Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T19:11:44.499Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2009

Wayne A. Davis
Affiliation:
Georgetown University, Washington DC
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aaron, R. I. (1967) The Theory of Universals, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Adams, F. & Fuller, G. (1992) Names, contents, and causes. Mind and Language, 7, 205–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F.Fuller, G. & Stecker, R. (1997) The semantics of fictional names. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78, 128–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. & Stecker, R. (1994) Vacuous singular terms. Mind and Language, 9, 387–401CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F.Stecker, R. & Fuller, G. (1993a) Schiffer on modes of presentation. Analysis, 53, 30–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F.Stecker, R. & Fuller, G. (1993b) The Floyd puzzle: Reply to Yagisawa. Analysis, 53, 36–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, R. M. (1975) Where do our ideas come from? In Innate Ideas, ed. S. P. Stich, pp. 71–87. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press
Adams, R. M. (1989) Time and thisness. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 23–42. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Algeo, J. (1973) On Defining the Proper Name. Gainesville: University of Florida Press
Allan, K. (1986) Linguistic Meaning, Vol. I. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Allerton, D. J. (1987) The linguistic and sociolinguistic status of proper names. Journal of Pragmatics, 11, 61–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1963a) Meaning and use. Philosophical Quarterly, 13, 107–24. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Language, ed. J. Rosenberg & C. Travis, pp. 403–419. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1971
Alston, W. P. (1963b) The quest for meanings. Mind, 72, 79–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1964a) Philosophy of Language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Alston, W. P. (1964b) Linguistic acts. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1, 138–46Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1965) Expressing. In Philosophy in America, ed. M. Black, pp. 15–34. London: George Allen and Unwin
Alston, W. P. (1967a) Emotive meaning. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 3, pp. 486–93. New York: Macmillan
Alston, W. P. (1967b) Motives and motivation. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 5, pp. 399–409. New York: Macmillan
Alston, W. P. (1967c) Meaning. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 5, pp. 233–40. London: Macmillan
Alston, W. P. (1971) How does one tell whether a word has one, several, or many senses? In Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguistics, and Psychology, ed. D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits, pp. 35–52. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Alston, W. P. (1974) Semantic rules. In Semantics and Philosophy, ed. M. K. Munitz & P. Unger, pp. 17–48. New York: New York University Press
Alston, W. P. (1977) Sentence meaning and illocutionary act potential. Philosophical Exchange, 2, 17–35Google Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1980) The bridge between semantics and pragmatics. In The Signifying Animal: The Grammar of Language and Experience, ed. I. Rauch & G. Carr, pp. 123–34. Bloomington: Indiana University Press
Alston, W. P. (1982) Review of Holdcroft's Words and Deeds. NoÛs, 16, 623–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. P. (1987) Matching illocutionary act types. In On Being and Saying, ed. J. J. Thomson, pp. 151–63. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Alston, W. P. (1994) Illocutionary acts and linguistic meaning. In Foundations of Speech Act Theory: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives, ed. S. L. Tsohatzidis. London: Routledge
Anderson, J. R. (1983) The Architecture of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Anttila, R. (1989) Historical and Comparative Linguistics. Philadelphia: John Benjamins
Aquinas, T. (1268) A Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima, trans. R. Pasnau. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999
Aquinas, T. (1272) Treatise on Man, trans. J. F. Anderson. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1962
Aristotle. De Anima. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon, pp. 535–606. New York: Random House, 1941
Aristotle. De Interpretatione. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon, pp. 40–61. New York: Random House, 1941
Aristotle. De Memoria et Reminiscentia, trans. J. I. Baere. In The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon, pp. 607–17. New York: Random House, 1941
Armstrong, D. M. (1971) Meaning and communication. Philosophical Review, 80, 427–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A. (1641) Objections to the Meditations. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. and trans. E. Haldane & G. Ross, vol. 2, pp. 79–95. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Arnauld, A. (1662) The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic, ed. J. Dickoff & P. James. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964
Arnauld, A. (1683) On True and False Ideas, ed. and trans. S. Gaukroger. Manchester: Manchester University Press
Arnauld, A. & Lancelot, C. (1660) General and Rational Grammar: The Port-Royal Grammar, ed. and trans. J. Rieux & B. E. Rollin. The Hague: Mouton, 1975
Asher, R. E. (1994) Design features. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 875–7. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Atlas, J. D. (1989) Philosophy without Ambiguity. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Audi, R. (1982) Believing and affirming. Mind, 91, 115–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Augustine. (397) On Christian doctrine. In Great Books of the Western World, Vol. 18: Augustine, ed. R. M. Hutchins, trans. J. F. Shaw, pp. 621–98. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1952
Aune, B. (1967a) Thinking. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 8, ed. P. Edwards, pp. 101–4. New York: Macmillan
Aune, B. (1967b) Thinking. In Knowledge, Mind, and Nature, pp. 177–211. New York: Random House. Reprinted in Intentionality, Mind, and Language, ed. A. Marras, pp. 249–86. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1972
Austin, D. F. (1990) What's the Meaning of “This”?: A Puzzle about Demonstrative Belief. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Austin, J. L. (1961) The meaning of a word. In his Philosophical Papers, pp. 23–43. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Austin, J. L. (1962) How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Avramides, A. (1989) Meaning and Mind: An Examination of a Gricean Account of Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Avramides, A. (1997) Intention and convention. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. B. Hale & C. Wright, pp. 60–86. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Ayer, A. J. (1952) Language, Truth, and Logic. New York: Dover
Bach, K. (1987a) Thought and Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Bach, K. (1987b) On communicative intentions: A reply to Recanati's “On defining communicative intentions.” Mind and Language, 2, 141–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. (1994a) Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language, 9, 124–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. (1994b) Meaning, speech acts, and communication. In Basic Topics in the Philosophy of Language, ed. R. Harnish, pp. 3–21. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Bach, K. (1999) The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22, 327–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. & Harnish, R. (1979) Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Bain, A. (1855) The Senses and the Intellect. In Significant Contributions to the History of Psychology, ed. D. Robinson, vol. 4. Washington, DC: University Publications of America, 1977CrossRef
Baldi, P. (1994) Latin. In Encyclopedia of Languages and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 2015–55. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Barnes, W. H. F. (1944–5) The myth of sense data. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 45, 89–118. Reprinted in Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing, ed. R. J. Schwartz, pp. 138–67. New York: Doubleday Anchor, 1965
Barwise, J. (1987) Unburdening the language of thought. Mind and Language, 2, 82–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barwise, J. & Perry, J. (1981a) Situations and attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 668–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barwise, J. & Perry, J. (1981b) Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 6, 387–404. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 392–404. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990
Barwise, J. & Perry, J. (1983) Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Bealer, G. (1993a) A solution to Frege's puzzle. In Philosophical Perspectives, 7: Language and Logic, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 17–60. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Bealer, G. (1993b) Universals. The Journal of Philosophy, 90(1), 5–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bealer, G. (1998) A theory of concepts and concept possession. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 261–301. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Bechtel, W. (1988) Connectionism and the philosophy of mind: An overview. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 30–55. Dordrecht: Kluwer. From Southern Journal of Philosophy, 26 supplement, 17–42CrossRef
Benjafield, J. G. (1992) Cognition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Bennett, J. (1971) Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Bennett, J. (1973) The meaning-nominalist strategy. Foundations of Language, 10, 141–68Google Scholar
Bennett, J. (1976) Linguistic Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Benson, J. (1967) Emotion and expression. Philosophical Review, 76, 335–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, J. (1816) Universal grammar. In The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Vol. VIII, ed. J. Bowring, pp. 184–91. New York: Russell & Russell, 1962
Bentham, J. (1843) Essay on language. In The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Vol. VIII, ed. J. Bowring, pp. 297–338. New York: Russell & Russell, 1962
Berg, J. (1999) Referential attribution. Philosophical Studies, 96, 73–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergmann, M. (1982) Metaphorical assertions. Philosophical Review, 91, 229–45. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. L. Garfield & M. Kiteley, pp. 599–612. New York: Paragon House, 1991
Berkeley, G. (1710) A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, 2nd ed., ed. C. M. Turbayne. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1957
Bertolet, R. (1987) Speaker reference. Philosophical Studies, 52, 199–226CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezuidenhout, A. (1997) The communication of de re thoughts. NoÛs, 31, 197–225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickerton, D. (1981) Roots of Language. Ann Arbor, MI: Karoma Publishers
Biro, J. (1979) Intentionalism in the theory of meaning. The Monist, 62, 238–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, M. (1972–3) Meaning and intention: An examination of Grice's views. New Literary History, 4, 257–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. (1984) Spreading the Word. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Blackburn, S. (1992) Theory, observation and drama. Mind and Language, 7, 187–203CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blakemore, D. (1987) Semantic Constraints on Relevance. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Blakemore, D. (1992) Understanding Utterances. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Block, N. (1978) Troubles with functionalism. In Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, ed. N. Block, vol. 1, pp. 268–305. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980. From Perception and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations of Psychology. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 9 ed. C. W. Savage, pp. 261–325. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 1978
Block, N. (1986) Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. In Midwest Studies in Philosophy Volume 10, ed. P. French., T. E. Uehling, Jr. & H. K. Wettstein, pp. 615–78. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Block, N. (1993) Holism, hyper-analyticity, and hyper-compositionality. Mind and Language, 8, 1–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloomfield, L. (1933) Language. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston
Boden, M. A. (1991) A horse of a different color? In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 3–20. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Boehner, P. (1964) Introduction. In Ockham: Philosophical Works, ed. P. Boehner. pp. ⅸ–ⅼⅰ. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill
Boër, S. (1986) Chisholm on intentionality, thought, and reference. In Roderick Chisholm, ed. R. J. Bogdan, pp. 81–111. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Boër, S. (1989) Neo-Fregean thoughts. In Philosophical Perspectives, 3: Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory, ed. J. E. Tomberlin, pp. 187–224. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Boër, S. (1995) Propositional attitudes and compositional semantics. In Philosophical Perspectives, 9: AI, Connectionism, and Philosophical Psychology, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 341–79. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Boër, S. & Lycan, W. (1975) Knowing who. Philosophical Studies, 28, 299–344CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boër, S. & Lycan, W. (1980) Who, me?Philosophical Review, 89, 427–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boër, S. & Lycan, W. (1986) Knowing Who. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press
Boghossian, P. A. (1993) Does an inferential semantics rest upon a mistake?Mind and Language, 8, 27–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. A. (1998a) What the externalist can know a priori. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 197–211. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Boghossian, P. A. (1998b) Replies to commentators. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 253–60. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Bolinger, D. (1980) Language – the Loaded Weapon. London: Longman
Bolinger, D. (1982) Usage and acceptability in language. In The American Heritage Dictionary, ed. M. Berube, D. Neely & P. DeVinne, pp. 30–2. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Bradshaw, D. E. (1991) Connectionism and the specter of representationalism. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 417–36. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Brand, M. (1983) Intending and believing. In Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World: Essays Presented to Hector-Neri Castañeda, with His Replies, ed. J. E. Tomberlin, pp. 171–93. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Brand, M. (1984) Intending and Acting: Toward a Naturalized Action Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Brandom, R. (1994) Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Braun, D. (1991) Proper names, cognitive contents, and beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 62, 289–305CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, D. (1993) Empty names. NoÛs, 27, 449–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, D. (1995) Katz on names without bearers. Philosophical Review, 104, 553–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brentano, F. (1874) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, ed. L. L. McAlister. New York: Humanities Press, 1973
