Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T18:32:45.094Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Selected Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2015

Maurice A. Finocchiaro
Affiliation:
University of Nevada, Las Vegas
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Arguments about Arguments
Systematic, Critical, and Historical Essays In Logical Theory
, pp. 431 - 452
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adamson, W. L. 1980. Hegemony and Revolution. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Agassi, J. 1963. Towards an Historiography of Science. The Hague: MoutonGoogle Scholar
Agassi, J. 1968. The Continuing Revolution. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Agassi, J. 1971. Faraday as a Natural Philosopher. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Agassi, J., and Jarvie, I. C., eds. 1987. Rationality. Dordrecht: Martinus NijoffGoogle Scholar
Agazzi, E. 1981. “What Have the History and Philosophy of Science to Do for One Another?” In Hintikka et al. 1981, 2: 241–48
Angeles, P. A. 1981. Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Barnes & NobleGoogle Scholar
Angell, R. B. 1964. Reasoning and Logic. New York: AppletonGoogle Scholar
Anselm, Saint. 1958. Proslogium; Monologium. Trans. S. N. Deane. La Salle, Ill.: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1952. The Summa Theologica. 2 vols. Chicago: Encyclopedia BritannicaGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, . 1952. The Works of Aristotle. 2 vols. Chicago: Encyclopedia BritannicaGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A., and Nicole, P. 1717. Logic; or, the Art of Thinking. Trans. G. Ozell. LondonGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A., and Nicole, P.. 1850. Logic, or the Art of Thinking: Being the Port-Royal Logic. Trans. T. S. Baynes. EdinburghGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A., and Nicole, P.. 1964. The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic. Trans. J. Dickoff and P. James. Indianapolis: Bobbs-MerrillGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A., and Nicole, P.. 1965. La Logique ou l'Art de Penser. Critical edition by P. Clair and F. Girbal. Paris: Presses Universitaires de FranceGoogle Scholar
Arnauld, A., and Nicole, P.. 1996. Logic or the Art of Thinking. Trans. J. V. Buroker. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asquith, P. D., and Kyburg, H. E., eds. 1978. Current Research in Philosophy of Science. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science AssociationGoogle Scholar
Bailin, S. 1988. Achieving Extraordinary Ends. Dordrecht: KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M. 1982. “A Normative-Pragmatical Foundation of the Rules of Some Systems of Formal3 Dialectics.” In Barth and Martens 1982, 159–70
Barth, E. M. 1985a. “A New Field: Empirical Logic.” Synthese 63: 375–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M. 1985b. “Toward a Praxis-Oriented Theory of Argumentation.” In Dialogue: An Interdisciplinary Approach, ed. Dascal, M., 73–86. Amsterdam: John BenjaminsCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M. 1987. “Logic to Some Purpose: Theses against the Deductive-Nomological Paradigm in the Science of Logic.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 33–45
Barth, E. M. 2002. “A Framework for Intersubjective Accountability: Dialogical Logic.” In Gabbay et al. 2002, 225–93
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W.. 1982. From Axiom to Dialogue. Berlin: Walter de GruyterCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W., eds. 1992. Logic and Political Culture. Amsterdam: Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and SciencesGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M., and Martens, J. L., eds. 1982. Argumentation: Approaches to Theory Formation. Amsterdam: John BenjaminsCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barth, E. M., Vandormael, J., and Vandamme, F., eds. 1992. From an Empirical Point of View: The Empirical Turn in Logic. Ghent, Belgium: Communication and CognitionGoogle Scholar
Barth, K. 1963. God in Action. Manhasset, N.Y. : Round Table PressGoogle Scholar
Barth, K. 1964. God Here and Now. Trans. P. M. van Buren. New York: Harper & RowGoogle Scholar
Bartley, W. W. III. 1962. The Retreat to Commitment. New York: Alfred A. KnopfGoogle Scholar
Bartley, W. W., III. 1964. “Rationality versus the Theory of Rationality.” In The Critical Approach to Science and Philosophy, ed. Bunge, M., 3–31. New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Bartley, W. W. III. 1982. “Critical Study: The Philosophy of Karl Popper.” Philosophia 11: 121–221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartley, W. W. III. 1984. The Retreat to Commitment. 2nd ed. La Salle, Ill.: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Bartley, W. W., III. 1987. “Theories of Rationality.” In Evolutionary Epistemology, Theory of Rationality, and the Sociology of Knowledge, ed. Radnitsky, G. and Bartley, W. W. III, 205–16. La Salle, Ill.: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Battersby, M. E. 1989. “Critical Thinking as Applied Epistemology.” Informal Logic 11: 91–100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baynes, T. S., ed. and trans. 1850. Logic, or the Art of Thinking: Being the Port-Royal Logic. EdinburghGoogle Scholar
Beardsley, M. C. 1966. Thinking Straight. 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Bechler, Z. 1981. “What Have They Done to Kuhn?” In Hintikka et al. 1981, 1: 63–86
