E., and Rause, V. (2001). Why God Won't Go Away. Brain Science and the Biology of Belief. New York: Ballantine Books.Google Scholar
Noonan, H. (1991). Personal Identity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Park, K. (1990). The organic soul. In Schmitt et al. (1990).
Perry, J. (ed.) (1975). Personal Identity. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Porter, R. (1991). History of the body. In Burke, Peter (ed.), New Perspectives on Historical Writing. Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Petitot, J., Varela, F., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J. M. (eds.). (2000). Naturalizing Phenomenology. Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, Truth, and History. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Randerson, J. (2004) Brain not body makes athletes feel tired. New Scientist, 29 July. www.newscientist.com/article.ns?id=dn6208
Renneville, M. (2000). Le langage des crânes. Une histoire de la phrénologie (The Language of Skulls. A History of Phrenology). Paris: Les Empêcheurs de tourner en rond.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. (1990). Soi-même comme un autre (Oneself as Another). Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
Schlich, T. and Wiesemann, C. (eds.) (2001). Hirntod. Zur Kulturgeschichte der Todesfeststellung (Brain Death. On the Cultural History of the Definition of Death). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Schmitt, C. B., Quentin, Kessler E., and Kraye, J. (eds.). (1990). The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. (1963). Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the Self. The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Temkin, O. (1973). Galenism. Rise and Decline of a Medical Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Varela, F. (1996). Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3, 330–350.Google Scholar
Varela, F., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Vergote, A. (1979). The body as understood in contemporary thought and biblical categories. Philosophy Today, 35, 93–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vidal, F. (2000). The eighteenth century as ‘century of psychology’. Annual Review of Law and Ethics, 8, 407–434.Google Scholar
Vidal, F.(2002). Brains, bodies, selves, and science. Anthropologies of identity and the resurrection of the body. Critical Inquiry, 28(4), 930–974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vidal, F.(2003). Soul. In Kors, A. C. (ed.). Encyclopedia of the Enlightenment. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vidal, F.(2006). Les sciences de l'âme, XVIe–XVIIIe siècle (The Sciences of the Soul, 16th–18th Century). Paris: Champion.Google Scholar
Warner, M. (1989). In the garden of delights. In Chadwick, H., Enfleshings. New York: Aperture.Google Scholar
Warner, M.(1996). In extremis: Helen Chadwick & the wound of difference. In Chadwick, H., Stilled Lives. Edinburgh: Portfolio Gallery / Odense: Kunsthallen Brandts Klædefabrik.Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. (1988). Real People. Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Zimmer, C. (2004). A distant mirror for the brain. Science, 303, n° 5654 (2 January), 43–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×