Broad, C. D. (1923) The theory of sensa. In his Scientific Thought, Chapters 7–8. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Reprinted in Perceiving, Sensing, and Knowing, ed. R. J. Schwartz, pp. 85–129. New York: Doubleday Anchor, 1965
Brody, B. (1969) Introduction. In T. Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (1785), ed. B. Brody, pp. ⅹⅱ–ⅹⅹⅵ. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Bruner, J., Goodnow, J. J. & Austin, G. A. (1956) A Study of Thinking. New York: Wiley
Buckley, W. F. J. (1982) Usage and acceptability in language. In The American Heritage Dictionary, ed. M. Berube, D. Neely & P. DeVinne, pp. 32–3. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Burge, T. (1975) On knowledge and convention. Philosophical Review, 84, 249–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. (1977) Belief de re. Journal of Philosophy, 74, 338–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. (1978) Belief and synonymy. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 119–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. (1979a) Sinning against Frege. Philosophical Review, 88, 398–432CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. (1979b) Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–121. Reprinted in The Nature of Mind, ed. D. M. Rosenthal, pp. 536–67. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Burks, A. W. (1949) Icon, index, and symbol. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 9, 673–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burks, A. W. (1977) Cause, Chance, and Reason: An Inquiry into the Nature of Scientific Evidence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Butchvarov, P. (1996) Conceptualism. In The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, ed. R. Audi, p. 148. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Campbell, L. (1994) Language death. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 1960–8. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Carey, S. (1991) Knowledge acquisition: Enrichment or conceptual change? In The Epigenesis of Mind: Essays on Biology and Cognition, ed. S. Carey & R. Gelman, pp. 257–91. New York: Erlbaum. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 459–87. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991
Carnap, R. (1947) Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Carnap, R. (1954) On belief sentences. In Philosophy and Analysis, ed. M. MacDonald, pp. 128–31. New York: Philosophical Library
Carr, C. R. (1978a) Expression, meaning, conversation, and indirect speech acts. Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 9, 89–100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, C. R. (1978b) Speaker meaning and illocutionary acts. Philosophical Studies, 34, 281–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (1989) Tractarian Semantics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Carruthers, P. (1992) Human Knowledge and Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Carston, R. (1994) Thought. In The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 4609–10. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Cartwright, R. (1962) Propositions. In Analytic Philosophy, ed. R. Butler, pp. 81–103. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Castañeda, H.-N. (1967) Indicators and quasi-indicators. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 85–100Google Scholar
Castañeda, H.-N. (1977) On the philosophical foundations of the theory of communication: I. Reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 165–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, H.-N. (1985) The semantics and the causal role of proper names. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46, 91–114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chastain, C. (1975) Reference and context. In Language, Mind, and Knowledge, ed. K. Gunderson, pp. 194–269. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Chierchia, G. & McConnell-Ginet, S. (1990) Meaning and Grammar: An Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Chihara, C. & Fodor, J. A. (1965) Operationalism and ordinary language. American Philosophical Quarterly, 2, 281–95Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. M. (1955–6) Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. M. (1958) The Chisholm-Sellars correspondence on intentionality. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, ed. H. Feigl, M. Scriven & G. Maxwell, vol. 2, pp. 529–39. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Intentionality, Mind, and Language, ed. A. Marras, pp. 214–48. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1972
Chisholm, R. M. (1976) Person and Object. La Salle, IL: Open Court
Chisholm, R. M. (1981) The First Person. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Chisholm, R. M. (1990) Referring to things that no longer exist. In Philosophical Perspectives, 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 545–56. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Chomsky, N. (1959) A review of B. F. Skinner's Verbal Behavior. Language, 35, 26–58. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 547–78. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964
Chomsky, N. (1961a) Degrees of grammaticalness. Word, 17, 219–39. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 384–9. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964
Chomsky, N. (1961b) On the notion “rule of grammar”. Proceedings of the Twelfth Symposium in Applied Mathematics, 12, 6–24. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 119–36. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964
Chomsky, N. (1962) A transformational approach to syntax. In Proceedings of the Third Texas Conference on Problems of Linguistic Analysis of English, 1958, ed. A. A. Hill, pp. 124–58. Austin: University of Texas Press. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 211–45. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964
Chomsky, N. (1964) Current issues in linguistic theory. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 50–118. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Chomsky, N. (1965) Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chapter 1 reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Language, ed. J. Rosenberg and C. Travis, pp. 324–64. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1971
Chomsky, N. (1972) Language and Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich
Chomsky, N. (1975) Reflections on Language. New York: Pantheon
Christensen, C. (1997) Meaning things and meaning others. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, 495–522CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (1950) On Carnap's analysis of statements of assertion and belief. Analysis, 10(5), 97–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (1951) The need for abstract entities in semantics. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 437–45. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964. From Contributions to the Analysis and Synthesis of Knowledge, Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80, 100–12
Church, A. (1954) Intensional isomorphism and the identity of belief. Philosophical Studies, 5, 65–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (1956) Propositions and sentences. In his The Problem of Universals, pp. 3–11. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Language, ed. J. Rosenberg & C. Travis, pp. 276–82. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1971
Churchland, P. M. (1979) Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Churchland, P. M. (1980) Plasticity: Conceptual and neuronal. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 133–4Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1981) Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90. Reprinted in Mind and Cognition, ed. W. G. Lycan, pp. 206–23. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990
Churchland, P. M. & Churchland, P. S. (1983) Stalking the wild epistemic engine. NoÛs, 17, 5–18. Reprinted in Mind and Cognition, ed. W. G. Lycan, pp. 300–11. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990CrossRef
Churchland, P. S. (1980) Language, thought, and information processing. NoÛs, 14, 147–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. (1991) Systematicity, structured representations, and cogntive architecture: A reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 193–217. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Clark, H. H. (1983) Making sense of nonce sense. In The Process of Language Understanding, ed. G. F. D'Arcais & R. J. Javella, pp. 297–331. New York: Wiley. Reprinted in his Arenas of Language Use, pp. 305–40. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993
Clark, H. H. (1993) Arenas of Language Use. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Clark, H. H. & Marshall, C. (1981) Definite reference and mutual knowledge. In Elements of Discourse Understanding, ed. A. Joshi, B. Webber & I. Sag, pp. 10–63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Cocchiarella, N. B. (1984) Philosophical perspectives on quantification in tense and modal logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. II, ed. D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner, pp. 309–53. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Collins, A. M. & Loftus, E. F. (1975) A spreading activation theory of semantic processing. Psychological Review, 82, 407–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Condillac, E. B. D. (1746) Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge, ed. R. G. Weyant, trans. T. Nugent. Gainesville, FL: Scholars' Facsimiles and Reprints, 1971
Cormack, A. & Kempson, R. (1991) On specificity. In Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. L. Garfield & M. Kiteley, pp. 546–81. New York: Paragon Press
Cottingham, J. (1997) Thought and language in Descartes. In Thought and Language, ed. J. Preston, pp. 29–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Cowie, A. P. (1994) Phraseology. In The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. Asher, pp. 3168–71. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Cowie, A. P., Mackin, R. & McCaig, I. (1983) Oxford Dictionary of Current Idiomatic English. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Cowie, F. (1999) What's Within? Nativism Reconsidered. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Crane, T. (1990) The language of thought: No syntax without semantics. Mind and Language, 5, 187–212CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, T. (1991) All the difference in the world. Philosophical Quarterly, 41, 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. (1985) Structured Meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Crimmins, M. (1989) Having ideas and having the concept. Mind and Language, 4, 280–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crimmins, M. (1992) Talking about Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Crimmins, M. (1995) Notional specificity. Mind and Language, 10, 464–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crimmins, M. (1998) Hesperus and Phosphorus: Sense, pretense, and reference. Philosophical Review, 107, 1–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crimmins, M. & Perry, J. (1989) The prince and the phone booth: Reporting puzzling beliefs. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 685–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cruse, D. A. (1986) Lexical Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Cummins, R. (1979) Intention, meaning, and truth-conditions. Philosophical Studies, 35, 345–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (1989) Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Cummins, R. (1991) The role of representation in connectionist explanations of cognitive capacities. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 91–114. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Cummins, R. (1996) Systematicity. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 591–614CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (1997) The LOT of the causal theory of mental content. Journal of Philosophy, 94, 535–42Google Scholar
Daniels, P. T. & Bright, W., eds. (1996) The World's Writing Systems. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Danto, A. C. (1975) Preface. In General and Rational Grammar: The Port-Royal Grammar, ed. J. Rieux, B. E. Rollin & N. Kretzmann, pp. 11–17. The Hague: Mouton
Davidson, D. (1967) Truth and meaning. Synthese, 17, 304–23. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 79–90. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990CrossRef
Davidson, D. (1968) On saying that. Synthese, 19, 130–46. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 337–46. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996CrossRef
Davidson, D. (1973) Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27, 313–28. Reprinted in Truth and Interpretation, ed. D. Davidson, pp. 125–39. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984CrossRef
Davidson, D. (1974) Belief and the basis of meaning. Synthese, 27, 309–23. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 456–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996CrossRef
Davidson, D. (1975) Thought and talk. In Mind and Language, ed. S. Guttenplan, pp. 7–23. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in The Nature of Mind, ed. D. M. Rosenthal, pp. 363–71. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Davidson, D. (1977) Reality and reference. Dialectica, 31, 247–53. Reprinted in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, ed. D. Davidson, pp. 215–25. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Davidson, D. (1983) Communication and convention. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1, 13–25. Reprinted in his Truth and Interpretation, pp. 265–80. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Davidson, D. (1986) A nice derangement of epitaphs. In Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, ed. R. Grandy & R. Warner, pp. 157–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Davidson, D. & Harman, G., eds. (1972) Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Davies, M. (1981) Meaning, Quantification, Necessity: Themes in Philosophical Logic. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Davies, M. (1987) Relevance and mutual knowledge. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 716–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. (1991) Concepts, connectionism, and the language of thought. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 229–57. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Davis, S. (1994) The Grice program and expression meaning. Philosophical Studies, 75, 293–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1981a) A theory of happiness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 111–20Google Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1981b) Pleasure and happiness. Philosophical Studies, 39, 305–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1982) A causal theory of enjoyment. Mind, 91, 240–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1984a) A causal theory of intending. American Philosophical Quarterly, 21, 43–54Google Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1984b) The two senses of desire. Philosophical Studies, 45, 181–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1986) An Introduction to Logic. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Davis, W. A. (1987) The varieties of fear. Philosophical Studies, 51, 287–310CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1988a) Expression of emotion. American Philosophical Quarterly, 25, 279–91Google Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1988b) A causal theory of experiential fear. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 13, 459–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1992a) Speaker meaning. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 223–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1992b) Cogitative and cognitive speaker meaning. Philosophical Studies, 67, 71–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (1998) Implicature: Intention, Convention, and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Davis, W. A. (1999) Communicating, telling, and informing. Philosophical Inquiry, 21, 21–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. A. (forthcoming) Nondescriptive Meaning and Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Denkel, A. (1983) The fringes of natural meaning. Philosophia, 12, 337–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1969) Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Dennett, D. C. (1978) Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books