Bell, A. E. 1947. Christian Huygens and the Development of Science in the Seventeenth Century. London: Edward ArnoldGoogle Scholar
Bencivenga, E. 1979. “On Good and Bad Arguments.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 247–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkeley, G. 1929. Essay, Principles, Dialogues. New York: Scribner'sGoogle Scholar
Beth, E. W., and Piaget, J.. 1966. Mathematical Epistemology and Psychology. Dordrecht: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Beth, E. W.., eds. 1962. Implication, Formalisation, et Logique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de FranceGoogle Scholar
Black, M. 1952. Critical Thinking. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Blair, J. A. 1995. “Premise Adequacy.” In Eemeren et al. 1995a, 191–202
Blair, J. A. 1998. “The Limits of the Dialogue Model of Argument.” In Hansen et al. 1998
Blair, J. A., and Johnson, R. H., eds. 1980. Informal Logic: The First International Symposium. Inverness, Calif.: EdgepressGoogle Scholar
Blair, J. A., and Johnson, R. H.. 1987. “Argumentation as Dialectical.” Argumentation 1: 41–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bochenski, I. M. 1961. A History of Formal Logic. Trans. I. Thomas. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Bogazzi, R. 1977. “Il Kosmotheoros di Christiaan Huygens.” Physis 19: 87–109Google Scholar
Boltzmann, L. 1964. Lectures on Gas Theory. Trans. S. G. Brush. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Boltzmann, L. 1974. Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems. Trans. P. Foulkes. Ed. McGuinness, B.. Dordrecht: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Bos, H. J. M., Rudwick, M. J. S., Snelders, H. A. M., and Visser, R. P. W., eds. 1980. Studies on Christiaan Huygens. Lisse: Swets & ZeitlingerGoogle Scholar
Braine, M. S. 1978. “On the Relation between the Natural Logic of Reasoning and Standard Logic.” Psychological Review 85: 1–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. I. 1975. “Paradigmatic Propositions.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 86–90Google Scholar
Brown, H. I. 1977. Perception, Theory and Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: Precedent PublishingGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. I. 1979. Perception, Theory and Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. I. 1987. Observation and Rationality. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. I. 1989. Rationality. London: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Brush, S. G. 1964. “Introduction” to Boltzmann 1964
Brush, S. G. 1976. The Kind of Motion We Call Heat. 2 vols. New York: North-HollandGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, G. 1970a. “Gravity and Intelligibility: Newton to Kant.” In The Methodological Heritage of Newton, ed. Butts, R. E. and Davis, J. W., 74–102. Toronto: University of Toronto PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, G. 1970b. “History of Science and Criteria of Choice.” In Historical and Philosophical Perspectives on Science, ed. Stuewer, R. H., 204–30. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, G. 1973. “Explanation and Gravity.” In Changing Perspectives in the History of Science, ed. Teich, M. and Young, R., 167–203. Dordrecht: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Buroker, J. V. 1993. “The Port-Royal Semantics of Terms.” Synthese 96: 455–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buroker, J. V. 1994. “Judgment and Predication in the Port-Royal Logic.” In The Great Arnauld and Some of His Philosophical Correspondents, ed. Kremer, E. J., 3–27. Toronto: University of Toronto PressGoogle Scholar
Buroker, J. V., ed. and trans. 1996. Logic or the Art of Thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Byrne, R. 1983. “Protocol Analysis in Problem Solving.” In Evans 1983c, 227–49
Carnap, R. 1950. Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Cattani, A. 2001. Botta e risposta: L'arte della replica. Bologna: Il MulinoGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. M. 1970. “On the Nature of Empirical Evidence.” In Experience and Theory, ed. Foster, L. and Swanson, J. L., 103–34. London: DuckworthGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1959. Review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior. Language 35: 26–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clair, P., and Girbal, F., eds. 1965. La Logique ou l'Art de Penser. Paris: Presses Universitaires de FranceGoogle Scholar
Clark, M. 1975. “The Patron Saint of the Left.” Times Literary Supplement (London), 31 October, no. 3842, p. 1280Google Scholar
Cohen, I. B. 1966. “Hypotheses in Newton's Philosophy.” Physis 8: 163–84Google Scholar
Cohen, I. B. 1971. Introduction to Newton's Principia. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1966. The Diversity of Meaning. 2nd ed. London: Methuen