Dennett, D. C. (1982) Beyond belief. In Thought and Object: Essays on Intentionality, ed. A. Woodfield, pp. 1–95. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Dennett, D. C. (1986) The logical geography of computational approaches: A view from the east pole. In The Representation of Knowledge and Belief, ed. M. Brand & R. M. Harnish, pp. 59–79. Tucson: University of Arizona Press
Dennett, D. C. (1991) Mother nature versus the walking encyclopedia. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 21–30. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Dennett, D. C. (1997) How to do other things with words. In Thought and Language, ed. J. Preston, pp. 219–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Descartes, R. (1641a) Meditations. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. E. Haldane & G. Ross, vol. 1, pp. 131–99. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Descartes, R. (1641b) Replies to Objections. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. & trans. E. Haldane & G. Ross, 2, pp. 1–380. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Descartes, R. (1644) The Principles of Philosophy. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. E. Haldane & G. Ross, vol. 1, pp. 203–302. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Descartes, R. (1647) Notes directed against a certain programme. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. E. Haldane & G. Ross, pp. 432–50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Descartes, R. (c. 1632) Treatise of Man, ed. and trans. T. S. Hall. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1972
DeSousa, R. (1971) How to give a piece of your mind: Or the logic of belief and assent. Review of Metaphysics, 25, 52–79Google Scholar
Deuchar, M. (1984) British Sign Language. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Devitt, M. (1981) Designation. New York: Columbia University Press
Devitt, M. (1989) The revival of ‘Fido’-Fido. In Cause, Mind, and Reality, ed. J. Heil, pp. 73–94. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Devitt, M. & Sterelny, K. (1987) Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Dickoff, J. & James, P. (1964) Introduction. In The Port Royal Logic, pp. ⅹⅹⅶ–ⅼⅰ. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill
Donnellan, K. (1966) Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 235–47. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990CrossRef
Donnellan, K. (1977) The contingent a priori and rigid designators. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 6–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorian, N. C. (1981) Language Death: The Life Cycle of a Scottish Gaelic Dialect. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
Dressler, W. U. (1996) Language death. In Towards a Critical Sociolinguistics, ed. R. Singh, pp. 195–210. Amsterdam: John Benjamins
Dretske, F. (1969) Seeing and Knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Dretske, F. (1981) Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Dretske, F. (1995) Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Dummett, M. (1967) Frege, Gottlob. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 3, pp. 225–37. New York: Macmillan
Dummett, M. (1973) Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth
Dummett, M. (1975) What is a theory of meaning? In Mind and Meaning, ed. S. Gutenplan, pp. 97–138. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Dummett, M. (1976) What is a theory of meaning? (II). In Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, ed. G. Evans & J. McDowell, pp. 67–137. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Dyer, M. (1991) Connectionism versus symbolism in high-level cognition. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 382–416. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Ebbinghaus, H. (1885) On Memory, trans. H. Ruger & C. Bussenius. New York: Teachers College, 1964
Elugardo, R. (1997) Descriptions, indexicals, and speaker meaning. Protosociology, 10, 155–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emmett, K. (1988) Meaning and mental representation. In Perspectives on Mind, ed. H. R. Otto, pp. 77–84. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Evans, G. (1973) The causal theory of names. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 47, 187–208. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 295–307. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990CrossRef
Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Evans, G. (1985) Understanding demonstratives. In his Collected Papers, pp. 291–321. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in Demonstratives, ed. P. Yourgrau, pp. 71–96. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990
Evans, G. & McDowell, J., eds. (1976) Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Evans, J. (1989) Concepts and inference. Mind and Language, 4, 29–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J., Newstead, S. E. & Byrne, R. (1993) Human Reasoning: The Psychology of Deduction. Hove, UK: Erlbaum
Fasold, R. (1990) The Sociolinguistics of Language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Feit, N. (2000) Self-ascription and belief de re. Philosophical Studies, 98, 37–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1972) Tarski's theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 69, 347–75. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth: Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. Garfield and M. Kitely, pp. 271–96. New York: Paragon House, 1991
Field, H. (1978) Mental representation. Erkenntnis, 13, 9–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. (1989) The problem of de re modality. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 197–272. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fischer, R. (1993) Abbé de l'Epée and the living dictionary. In Deaf History Unveiled, ed. J. V. Van Cleve, pp. 12–26. Washington, DC: Gallaudet University Press
Fitch, G. W. (1985) On the logic of belief. NoÛs, 19, 205–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitch, G. W. (1987) Naming and Believing. Dordrecht: D. Reidel
Fitch, G. W. (1990) Thinking of something. NoÛs, 24, 675–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitch, G. W. (1993) Non-denoting. In Philosophical Perspectives, 7: Language and Logic, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 461–86. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Fodor, J. A. (1968) Psychological Explanation. New York: Random House
Fodor, J. A. (1975) The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell
Fodor, J. A. (1981) Representations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Fodor, J. A. (1983) Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Fodor, J. A. (1987) Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Fodor, J. A. (1989) Substitution arguments and the individuation of beliefs. In Method, Reason, and Language, ed. G. Boolos, pp. 63–78. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in A Theory of Content, ed. J. Fodor, pp. 161–76. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990
Fodor, J. A. (1990a) A Theory of Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Fodor, J. A. (1990b) Psychosemantics or: Where do truth conditions come from? In Mind and Cognition, ed. W. Lycan, pp. 312–37. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Fodor, J. A. (1991) Information and representation. In Information, Language, and Cognition, 1990, ed. P. Hanson, pp. 175–97. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 513–524. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Fodor, J. A. (1994) The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Fodor, J. A. (1998a) Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fodor, J. A. (1998b) There are no recognitional concepts; not even RED. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 1–14. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Fodor, J. A. Garrett, M. Walker, E. & Parkes, C. (1980) Against definitions. Cognition, 8, 263–367. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, pp. 491–512. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Fodor, J. A. & Katz, J. J., eds. (1964) The Structure of Language: Readings in the Philosophy of Language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Fodor, J. A. & Lepore, E. (1992) Holism: A Shopper's Guide. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Fodor, J. A. & McLaughlin, B. (1990) Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work. In Connectionism, ed. C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald, pp. 199–222. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. From Cognition, 35, 183–204CrossRef
Fodor, J. A. & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988) Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. In Connectionism, ed. C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald, pp. 90–163. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1995. From Cognition, 28, 3–71
Fodor, J. D. (1977) Semantics: Theories of Meaning in Generative Grammar. New York: Crowell
Follett, W. (1970) Modern American Usage. New York: Grosset and Dunlop
Forbes, G. (1987) Indexicals and intensionality: A Fregean perspective. Philosophical Review, 96, 3–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, G. (1989) Indexicals. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, ed. D. Gabbay, pp. 463–90. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Forbes, G. (1990) The indispensability of sinn. The Philosophical Review, 99, 535–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, G. (1993) Solving the iteration problem. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16, 311–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, G. (1997a) Essentialism. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. B. Hale & C. Wright, pp. 515–33. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Forbes, G. (1997b) How much substitutivity?Analysis, 57, 109–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forbes, G. (1997c) Belief reports and speech reports. In Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes, ed. W. Kunne, A. Newen & M. Anduschus, pp. 313–30. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Forster, P. G. (1982) The Esperanto Movement. The Hague: Mouton
Frances, B. (1998) Defending Millian theories. Mind, 107, 703–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, A. C. (1894) “Prolegomena” to Locke's Essay on Human Understanding, pp. ⅺ–ⅽⅹⅼ. New York: Dover, 1959
Freddoso, A. J., ed. (1980) Ockham's Theory of Propositions: Part II of the Summa Logicae, trans. A. J. Freddosso & H. Schuurman. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
Frege, G. (1879) Begriffshrift. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach & M. Black, pp. 1–20. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952
Frege, G. (1884) The Foundations of Arithmetic, 2nd ed., ed. and trans. J. L. Austin. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1959
Frege, G. (1892a) On concept and object. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach & M. Black, pp. 42–55. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952. From Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 16, 192–205
Frege, G. (1892b) On sense and reference. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach & M. Black, pp. 56–78. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952. From Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50
Frege, G. (1894) Review of Husserl's Philosophie der arithmetic. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. T. Geach & M. Black, pp. 79–85. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952. From Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 103, 313–32
Frege, G. (1918) Thoughts. In Logical Investigations, ed. P. T. Geach, pp. 1–30. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1977
Frege, G. (1919) Notes for L. Darmstädter. In Gottlob Frege: Posthumous Works, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel & F. Kaulbach, pp. 253–7. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979
Frege, G. (1923) Compound thoughts. In Logical Investigations, ed. P. T. Geach, pp. 55–78. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1977
Frege, G. (1979) Posthumous Works, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel & F. Kaulbach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Fries, C. (1940) American English Grammar: The Grammatical Structure of Present-Day American English with Especial Reference to Social Differences or Class Dialects. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts
Gale, R. M. (1967) Indexical signs, egocentric particulars, and token-reflexive words. In The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 4, ed. P. Edwards, pp. 151–4. New York: Macmillan
Garson, J. W. (1991) What connectionists cannot do. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 113–42. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Gassendi, P. (1641) Objections to the Meditations. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes, ed. and trans. E. Haldane & G. Ross, vol. 2, pp. 135–203. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969
Gauker, C. (1994) Thinking Out Loud: An Essay on the Relation between Thought and Language. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Geach, P. T. (1957a) Mental Acts. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Geach, P. T. (1957b) On beliefs about oneself. Analysis, 18, 23–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1969) God and the Soul. London: Macmillan
Geach, P. T. (1980) Some problems about the sense and reference of proper names. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement, 6, 83–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (1996) Living Together: Rationality, Sociality, and Obligation. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
Gillett, G. (1992) Representation, Meaning, and Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Ginnane, W. J. (1960) Thoughts. Mind, 49, 372–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1970) A Theory of Human Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Goldman, A. (1986) Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Goldstein, I. (1986) Must there be indefinable words?Metaphilosophy, 17, 90–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1952) On likeness of meaning. In Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, ed. L. Linsky, pp. 67–76. Urbana: University of Illinois Press
Goodman, N. (1955) Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 2nd ed. 1965
Goschke, T. & Koppelberg, D. (1991) The concept of representation and the representation of concepts in connectionist models. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 129–62. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Graham, G. (1988) Connectionism in Pavlovian harness. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 143–65. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991. From The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 26, 73–91CrossRef
Grandy, R. (1977) Review of Convention by David Lewis. Journal of Philosophy, 74, 129–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grandy, R. (1990) Understanding and the principle of compositionality. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 557–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grandy, R. (1998) Recognitional concepts and compositionality. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 20–5. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Grandy, R. & Warner, R., eds. (1986) Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Green, M. (1997) On the autonomy of linguistic meaning. Mind, 106, 217–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, O. H. (1968) Intentions and speech acts. Analysis, 29, 109–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, O. H. (1970) The expression of emotion. Mind, 79, 551–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1957) Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1961) The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 35, 121–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1967) Indicative conditionals. In his Studies in the Way of Words, pp. 58–85. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989. A revised version of part the William James Lectures entitled “Logic and Conversation” presented at Harvard University in 1967
Grice, H. P. (1968) Utterer's meaning, sentence meaning, and word meaning. Foundations of Language, 4, 225–42. Reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words, ed. H. P. Grice, pp. 117–37. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989CrossRef
Grice, H. P. (1969) Utterer's meaning and intentions. Philosophical Review, 78, 147–77. Reprinted in his Studies in the Way of Words, pp. 86–116. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989CrossRef
Grice, H. P. (1975) Logic and conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, 3: Speech Acts, ed. P. Cole & J. Morgan. New York: Academic Press. Reprinted in his Studies in the Way of Words, pp. 22–40. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989
Grice, H. P. (1982) Meaning revisited. In Mutual Knowledge, ed. N. Smith, pp. 223–43. New York: Academic Press
Grice, H. P. (1986) Reply to Richards. In Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, ed. R. Grandy & R. Warner, pp. 45–106. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Grice, H. P. (1989) Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Guttenplan, S., ed. (1975) Mind and Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Hacking, I. (1975) Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Hale, B. & Wright, C. (1997) A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Hall, R. A. Jr. (1962) Review of Webster's Third New International Dictionary. The Quarterly Journal of Speech, 68, 434–5Google Scholar
Halle, M. (1962) Phonology in generative grammar. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 334–52. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964. From Word, 18, 54–72CrossRef
Hamlyn, D. W. (1967a) Analytic and synthetic statements. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 1, pp. 105–9. New York: Macmillan
Hamlyn, D. W. (1967b) A priori and a posteriori. In The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 2, pp. 140–4. New York: Macmillan
Hamlyn, D. W. (1971) Epistemology and conceptual development. In Cognitive Development and Epistemology, ed. T. Mischel, pp. 3–24. New York: Academic Press
Hampshire, S. (1939–40) Ideas, propositions, and signs. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 40, 1–26
Hampshire, S. (1972) Feeling and expression. In Freedom of Mind and Other Essays, pp. 143–60. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Harman, G. (1968) Three levels of meaning. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 590–602CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1972) Deep structure as logical form. In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson & G. Harman, pp. 25–47. Dordrecht: Reidel
Harman, G. (1973) Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Harman, G. (1974) Review of Meaning by S. Schiffer. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 224–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1975) Language, thought, and communication. In Language, Mind, and Knowledge, ed. K. Gunderson, pp. 270–98. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Harman, G. (1977a) Review of Bennett. Language, 53, 417–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1977b) How to use propositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 14, 173–6Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1978) Is there mental representation? In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume IX: Perception and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations of Psychology, ed. C. W. Savage, pp. 57–65. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Harnish, R. (1976) Logical form and implicature. In An Integrated Theory of Linguistic Ability, ed. T. G. Bever, J. J. Katz & T. Langedoen, pp. 313–92. New York: Crowell. Reprinted in Pragmatics: A Reader, ed. S. Davis, pp. 316–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Harris, R. (1980) The Language Makers. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Harris, R. & Taylor, T. (1997) Landmarks in Linguistic Thought: The Western Tradition from Socrates to Saussure. London: Routledge
Harrison, G. (1980) Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. New York: St. Martin's Press
Hartley, D. (1749) Observations on Man, ed. T. L. Huguelet. Gainesville, FL: Scholars' Facsimiles and Reprints, 1966
Hartnack, J. (1972) On thinking. Mind, 81, 543–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, G. (1991) Representation in perception and cognition: Connectionist affordances. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 163–95. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Heal, J. (1997) Indexical predicates and their uses. Mind, 106, 619–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heath, P. L. (1967) Concepts. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 2, pp. 177–80. New York: Macmillan
Hebb, D. O. (1966) A Textbook of Psychology. Philadelphia: Saunders
Heidelberger, H. (1982) What is it to understand a sentence that contains an indexical?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 43, 21–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (1980) Computation, cognition, and representation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 139CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. (1981) Does cognitive psychology rest on a mistake?Mind, 90, 321–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Higginbotham, J. (1998) Conceptual competence. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 149–62. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Hill, C. O. (1991) Word and Object in Husserl, Frege, and Russell: The Roots of Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press
Hintikka, J. (1963) The modes of modality. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 65–79. Reprinted in The Possible and the Actual, ed. M. J. Loux, pp. 65–79. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979
Hirschberg, J. (1991) A Theory of Scalar Implicature. New York: Garland
Hobbes, T. (1651) Leviathan, ed. A. D. Lindsay. New York: Dutton
Hobbes, T. (1655) Computation or Logic, trans. A. P. Martinich. In Thomas Hobbes: Part I of De Corpore, ed. I. C. Hungerland & G. R. Vick, pp. 171–331. New York: Abaris, 1981
Hockett, C. F. (1958) A Course in Modern Linguistics. New York: Macmillan
Hockett, C. F. (1966) The problems of universals in language. In Universals of Language, 2nd ed., ed. J. H. Greenberg, pp. 1–29. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Holdcroft, D. (1978) Words and Deeds: Problems in the Theory of Speech Acts. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Horgan, T. (1998) Recognitional concepts and the compositionality of concept possession. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 28–33. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Horgan, T. & Tienson, J. (1988) Settling into a new paradigm. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 241–60. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991a. From The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 26 supplement, 97–113CrossRef
Horgan, T. & Tienson, J., eds. (1991b) Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Hornstein, N. (1984) Logic as Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Horwich, P. (1997) The composition of meanings. Philosophical Review, 106, 503–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. (1998a) Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Horwich, P. (1998b) Concept constitution. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 15–19. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Horwich, P. (1998c) The deflationary view of reference. Lingua e Stile, 33, 367–81Google Scholar
Hugly, P. & Sayward, C. (1979) A problem about conversational implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy, 3, 19–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hugly, P. & Sayward, C. (1995) What's so special about sentences?Communication and Cognition, 28, 409–26Google Scholar
Hull, C. L. (1920) Quantitative aspects of the evolution of concepts. Psychological Monographs, 28, 1–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, C. L. (1943) The Principles of Behavior. New York: Appleton-Century
Hume, D. (1739) A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888
Humphrey, G. (1951) Thinking: An Introduction to Experimental Psychology. London: Methuen
Hungerland, I. C. (1960) Contextual implication. Inquiry, 3, 211–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hungerland, I. C. & Vick, G. R. (1981) Hobbes's theory of language, speech, and reasoning. In Thomas Hobbes: Part I of De Corpore, ed. I. C. Hungerland & G. R. Vick, pp. 1–70. New York: Abaris
Hunt, E. B. (1962) Concept Learning: An Information Processing Problem. New York: Wiley
Husserl, E. (1891) Philosophie der Arithmetik. Halle: Pfeffer
Husserl, E. (1900) Logical Investigations, trans. J. N. Findlay. New York: Humanities Press, 1970
Hyslop, A. (1977) Grice without an audience. Analysis, 37, 67–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackendoff, R. (1983) Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Jackendoff, R. (1989) What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?Mind and Language, 4, 68–101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacob, P. (1997) Frege's puzzle and belief ascription. In Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes, ed. W. Kunne, A. Newen & M. Anduschus, pp. 215–45. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Jacob, P. (1998) Conceptual competence and inadequate conceptions. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 169–73. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
James, W. (1890) The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover, 1950
Jamieson, D. (1975) David Lewis on convention. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 5, 73–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Janton, P. (1993) Esperanto: Language, Literature, and Community, trans. H. Tonkin, J. Edwards & K. Johnson-Weiner. Albany: State University of New York Press
Johnson-Laird, P. N.Hermann, D. J. & Chaffin, R. (1984) Only connections: A critique of semantic networks. Psychological Bulletin, 96, 292–315CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. & Steedman, M. (1978) The psychology of syllogisms. Cognitive Psychology, 10, 64–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, D. K. (1992) What is colloquial Esperanto?Esperantic Studies, 2, 3–4Google Scholar
Joseph, H. W. B. (1916) An Introduction to Logic, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Jubien, M. (1996) The myth of identity conditions. In Philosophical Perspectives, 10: Metaphysics, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 343–56. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Kamp, H. & Partee, B. (1995) Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57, 129–91CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kant, I. (1787) Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. K. Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965
Kapitan, T. (1994) Exports and imports: Anaphora in attitudinal ascriptions. In Philosophical Perspectives, 8: Logic and Language, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 273–92. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Kaplan, D. (1969) Quantifying in. In Words and Objections: Essays on the Work of W. V. Quine, ed. D. Davidson & J. Hintikka, pp. 206–42. Dordrecht: Reidel
Kaplan, D. (1977) Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 481–563. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989
Kaplan, D. (1989) Afterthoughts. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 565–614. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Kaplan, D. (1990a) Thoughts on demonstratives. In Demonstratives, ed. P. Yourgrau, pp. 34–49. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Kaplan, D. (1990b) Words. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 64, 93–119CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karttunen, L. & Peters, S. (1979) Conversational implicature. In Syntax and Semantics, 11: Presupposition, ed. C.-K. Oh & D. A. Dinneen, pp. 1–56. New York: Academic Press
Kasher, A. (1982) Gricean inference revisited. Philosophica, 29, 25–44Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1964a) Semi-sentences. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 400–16. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Katz, J. J. (1964b) Analyticity and contradiction in natural language. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 519–43. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Katz, J. J. (1964c) Mentalism in linguistics. Language, 40, 124–37. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Language, ed. J. Rosenberg & C. Travis, pp. 364–78. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1971
Katz, J. J. (1966) Philosophy of Language. New York: Harper and Row
Katz, J. J. (1972) Semantic Theory. New York: Harper and Row
Katz, J. J. (1974) Where things now stand with the analytic-synthetic distinction. Synthese, 28, 283–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1977a) A proper theory of names. Philosophical Studies, 31, 1–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1977b) Propositional Structure and Illocutionary Force. New York: Crowell
Katz, J. J. (1986a) Why intensionalists ought not be Fregeans. In Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, ed. E. LePore, pp. 59–91. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Katz, J. J. (1986b) Cogitations. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Katz, J. J. (1987) Descartes's Cogito. Philosophical Quarterly, 68, 154–81. Reprinted in Demonstratives, ed. P. Yourgrau, pp. 154–181. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990CrossRef