Cohen, L. J. 1970. The Implications of Induction. London: MethuenGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1977. The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: ClarendonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1979. “On the Psychology of Prediction: Whose Is the Fallacy?Cognition 7: 385–407CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1980. “Whose Is the Fallacy? A Rejoinder to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky.” Cognition 8: 89–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1981a. “Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 317–31 and 359–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1981b. “Subjective Probability and the Paradox of the Gatecrasher.” Arizona State Law Journal, pp. 627–34Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1982. “Are People Programmed to Commit Fallacies?Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 12: 251–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1986. The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy. Oxford: ClarendonGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. 1991. “Some Comments by L. J. C.” In Eells and Maruszewski 1991, 319–42
Cohen, M. R., and Nagel, E.. 1934. An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method. New York: Harcourt, BraceGoogle Scholar
Colodny, R. G., ed. 1962. Frontiers of Science and Philosophy. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M. 1968. Introduction to Logic. 3rd ed. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M. 1972. Introduction to Logic. 4th ed. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M. 1986a. Informal Logic. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M. 1986b. Introduction to Logic. 7th ed. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M., and Cohen, C.. 1990. Introduction to Logic. 8th ed. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Copi, I. M., and Cohen, C.. 1994. Introduction to Logic. 9th ed. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Crosland, M. 1973. “Lavoisier's Theory of Acidity.” Isis 64: 306–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummings, L. 2002. “Hilary Putnam's Dialectical Thinking.” Argumentation 16: 197–229CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Czapinski, J. 1980. “Positive-Negative Asymmetry on the Group Level.” Polish Psychological Bulletin 11: 203–5Google Scholar
Czapinski, J. 1982. “Positive-Negative Asymmetry at Group and Individual Level.” Polish Psychological Bulletin 13: 153–58Google Scholar
Czapinski, J. 1986. “Informativeness of Evaluations in Interpersonal Communications.” Polish Psychological Bulletin 17: 155–64Google Scholar
Dahl, R. A. 1956. A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1968. “The Logical Form of Action Sentences.” In The Logic of Decision and Action, ed. Rescher, N.. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
Del Noce, A. 1978. Il suicidio della rivoluzione. Milan: RusconiGoogle Scholar
Descartes, R. 1644. Principia Philosophiae. LeidenGoogle Scholar
Dickoff, J., and James, P., eds. and trans. 1964. The Art of Thinking: Port-Royal Logic. Indianapolis: Bobbs-MerrillGoogle Scholar
Dijksterhuis, E. J. 1961. The Mechanization of the World Picture. Trans. C. Dikshoorn. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Doss, S. 1985. “Three Steps toward a Theory of Informal Logic.” Informal Logic 7: 127–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drake, S. 1978. Galileo at Work. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Eddington, A. S. 1930. The Nature of the Physical World. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Eells, E., and Maruszewski, T., eds. 1991. Probability and Rationality. Atlanta: RodopiGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H. van. 1987. “For Reason's Sake: Maximal Argumentative Analysis of Discourse.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 201–15
Eemeren, F. H., ed. 2002. Advances in Pragma-Dialectics. Newport News, Va.: ValeGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Blair, J. A., Willard, C. A., and Henkemans, A. F. Snoeck, eds. 2003. Proceedings of the Fifth Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., and Grootendorst, R.. 1984. Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions. Dordrecht: ForisCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., and Grootendorst, R.. 1992. Argumentation, Communication, and Fallacies. Hillsdale, N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., and Grootendorst, R., eds. 1994. Studies in Pragma-Dialectics. Amsterdam: International Centre for the Study of ArgumentationGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Blair, J. A., and Willard, C. A., eds. 1987. Argumentation across the Lines of Discipline: Proceedings of the Conference on Argumentation 1986. Dordrecht: ForisCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Blair, J. A., and Willard, C. A., eds. 1992. Argumentation Illuminated. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Blair, J. A., and Willard, C. A., eds. 1995a. Analysis and Evaluation: Proceedings of the Third ISSA Conference on Argumentation, vol. 2. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Blair, J. A., and Willard, C. A., eds. 1995b. Perspectives and Approaches: Proceedings of the Third ISSA Conference on Argumentation, vol. 1. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Blair, J. A., and Willard, C. A., eds. 1999. Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Jackson, S., and Jacobs, S.. 1993. Reconstructing Argumentative Discourse. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama PressGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., and Kruiger, T.. 1984. The Study of Argumentation. New York: IrvingtonGoogle Scholar
Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., and Henkemans, A. F. Snoeck, eds. 1996. Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory. Mahwah, N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Einstein, A. 1934. “On the Method of Theoretical Physics.” In idem, The World As I See It. New York: Covici Friede