Katz, J. J. (1990) Has the description theory been refuted? In Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam, ed. G. Boolos, pp. 31–61. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Katz, J. J. (1994) Names without bearers. Philosophical Review, 103, 1–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. J. & Fodor, J. A. (1963) The structure of a semantic theory. Language, 39, 170–210. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 479–518. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964CrossRef
Katz, J. J. & Langendoen, D. T. (1976) Pragmatics and presupposition. Language, 52, 1–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemmerling, A. (1986) Utterer's meaning revisited. In Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, ed. R. Grandy & R. Warner, pp. 131–55. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Kempson, R. (1975) Presupposition and the Delimitation of Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Kiel, F. C. (1989) Concepts, Kinds, and Cognitive Development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Kim, J. (1972) Physicalism and the multiple realizability of mental states. In Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, ed. N. Block, vol. 1, pp. 235–6. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980. Originally published as Phenomenal properties, psychophysical laws, and the identity theory. Monist, 56, 177–192CrossRef
Kimble, G. A. (1961) Hilgard and Marquis' Conditioning and Learning. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts
Kiteley, M. (1991) Subjectivity's bailiwick and the person of its bailiff. In Meaning and Truth: Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. Garfield and M. Kiteley, pp. 372–95. New York: Paragon House
Kittay, E. (1987) Metaphor: Its Cognitive Force and Linguistic Structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Kneale, W. & Kneale, M. (1962) The Development of Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Knott, T. (1934) Standard English and incorrect English. American Speech, 9, 83–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koch, P. J. (1983) Expressing emotions. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 176–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krech, D., Crutchfield, R. S. & Livson, N. (1969) Elements of Psychology, 2nd ed. New York: Knopf
Kretzmann, N. (1967) History of semantics. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 8, ed. P. Edwards, pp. 358–406. New York: Macmillan
Kretzmann, N. (1968) The main thesis of Locke's semantic theory. Philosophical Review, 77, 175–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1977) Speaker reference and semantic reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 255–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1979) A puzzle about belief. In Meaning and Use, ed. A. Margalit, pp. 239–83. Dordrecht: Reidel
Kripke, S. (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Krucêra, H. (1982) The mathematics of language. In The American Heritage Dictionary, Second College Edition, ed. M. Berube, D. Neely & P. DeVinne, pp. 37–40. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Kuhn, T. S. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Künne, W. (1997) First person propositions: A Fregean account. In Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes, ed. W. Künne, A. Newen & M. Anduschus, pp. 49–68. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Kyburg, H. (1980) Functional architecture and free will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 143–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyle, J. G. & Woll, B. (1985) Sign Language: The Study of Deaf People and Their Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Labov, W. (1966) The Social Stratification of Behavior. Washington, DC: Center for Applied Linguistics
Labov, W. (1970) The Study of Nonstandard English. Champaign, IL: National Council of Teachers of English
Lahav, R. (1989) Against compositionality: The case of adjectives. Philosophical Studies, 57, 261–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1971a) On generative semantics. In Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader, ed. D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits, pp. 232–96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Lakoff, G. (1971b) Presupposition and relative well-formedness. In Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader, ed. D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits, pp. 329–40. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Lakoff, G. (1987) Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Lakoff, G. (1989) Some empirical results about the nature of concepts. Mind and Language, 4, 103–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lance, M. & O'Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1997) The Grammar of Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Landau, S. I. (1984) Dictionaries: The Art and Craft of Lexicography. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons
Large, A. (1985) The Artificial Language Movement. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Laurence, S. (1996) A Chomskian alternative to convention-based semantics. Mind, 105, 269–301CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laurence, S. & Margolis, E. (1997) Regress arguments against the language of thought. Analysis, 57, 60–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leech, G. (1983) Principles of Pragmatics. London: Longmans
Lehrer, A. (1974) Semantic Fields and Lexical Structure. Amsterdam: North Holland
Leibniz, G. W. F. (1676) What is an idea? In Leibniz: Selections, ed. P. P. Wiener, pp. 281–3. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1951
Leibniz, G. W. F. (1677) Dialogue on the connection between things and words. In Leibniz: Selections, ed. P. P. Wiener, pp. 6–11. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1951
Leibniz, G. W. F. (1684) Reflections on knowledge, truth, and ideas. In Leibniz: Selections, ed. P. P. Wiener, pp. 283–90. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1951
Leibniz, G. W. F. (1709) New Essays Concerning Human Understanding, 2nd ed., trans. A. G. Langley. Chicago: Open Court
Leonard, S. A. (1929) The Doctrine of Correctness in English Usage 1700–1800. New York: Russell and Russell
Levinson, S. C. (1983) Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Lewis, D. (1969) Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Lewis, D. (1972) General semantics. In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson & G. Harman, pp. 169–218. Dordrecht: Reidel
Lewis, D. (1975) Languages and language. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Language, ed. K. Gunderson, vol. 7, pp. 3–35. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Lewis, D. (1976) Conventions: Reply to Jamieson. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6, 113–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979) Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88, 513–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1981a) What puzzling Pierre does not believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59, 282–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1981b) Index, context, and content. In Philosophy and Grammar, ed. S. Kanger & S. Ohman, pp. 79–100. Dordrecht: Reidel
Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Lewis, D. (1992) Meaning without use: Reply to Hawthorne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 106–10CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewy, C. (1976) Meaning and Modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Liedtke, F. (1990) Meaning and expression: Marty and Grice on intentional semantics. In Mind, Meaning, and Metaphysics, ed. K. Mulligan, pp. 29–49. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Linde, C. & Labov, W. (1975) Spatial networks as a site for the study of language and thought. Language, 51, 924–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linsky, L. (1963) Reference and referents. In Philosophy and Ordinary Language, ed. C. C. Caton, pp. 74–89. Urbana: University of Illinois Press
Linsky, L. (1972) Analytic/synthetic and semantic theory. In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson & G. Harman, pp. 473–82. Dordrecht: Reidel
Linsky, L. (1977) Names and Descriptions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Linsky, L. (1983) Oblique Contexts. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Lloyd, D. (1991) Leaping to conclusions: Connections, consciousness, and the computational mind. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 444–57. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Loar, B. (1972) Reference and propositional attitudes. Philosophical Review, 81, 43–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, B. (1976a) The semantics of singular terms. Philosophical Studies, 30, 353–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, B. (1976b) Two theories of meaning. In Truth and Meaning, ed. G. Evans & J. McDowell, pp. 138–61. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Loar, B. (1981) Mind and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Loar, B. (1987) Names in thought. Philosophical Studies, 51, 169–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, B. (1988) Social content and psychological content. In Contents of Thought, ed. R. H. Grimm & D. D. Merrill, pp. 99–110. Tucson: University of Arizona Press. Reprinted in The Nature of Mind, ed. D. M. Rosenthal, pp. 569–75. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Loar, B. (1991) Can we explain intentionality? In Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, ed. B. Lower & G. Rey, pp. 119–35. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Locke, J. (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A. C. Fraser. New York: Dover, 1959
Loewer, B. & Rey, G., eds. (1991) Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Lombard, L. G. & Stine, G. C. (1974) Grice's intentions. Philosophical Studies, 25, 207–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loux, M., ed. (1974) Ockham's Theory of Terms: Part I of the Summa Logicae. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
Loux, M., ed. (1979) The Possible and the Actual. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Love, N. (1994) Correctness and norms. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. Asher, pp. 1398–403. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Löfstedt, E. (1959) Late Latin. London: Kegan Paul, Trench Trubner
Luntley, M. (1984) The sense of a name. Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 265–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. (1981) Toward a homuncular theory of believing. Cognition and Brain Theory, 4, 139–59Google Scholar
Lycan, W. (1984) Logical Form in Natural Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Lycan, W. (1985) The paradox of naming. In Analytical Philosophy in Comparative Perspective, ed. B. K. Matilal & J. L. Shaw, pp. 81–102. Dordrecht: Reidel
Lycan, W., ed. (1990) Mind and Cognition: A Reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Lycan, W. (1993) A deductive argument for the representational theory of thought. Mind and Language, 8, 414–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. (1995) Philosophy of language. In The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, ed. R. Audi, pp. 586–9. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Lyons, J. (1971) Introduction to Theoretical Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Lyons, J. (1977) Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Macdonald, C. (1995) Introduction: Classicism v. connectionism. In Connectionism, ed. C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald, pp. 3–27. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Macdonald, C. & Macdonald, G., eds. (1995) Connectionism: Debates in Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Macià, J. (1998) On concepts and conceptions. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 175–85. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
MacKay, A. F. (1972) Professor Grice's theory of meaning. Mind, 81, 57–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N. (1954) Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. Philosophical Review, 63, 530–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N. (1973) Thoughtless brutes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 46, 5–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maloney, J. C. (1989) The Mundane Matter of the Mental Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Marconi, D. (1990) Dictionaries and proper names. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 7, 77–92Google Scholar
Margolis, E. (1998) How to acquire a concept. Mind and Language, 13, 347–69. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, pp. 549–67. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Margolis, E. & Laurence, S. (1999) Concepts and cognitive science. In Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 3–81. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Martinich, A. P. (1979) The attributive use of proper names. Analysis, 37, 159–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martinich, A. P. (1981) Translator's commentary. In Thomas Hobbes: Part I of de Corpore, ed. I. C. Hungerland & G. R. Vick, pp. 335–440. New York: Abaris
Martinich, A. P. (1984) Communication and Reference. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter
Marty, A. (1908) Untersuchungen Zur Grundlegung der Allgemeinen Grammatik und Sprach-Philosophie. Halle: Niemeyer
Marx, M. H., ed. (1969) Learning: Processes. New York: Macmillan
Mates, B. (1950) Synonymity. University of California Publications in Philosophy, 25, 201–26. Reprinted in Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, ed. L. Linsky, pp. 111–38. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1952
Mates, B. (1958) Comments on the foregoing. Inquiry, 1, 240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mates, B. (1986) The Philosophy of Leibniz. New York: Oxford University Press
McCawley, J. D. (1968) The role of semantics in a grammar. In Universals in Linguistic Theory, ed. E. Bach & R. T. Harms, pp. 124–69. New York: Holt
McCawley, J. D. (1987) The multidimensionality of pragmatics. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 723–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCawley, J. D. (1994) Generative semantics. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 1398–1403. Oxford: Pergamon Press
McClelland, J. L., Rumelhart, D. E. & Hinton, G. E. (1986) The appeal of parallel distributed processing. In Parallel Distributed Processing, ed. D. E. Rumelhart & J. L. McClelland, pp. 3–44. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
McDermott, M. (1988) The narrow semantics of names. Mind, 97, 224–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1977) On the sense and reference of a proper name. Mind, 86, 159–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1978) Physicalism and primitive denotation: Field on Tarski. Erkenntnis, 13, 131–52. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth: Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. Garfield and M. Kiteley, pp. 297–315. New York: Paragon House, 1991
McDowell, J. (1980) Meaning, communication, and knowledge. In Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson, ed. Z. van Straaten, pp. 117–39. Oxford: Clarendon Press
McGinn, C. (1982) The structure of content. In Thought and Object, ed. A. Woodfield, pp. 207–58. Oxford: Clarendon Press
McGinn, C. (1997) The Character of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press
McKay, T. (1981) On proper names in belief ascriptions. Philosophical Studies, 39, 287–303CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinsey, M. (1978) Names and intentionality. Philosophical Review, 87, 171–200CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinsey, M. (1994) Individuating beliefs. In Philosophical Perspectives, 8: Logic and Language, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 303–29. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Meggle, G. (1997) Brundbegriffe de Kommunicakation, 2nd ed. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter
Meinong, A. (1904) The theory of objects. In Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, ed. R. M. Chisholm, pp. 76–117. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1960
Meinong, A. (1910) On Assumptions, ed. and trans. J. Heanue. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983
Mesthrie, R. (1994) Language maintenance, shift, and death. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 1988–93. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Mey, J. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Mill, J. (1829) Analysis of the Phenomenon of the Human Mind, ed. J. S. Mill. London: Longmans Green Reader and Dyer, 1869
Mill, J. S. (1843) A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green
Mill, J. S. (1865) An Examination of the Philosophy of Sir William Hamilton. London: Longmans
Mill, J. S. (1869) Notes. In James Mill: Analysis of the Phenomenon of the Human Mind, ed. J. S. Mill, vol. 1, London: Longmans Green Reader and Dyer
Mill, J. S. (1879) A System of Logic, 10th ed. London: Longmans, Green
Miller, S. (1986) Conventions, interdependence of action, and collective ends. NoÛs, 20, 117–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, S. (1992) On conventions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 435–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. (1984) Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Millikan, R. (1986) Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science without content. Philosophical Review, 95, 47–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. (1987) What Peter thinks when he hears Mary speak. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 725–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. (1998a) A more plausible kind of “recognitional concept.” In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 35–41. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Millikan, R. (1998b) A common structure for concepts of individuals, stuffs, and real kinds: More mama, more milk, and more mouse. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 55–65. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 525–47. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Minsky, M. (1975) A framework for representing knowledge. In The Psychology of Computer Vision, ed. P. H. Winston. New York: McGraw Hill
Moore, G. E. (1942) A reply to my critics. In The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. P. A. Schilpp, pp. 533–689. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1968
Moore, J. G. (1999a) Misdisquotation and substitutivity: When not to infer belief from assent. Mind, 108, 335–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, J. G. (1999b) Saving substitutivity in simple sentences. Analysis, 59, 91–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, C. (1946) Signs, Language, and Behaviour. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Moya, C. (1998) Boghossian's reductio of compatibilism. In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 243–51. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Muller, S. H. (1964) The World's Living Languages. New York: Ungar
Murphy, G. & Medin, D. (1985) The role of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological Review, 92, 289–316. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, pp. 425–58. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Nagel, T. (1974) What is it like to be a bat?The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neale, S. (1992) Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, R. J. (1992) Naming and Reference. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Newman, J. (1962) Review of Webster's Third New International Dictionary. The Quarterly Journal of Speech, 68, 437–8Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. & Ross, L. (1980) Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Noonan, H. (1980–1) Names and belief. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81, 93–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noonan, H. (1984) Fregean thoughts. Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 205–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nunberg, G. (1981) Validating pragmatic explanations. In Radical Pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, pp. 199–222. New York: Academic Press
Nunberg, G. (1982) English and good English. In The American Heritage Dictionary, ed. M. Berube, D. Neely & P. DeVinne, pp. 34–6. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Nurse, D. & Spear, T. (1985) The Swahili. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
Ockham, W. Expositio super duos libros perihermenias, trans. P. Boehner. In Philosophical Writings: A Selection, ed. P. Boehner. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964
Ockham, W. Ordinatio, trans. P. Boehner. In Philosophical Writings: A Selection, ed. P. Boehner. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964
Ockham, W. Quodlibeta, trans. P. Boehner. In Philosophical Writings: A Selection, ed. P. Boehner. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964
Ockham, W. (1325) Summa Logicae, Part I: On Terms. In Ockham's Theory of Terms: Part I of the Summa Logicae, ed. M. J. Loux, pp. 49–221. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974
Osherson, D. & Smith, E. (1981) On the adequacy of prototype theory as a theory of concepts. Cognition, 9, 35–58. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 261–78. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
O'Grady, W., Dobrovolsky, M. & Aronoff, M. (1993) Contemporary Linguistics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin's Press
O'Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1989) On the compatibility of connectionist and classical models. Philosophical Psychology, 2, 5–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1990) A note on “languages and language.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68, 116–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1993) Meaning and evidence: Reply to Lewis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 71, 202–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pap, A. (1955) Belief, synonymity, and analysis. Philosophical Studies, 6, 11–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pap, A. (1957) Belief and propositions. Philosophy of Science, 24, 123–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pappas, G. S. (1995) Idea. In The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, ed. R. Audi, p. 355. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Partee, B. (1984) Compositionality. In Varieties of Formal Semantics, ed. F. Landman & F. Veltman, pp. 281–311. Dordrecht: Foris
Pateman, T. (1982) David Lewis's theory of convention and the social life of language. Journal of Pragmatics, 6, 135–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patton, T. E. (1994) Proper names: Possibility and culture. In Language, Mind, and Art: Essays in Appreciation of Analysis, and in Honor of Paul Ziff, ed. D. Jamieson, pp. 39–53. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Patton, T. E. & Stampe, D. W. (1969) The rudiments of meaning: On Ziff on Grice. Foundations of Language, 5, 2–16Google Scholar
Pavlov, I. P. (1927) Conditioned Reflexes: An Investigation of the Physiological Activity of the Cerebral Cortex. London: Oxford University Press
Pawley, A. (1985) Lexicalization. In Language and Linguistics: The Interdependence of Theory, Data, and Application, ed. D. Tannen & J. E. Alatis, pp. 98–120. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press
Peacocke, C. (1975) Proper names, reference, and rigid designation. In Meaning, Reference, and Necessity, ed. S. Blackburn, pp. 109–32. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Definite Descriptions: A Reader, ed. G. Osterling, pp. 201–34. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1998
Peacocke, C. (1976) Truth definitions and actual languages. In Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, ed. G. Evans & J. McDowell, pp. 162–88. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Peacocke, C. (1981) Demonstrative thought and psychological explanation. Synthese, 49, 187–217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1983) Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and Their Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Peacocke, C. (1986) Thoughts: An Essay on Content. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Peacocke, C. (1989) Possession conditions: A focal point for theories of concepts. Mind and Language, 4, 51–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1992) A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Pelczar, M. & Rainsbury, J. (1998) The indexical character of names. Synthese, 114, 293–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, D. L. (1967) The Concept of Pleasure. The Hague: Mouton
Perry, J. (1977) Frege on demonstratives. Philosophical Review, 86, 474–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, J. (1979) The problem of the essential indexical. NoÛs, 13, 3–21. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, ed. J. Garfield and M. Kiteley, pp. 613–27. New York: Paragon House, 1991
Perry, J. (1980) A problem about continued belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 317–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, J. (1983) Castañeda on He and I. In Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 15–39. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Perry, J. (1990) Self-notions. Logos, 11, 17–31Google Scholar
Perry, J. (1997a) Indexicals and demonstratives. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. B. Hale & C. Wright, pp. 586–612. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Perry, J. (1997b) Reflexivity, indexicality, and names. In Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes, ed. W. Künne, A. Newen, and M. Anduschus, pp. 3–19. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Peters, R. (1956) Hobbes. Harmondsworth: Penguin
Peters, R. (1967) Hobbes, 2nd ed. Harmondsworth: Penguin
Pettit, P. (1987) Inference and information. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 727–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1931–5) Collected Papers, ed. P. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. W. Burks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Pitcher, G. (1964) Introduction. In his Truth, pp. 1–15. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Place, U. T. (1956) Is consciousness a brain process?British Journal of Psychology, 47, 44–50CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Plantinga, A. (1985) Self-profile and replies. In Alvin Plantinga, ed. J. E. Tomberlin & P. Van Inwagen, pp. 3–97, 313–94. Dordrecht: Reidel
Plato. Cratylus, trans. B. Jowett. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. E. Hamilton, pp. 421–74. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961
Plato. Phaedo, trans. H. Tredennick. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. E. Hamilton, pp. 40–98. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961
Plato. Theaetetus, trans. F. M. Cornford. In The Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. E. Hamilton, pp. 845–919. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1961
Platts, M. (1979) Ways of Meaning. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Pollock, J. L. (1980) Thinking about an object. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 487–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, R. (1980) Semantics and pragmatics of sentence connectives in natural languages. In Speech-Act Theory and Pragmatics, ed. J. Searle, F. Kiefer & M. Bierwisch, pp. 169–203. Amsterdam: Reidel
Posner, R. (1997) Romance languages. In Encyclopaedia Britannica, pp. 620–39. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica
Postal, P. M. (1964) Limitations of phrase structure grammars. In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 137–51. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Price, H. H. (1953) Thinking and Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Price, H. H. (1954) Belief and will. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 28, 1–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H. H. (1969) Belief. New York: Humanities
Priestley, J. (1762) A Course of Lectures on the Theory of Language and Universal Grammar. Menston, England: Scolar Press, 1970
Putnam, H. (1954) Synonymity, and the analysis of belief sentences. Analysis, 14, 114–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1967) The nature of mental states. In The Nature of Mind, ed. D. M. Rosenthal, pp. 197–210. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991. Originally published as “Psychological Predicates” in Art, Mind, and Religion, ed. W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill, pp. 37–8. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press
Putnam, H. (1970a) On properties. In Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, ed. A. R. Anderson, P. Benacerraf, A. Grünbaum, G. Massey, N. Rescher, and R. Rudner. Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted in his Philosophical Papers, pp. 305–22. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975
Putnam, H. (1970b) Is semantics possible? In Languages, Belief, and Metaphysics, ed. H. Kiefer & M. Munitz. New York: State University of New York Press. Reprinted in Concepts: Core Readings, ed. E. Margolis & S. Laurence, pp. 178–87. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999
Putnam, H. (1973) Meaning and reference. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 699–711. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Language, ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 308–15. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991CrossRef
Putnam, H. (1975) The meaning of “meaning.” In Language, Mind, and Knowledge, ed. K. Gunderson, pp. 131–93. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Putnam, H. (1981) Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Pylyshyn, Z. (1980) Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundations of cognitive science. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 111–32, 154–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quillian, M. R. (1968) Semantic memory. In Semantic Information Processing, ed. M. L. Minsky, pp. 216–55. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Quine, W. V. O. (1936) Truth by convention. In Essays for A. N. Whitehead, ed. O. H. Lee. New York: Longmans. Reprinted in Ways of Paradox, ed. W. V. O. Quine, pp. 70–9. New York: Random House, 1966
Quine, W. V. O. (1948) On what there is. In his From a Logical Point of View, pp. 1–19. New York: Harper and Row, 1963
Quine, W. V. O. (1953) Two dogmas of empiricism. In his From a Logical Point of View, pp. 20–46. New York: Harper and Row, 1963. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Language, ed. J. F. Rosenberg and C. Travis, pp. 63–81. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1971
Quine, W. V. O. (1956) Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53. Reprinted in The Ways of Paradox, ed. W. V. O. Quine, pp. 183–94. New York: Random House, 1966CrossRef
Quine, W. V. O. (1959) Methods of Logic. New York: Hold, Rinehart, and Winston
Quine, W. V. O. (1960) Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Quine, W. V. O. (1961) The problem of meaning in linguistics. In his From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed., pp. 47–64. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961. Reprinted in The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 21–32. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1964
Quine, W. V. O. (1967) Russell's ontological development. In Bertrand Russell, Philosopher of the Century, ed. R. Schoenman. Boston: Little Brown
Quine, W. V. O. (1969a) Ontological relativity. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, pp. 26–68. New York: Columbia University Press
Quine, W. V. O. (1969b) Foreword to Convention by D. K. Lewis, pp. ⅺ–ⅻ. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Quine, W. V. O. (1972) Methodological reflections on current linguistic theory. In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson & G. Harman, pp. 442–54. Dordrecht: Reidel
Quine, W. V. O. (1987) Ideas. In Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary, pp. 87–9. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Quintilian, M. F. Institutio Oratoria, trans. H. E. Butler. In Landmarks in Linguistic Thought I, ed. R. Harris & T. J. Taylor, pp. 60–75. London: Routledge, 1997
Radutzky, E. (1993) The education of deaf people in Italy and the use of Italian Sign Language. In Deaf History Unveiled, ed. J. V. Van Cleve, pp. 237–51. Washington, DC: Gallaudet University Press
Ramsey, W., Stich, S. P. & Garon, J. (1991) Connectionism, eliminativism, and the future of folk psychology. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 199–228. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Rand, A. (1969) Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology. New York: The Objectivist
Read, A. W. (1962) Review of Webster's Third New International Dictionary. The Quarterly Journal of Speech, 68, 438–9Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (1986) On defining communicative intentions. Mind and Language, 1, 213–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (1987) Meaning and Force: The Pragmatics of Performative Utterances. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Recanati, F. (1989) Referential/attributive: A contextualist proposal. Philosophical Studies, 56, 217–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (1990) Direct reference, meaning, and thought. NoÛs, 24, 697–722CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (1993) Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Recanati, F. (1995) The alleged priority of literal interpretation. Cognitive Science, 19, 207–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reid, T. (1764) Inquiry into the Human Mind. In Thomas Reid's Inquiry and Essays, ed. K. Lehrer & E. Beanblossom, pp. 3–125. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975
Reid, T. (1785) Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, ed. B. Brody. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1969
Reimer, M. (1995) A defense of de re belief reports. Mind and Language, 10, 446–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reimer, M. (1998) The Wettstein/Salmon debate: Critique and resolution. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, 130–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. (1991) An explanatory budget for connectionism and eliminativism. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 219–40. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Rey, G. (1994) Concepts. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, ed. S. Guttenplan. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Rey, G. (1995) A not “merely empirical” argument for a language of thought. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 201–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richard, M. (1981) Temporalism and eternalism. Philosophical Studies, 39, 1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richard, M. (1987) Attitude ascriptions, semantic theory, and pragmatic evidence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 87, 243–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richard, M. (1989) How I say what you think. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 14, 317–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richard, M. (1990) Propositional Attitudes: An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Rickford, J. (1992) Pidgins and creoles. In International Encyclopedia of Linguistics, Vol. 2, ed. W. Bright, pp. 224–9. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Rieber, S. (1997) Conventional implicatures as tacit performatives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 51–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rips, L. (1995) The current status of research on concept combination. Mind and Language, 10, 72–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robins, R. H., Maurer, D. W., & Ivic, P. (1997) Language. In Encyclopedia Britannica, pp. 548–71. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica
Rorty, R. (1970) Incorrigibility as the mark of the mental. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 399–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosch, E. & Mervis, C. B. (1975) Family resemblance: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573–605CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, J. (1974) Linguistic Representation. Dordrecht: Reidel
Rosenberg, J. (1993) Another look at proper names. In Philosophical Perspectives, 7: Language and Logic, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 505–30. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Ruhl, C. (1989) On Monosemy: A Study in Linguistic Semantics. Albany: State University of New York Press
Rumelhart, D. E. & McClelland, J. L. (1986) Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Russell, B. (1905) On denoting. In The Philosophy of Language, 2nd ed., ed. A. P. Martinich, pp. 203–11. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. From Mind, 14, 479–93CrossRef
Russell, B. (1910–11) Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108–28. Reprinted in his Mysticism and Logic, pp. 209–32. London: Allen and Unwin, 1917
Russell, B. (1921) The Analysis of Mind. London: Allen and Unwin
Russell, B. (1940) An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: Allen and Unwin
Russell, S. (1987) Rationality as an explanation of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 730–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind. New York: Barnes and Noble
Ryle, G. (1951) Thinking and language. From Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 25, 65–82. Reprinted in Collected Essays, vol. 2, pp. 258–71. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1971
Ryle, G. (1953) Thinking. Acta Psychologica, 9, 294–300. Reprinted in Collected Essays, vol. 2, pp. 294–300. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1971CrossRef
Ryle, G. (1955) Categories. In Logic and Language, ed. A. Flew, pp. 75–81. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Ryle, G. (1957) The theory of meaning. In British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, ed. C. A. Mace, pp. 239–64. London: Allen and Unwin
Ryle, G. (1958) A puzzling element in the notion of thinking. From Proceedings of the British Academy, 44, 129–44. Reprinted in Collected Essays, vol. 2, pp. 391–406. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1971
Ryle, G. (1962) Thinking thoughts and having concepts. From Logique et Analyse, 20, 446–50. Reprinted in Collected Essays, vol. 2, pp. 446–50. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1971
Ryle, G. (1979) On Thinking. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield
Sachs, J. S. (1967) Recognition memory for syntactic and semantic aspects of connected discourse. Perception and Psychophysics, 2, 437–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadock, J. M. (1974) Toward a Linguistic Theory of Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press
Salmon, N. (1981) Reference and Essence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Salmon, N. (1982) Assertion and incomplete definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies, 42, 37–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, N. (1986) Frege's Puzzle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Salmon, N. (1989a) Tense and singular propositions. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 331–92. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Salmon, N. (1989b) How to become a Millian heir. NoÛs, 23, 211–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, N. (1989c) Reference and information content: Names and descriptions. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Volume IV, ed. D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner, pp. 409–61. Dordrecht: Reidel
Salmon, N. (1990) A Millian heir rejects the wages of sinn. In Propositional Attitudes, ed. C. A. Anderson & J. Owens, pp. 215–57. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Samet, J. (1986) Troubles with Fodor's nativism. In Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume X: Studies in the Philosophy of Mind, ed. P. A. French, T. E. Uehling & H. K. Wettstein, pp. 575–94. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Samet, J. & Flanagan, O. (1989) Innate representation. In Rerepresentation: Readings in the Philosophy of Mental Representation, ed. S. Silver, pp. 189–210. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Saul, J. (2001) Review of Implicature: Intention, Convention, and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory by Wayne Davis. NoÛs, 35, 630–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saussure, F. (1916) Course in General Linguistics, trans. W. Baskin. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966
Schank, R. & Abelson, R. (1977) Scripts, Plans, Goals, and Understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Scheffler, I. (1955) On synonymy and indirect discourse. Philosophy of Science, 22, 39–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schein, J. D. & Stewart, D. A. (1996) Language in Motion: Exploring the Nature of Sign. Washington, DC: Gallaudet University Press
Schelling, T. (1960) The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Schiffer, S. (1972) Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Schiffer, S. (1978) The basis of reference. Erkenntnis, 13, 171–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1981) Indexicals and the theory of reference. Synthese, 49, 43–100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1982) Intention-based semantics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23, 119–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1987a) Remnants of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Schiffer, S. (1987b) The ‘Fido’-Fido theory of belief. In Philosophical Perspectives, 1: Metaphysics, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 455–80. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Schiffer, S. (1990) The mode-of-presentation problem. In Propositional Attitudes, ed. C. A. Anderson & J. Owens, pp. 249–68. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications
Schiffer, S. (1991) Does mentalese have a compositional semantics? In Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, ed. B. Loewer & G. Rey, pp. 181–99. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Schiffer, S. (1992) Belief ascription. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 499–521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1994) A paradox of meaning. NoÛs, 28, 279–324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1995) Descriptions, indexicals, and belief reports: Some dilemmas (but not the ones you expect). Mind, 104, 107–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schiffrin, D. (1994) Approaches to Discourse. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Schwarz, D. (1979) Naming and Referring: The Semantics and Pragmatics of Singular Terms. New York: De Gruyter
Searle, J. (1969) Speech-Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Searle, J. (1979) Expression and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Searle, J. (1986) Meaning, communication, and representation. In Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, ed. R. Grandy & R. Warner, pp. 209–26. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Searle, J. (1997) The explanation of cognition. In Thought and Language, ed. J. Preston, pp. 103–26. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Sellars, W. (1955) Putnam on synonymity and belief. Analysis, 15, 117–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. (1958) The Chisholm-Sellars correspondence on intentionality. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 2, ed. M. Feigl, M. Scriven & G. Maxwell, pp. 529–39. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Intentionality, Mind, and Language, ed. A. Marras, pp. 214–48. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1972
Sellars, W. (1963) Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In Science, Perception, and Reality, pp. 127–96. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Sellars, W. (1969) Language as thought and as communication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 29, 506–27. Reprinted in Essays in Philosophy and History, pp. 93–117. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1974CrossRef
Sellars, W. (1979) Naturalism and Ontology. Reseda, CA: Ridgeview
Shoemaker, S. (1984) Identity, Cause, and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Silverberg, A. (1992) Putnam on functionalism. Philosophical Studies, 67, 111–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simpson, J. M. Y. (1994) Language. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 1893–7. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Siple, P., ed. (1978) Understanding Language through Sign Language Research. New York: Academic Press
Skinner, B. F. (1938) The Organization of Behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts
Skinner, B. F. (1957) Verbal Behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts
Skulsky, H. (1986) Metaphorese. NoÛs, 20, 351–69. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth, ed. J. Garfield & M. Kiteley, pp. 582–98. New York: Paragon House, 1991CrossRef
Smart, J. J. C. (1959) Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 58, 141–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, D. V. et al. (1952) The English Language Arts. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Prepared by the Commission on the English Curriculum of the National Council of Teachers of English
Smith, D. W. (1981) Indexical sense and reference. Synthese, 49, 101–28Google Scholar
Smith, D. W. (1982) Husserl on demonstrative reference and perception. In Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science: Recent Studies in Phenomenology, ed. H. Dreyfus, pp. 193–214. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Smith, E. E. (1988) Concepts and thought. In The Psychology of Human Thought, ed. R. J. Sternberg & E. E. Smith, pp. 19–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Smith, E. E. & Medin, D. L. (1981) Categories and Concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Smith, N. V. & Wilson, D. (1979) Modern Linguistics: The Results of Chomsky's Revolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin
Smith, P. T. (1994) Thought and language. In Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. E. Asher, pp. 4610–15. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Smolensky, P. (1988) On the proper treatment of connectionsm. In Connectionism, ed. C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald, pp. 28–89. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. From Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11, 1–74CrossRef
Soames, S. (1987a) Substitutivity. In On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright, ed. J. J. Thompson, pp. 99–132. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Soames, S. (1987b) Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. Philosophical Topics, 15, 197–239CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1998) Innate knowledge. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. J. Craig, pp. 794–7. London: Routledge
Sosa, D. (1996) The import of a puzzle about belief. Philosophical Review, 105, 373–402CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (1970) Propositional attitudes de dicto and de re. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 883–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, E. (1983) Propositions and indexical attitudes. In On Believing: Epistemological and Semiotic Approaches, ed. H. Parret, pp. 316–31. New York: Walter de Gruyter
Sosa, E. (1995) De re belief, action explanations, and the essential indexical. In Modality, Morality, and Belief, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman & N. Asher, pp. 235–49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1986a) Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1986b) Loose talk. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 86, 153–71. Reprinted in Pragmatics: A Reader, ed. S. Davis, pp. 540–9. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1987) Précis of Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 679–754CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1976a) Possible worlds. NoÛs, 10, 65–75. Reprinted in The Possible and the Actual, ed. M. J. Loux, pp. 225–34. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979
Stalnaker, R. (1976b) Propositions. In Issues in the Philosophy of Language, ed. A. MacKay & D. Merrill, pp. 79–91. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Reprinted in Meaning and Truth, ed. J. Garfield and M. Kiteley, pp. 467–77. New York: Paragon, 1991
Stalnaker, R. (1998) What might nonconceptual content be? In Philosophical Issues, 9: Concepts, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 339–52. Atascadera, CA: Ridgeview
Stampe, D. W. (1968) Towards a grammar of meaning. Philosophical Review, 77, 137–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stampe, D. W. (1979) Towards a causal theory of linguistic representation. In Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, ed. P. French, T. Uehling & H. Wettstein, pp. 81–102. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
Stanley, J. (1997) Names and rigid designation. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. B. Hale & C. Wright, pp. 555–85. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Sterelny, K. (1989) Fodor's nativism. Philosophical Studies, 55, 119–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (1990) The Representational Theory of Mind. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Stich, S. (1975) Introduction: The idea of innateness. In his Innate Ideas, pp. 1–22. Berkeley: University of California Press
Stich, S. (1980) Computation without representation. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. (1983) From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Stich, S. (1986) Are belief predicates systematically ambiguous? In Belief: Form, Content, and Function, ed. R. Bogdan, pp. 119–47. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Stillings, N. A., Feinstein, M. H., Garfield, J. L., Rissland, E. L., Rosenbaum, D. A., Weisler, S. E. & Baker-Ward, L. (1987) Cognitive Science: An Introduction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Stillings, N. A., Weisler, S. E., Chase, C. H., Feinstein, M. H., Garfield, J. L. & Rissland, E. L. (1995) Cognitive Science: An Introduction, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Stocker, M. (1987) Emotional thoughts. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24, 59–69Google Scholar
Stout, G. F. (1899) A Manual of Psychology. London: W. B. Clive
Strawson, P. F. (1964) Intention and convention in speech acts. Philosophical Review, 73, 439–60. Reprinted in Pragmatics: A Reader, ed. S. Davis, pp. 290–302. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991
Strawson, P. F. (1971) Meaning and truth. In Logico-Linguistic Papers, pp. 170–89. London: Methuen
Suppes, P. (1986) The primacy of utterer's meaning. In Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends., ed. R. Grandy & R. Warner, pp. 109–29. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Taschek, W. (1995) On belief content and that-clauses. Mind and Language, 10, 274–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C. (1980) Review of Linguistic Behavior, by J. Bennett. Dialogue, 19, 290–301CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, R. (1990) Accommodation, meaning, and implicature: Interdisciplinary foundations for pragmatics. In Intentions in Communication, ed. P. R. Cohen, J. L. Morgan & M. Pollack, pp. 325–63. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Thorndike, E. L. (1911) Animal Intelligence. New York: Macmillan
Tienson, J. (1991) Introduction. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 1–29. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Titchener, E. B. (1897) Outline of Psychology, 2nd ed. New York: Macmillan
Titchener, E. B. (1909) Lectures on the Experimental Psychology of the Thought Processes. New York: Macmillan
Titchener, E. B. (1914) A Primer of Psychology. New York: Macmillan
Titchener, E. B. (1929) Systematic Psychology: Prolegomena. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Tomberlin, J. (1991) Belief, self-ascription, and ontology. In Philosophical Issues, 1: Consciousness, ed. E. Villanueva, pp. 233–59. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Tormey, A. (1971) The Concept of Expression. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Travis, C. (1997) Pragmatics. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, ed. B. Hale & C. Wright, pp. 87–107. Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Tsohatzidis, S. L. (1994) Ways of doing things with words. In Foundations of Speech Act Theory: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives, ed. S. L. Tsohatzidis, pp. 1–25. London: Routledge
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1973) Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. In Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, ed. D. Kahneman, P. Slovic & A. Tversky, pp. 3–20. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1977) The Emergence of Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Urmson, J. O. (1967) Ideas. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 4, pp. 118–21. New York: Macmillan
Urmson, J. O. (1968) Criteria of intensionality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement, 42, 107–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelder, T. (1990) Compositionality: A connectionist variation on a classical theme. Cognitive Science, 14, 355–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Gelder, T. (1991a) Classical questions, radical answers: Connectionism and the structure of mental representations. In Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. T. Horgan & J. Tienson, pp. 355–81. Dordrecht: Kluwer
van Gelder, T. (1991b) What is the “D” in “PDP”? A survey of the concept of distribution. In Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, ed. W. Ramsey, S. P. Stich & D. E. Rumelhart, pp. 33–59. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
van Heijenoort, J. (1967) Gödel's theorem. In Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. P. Edwards, vol. 3, pp. 348–57. New York: Macmillan
Vanderveken, D. (1990) Meaning and Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Vendler, Z. (1972) Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Vendler, Z. (1976) Thinking of individuals. NoÛs, 10, 35–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vendler, Z. (1977) Words in thought. Philosophical Exchange, 2, 55–66Google Scholar
Vlach, F. (1981) Speaker's meaning. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 359–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogelin, C. & Vogelin, F. (1988) Languages of the world. In Encyclopaedia Britannica, ed. R. McHenry, pp. 591–815. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica
Walker, R. (1975) Conversational implicatures. In Meaning, Reference, and Necessity: New Studies in Semantics, ed. S. Blackburn, pp. 133–81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Wallace, J. (1977) Only in the context of a sentence do words have any meaning. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 305–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warnock, G. J. (1953) Berkeley. Harmondsworth: Pelican
Warren, H. C. (1921) A History of the Association Psychology. New York: Scribners
Watson, J. B. (1924) Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviorist, 2nd ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott
Watson, J. B. (1930) Behaviorism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Weiskrantz, L., ed. (1988) Thought without Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Weiskrantz, L. (1997) Thought without language: Thought without awareness? In Thought and Language, ed. J. Preston, pp. 127–50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Wells, J. C. (1994) Esperanto. In The Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. R. Asher, pp. 1143–5. Oxford: Pergamon Press
Wettstein, H. K. (1976) Can what is asserted be a sentence? Philosophical Review, 85, 196–207. Reprinted in Has Semantics Rested on a Mistake? and Other Essays, ed. H. Wettstein, pp. 9–19. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1991
Wettstein, H. K. (1981) Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies, 40, 241–57. Reprinted in Has Semantics Rested on a Mistake? and Other Essays, ed. H. Wettstein, pp. 35–58. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1991CrossRef
Wettstein, H. K. (1986) Has semantics rested on a mistake?Journal of Philosophy, 83, 185–209CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wettstein, H. K. (1991) Has Semantics Rested on a Mistake? and Other Essays. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press
Wetzel, L. (1989) That numbers could be objects. Philosophical Studies, 56, 273–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wetzel, L. (2002) On types and words. Journal of Philosophical Research, 27, 239–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wetzel, L. (forthcoming) Of Types and Tokens. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Whorf, B. (1956) Language, Thought, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Wierzbicka, A. (1992a) Semantic primitives and semantic fields. In Frames, Fields, and Contrasts, ed. A. Lehrer & E. Kittay, pp. 209–27. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Wierzbicka, A. (1992b) The semantics of interjection. Journal of Pragmatics, 18, 159–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, D. (1971) On sentence-sense, word-sense, and difference of word-sense. Towards a philosophical theory of dictionaries. In Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguistics, and Psychology, ed. D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits, pp. 14–34. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Wilbur, R. B. (1987) American Sign Language: Linguistic and Applied Dimensions. Boston: Little, Brown
Williams, C. J. F. (1991) You and she. Analysis, 51, 143–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, D. & Sperber, D. (1981) On Grice's theory of conversation. In Conversation and Discourse, ed. P. Werth, pp. 155–78. New York: St. Martin's Press
Wilson, N. L. (1970) Grice on meaning: The ultimate counterexample. NoÛs, 4, 295–302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1922) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1972
Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Woodfield, A. (1982) On specifying the contents of thought. In Thought and Object, ed. A. Woodfield, pp. 259–97. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Woodfield, A. (1991) Conceptions. Mind, 100, 547–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodfield, A. (1997) Social externalism and conceptual diversity. In Thought and Language, ed. J. Preston, pp. 77–102. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Woodward, J. (1978) Historical bases of American Sign Language. In Understanding Language through Sign Language Research, ed. P. Siple, pp. 333–47. New York: Academic Press
Woodworth, R. S. (1921) Psychology: A Study of Mental Life. New York: Holt
Woodworth, R. S. & Sells, S. B. (1935) An atmosphere effect in syllogistic reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 18, 451–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wreen, M. (1998) Proper names and the necessity of identity statements. Synthese, 114, 319–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, R. A. (1975) Meaningnn and conversational implicature. In Syntax and Semantics, 3: Speech Acts, ed. P. Cole & J. L. Morgan, pp. 363–82. New York: Academic Press
Wundt, W. (1911) An Introduction to Psychology, trans. R. Pintner. London: George Allen, 1912
Yagisawa, T. (1984) The pseudo-Mates argument. Philosophical Review, 93, 407–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yagisawa, T. (1993) A semantic solution to Frege's puzzle. In Philosophical Perspectives, 7: Language and Logic, ed. J. Tomberlin, pp. 135–54. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview
Yagisawa, T. (1998) Naming and its place in reference. Lingua e Stile, 33, 445–58Google Scholar
Yoder, C. H., Suydam, F. H. & Snavely, F. A. (1975) Chemistry. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich
Yolton, J. W. (1956) John Locke and the Way of Ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Yourgrau, P., ed. (1990) Demonstratives. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Yu, P. (1979) On the Gricean program about meaning. Linguistics and Philosophy, 3, 273–388CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zadrozny, W. (1994) From compositional to systematic semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 17, 329–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalta, E. N. (1989) Singular propositions, abstract constituents, and propositional attitudes. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein, pp. 455–78. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Ziff, P. (1960) Semantic Analysis. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Ziff, P. (1964) On understanding “understanding utterances.” In The Structure of Language, ed. J. Fodor & J. J. Katz, pp. 390–9. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Ziff, P. (1967) On H. P. Grice's account of meaning. Analysis, 28, 1–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Wayne A. Davis, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: Meaning, Expression and Thought
  • Online publication: 20 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498763.025
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Wayne A. Davis, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: Meaning, Expression and Thought
  • Online publication: 20 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498763.025
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Wayne A. Davis, Georgetown University, Washington DC
  • Book: Meaning, Expression and Thought
  • Online publication: 20 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498763.025
Available formats
×