Einstein, A., and Infeld, L.. 1938. The Evolution of Physics. New York: Simon and SchusterGoogle Scholar
Elzinga, A. 1971. “Huygens' Theory of Research and Descartes' Theory of Knowledge, I.” Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 2: 174–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elzinga, A. 1972a. “Huygens' Theory of Research and Descartes' Theory of Knowledge, II.” Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 3: 9–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elzinga, A. 1972b. On a Research Program in Early Modern Physics. New York: HumanitiesGoogle Scholar
Engel, S. M. 1976. With Good Reason. New York: St. Martin'sGoogle Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1962. “A Concept of Critical Thinking.” Harvard Educational Review 32: 81–111Google Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1968. “Enumerative Induction and Best Explanation.” Journal of Philosophy 65: 523–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1969. Ordinary Logic. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1976. “An Alternative to Piaget's Conceptualization of Logical Competence.” Child Development 17: 903–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1980. “A Conception of Rational Thinking.” In Philosophy of Education 1979, ed. Coombs, J. R., 3–30. Normal, Ill.: Philosophy of Education SocietyGoogle Scholar
Ennis, R. H. 1981. “Rational Thinking and Educational Practice.” In Philosophy and Education, ed. Soltis, J. F., 143–83. Chicago: National Society for the Study of EducationGoogle Scholar
Epstein, R. L. 2002. Critical Thinking. 2nd ed. Belmont, Calif.: WadsworthGoogle Scholar
Evans, J.St., B. T. 1972a. “Interpretation and ‘Matching Bias’ in a Reasoning Task.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 24: 193–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J.St., B. T. 1972b. “Reasoning with Negatives.” British Journal of Psychology 63: 213–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, J.St., B. T. 1982. The Psychology of Deductive Reasoning. London: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Evans, J. St. B. T. 1983a. “Introduction.” In Evans 1983c, 1–15
Evans, J. St. B. T. 1983b. “Selective Processes in Reasoning.” In Evans 1983c, 135–63
Evans, J.St., B. T., ed. 1983c. Thinking and Reasoning. London: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Falmagne, R. J., ed. 1975. Reasoning: Representation and Process. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Fearnside, W. W., and Holther, W. B.. 1959. Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H., and Maxwell, G., eds. 1962. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 3. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H., and Scriven, M., eds. 1956. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H., Scriven, M., and Maxwell, G., eds. 1958. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 2. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Femia, J. V. 1981. Gramsci's Political Thought. Oxford: ClarendonGoogle Scholar
Feuer, L. S. 1974. Einstein and the Generations of Science. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. 1962a. “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism.” In Feigl and Maxwell 1962, 28–97
Feyerabend, P. K. 1962b. “Problems of Microphysics.” In Colodny 1962, 189–283
Feyerabend, P. K. 1963. “How to Be a Good Empiricist.” In Philosophy of Science: The Delaware Seminar, vol. 1, ed. Baumrin, B., 3–39. New York: InterscienceGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. 1965. “Problems of Empiricism.” In Beyond the Edge of Certainty, ed. Colodny, R., 145–260. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. 1970a. “Against Method.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 4, ed. Radner, M. and Vinokur, S., 17–130. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. 1970b. “Consolations for the Specialist.” In Lakatos and Musgrave 1970, 197–230
Feyerabend, P. K. 1970c. “Problems of Empiricism, Part II.” In The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories, ed. Colodny, R., 275–353. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. 1975. Against Method. London: NLBGoogle Scholar
Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., and Sands, M.. 1963. The Feynman Lectures on Physics, vol. 1: Mainly Mechanics, Radiation, and Heat. Reading, Mass.: Addison-WesleyGoogle Scholar
Findlay, J. 1964. Hegel: A Re-examination. New York: HumanitiesCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1964. “An Analysis of Heisenberg's Attempt to Compare Quantum Mechanics and Thermodynamics.” B. S. thesis, Department of Humanities, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1969. “The Problem of Explanation in Historiography of Science.” Ph. D. dissertation, Department of Philosophy, University of California-Berkeley
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1973a. Essay-Review of Lakatos's Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 3: 357–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1973b. “Galileo's Space-Proportionality Argument: A Role for Logic in Historiography.” Physis 15: 65–72Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1973c. History of Science as Explanation. Detroit: Wayne State University PressGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1974a. “The Concept of ad Hominem Argument in Galileo and Locke.” Philosophical Forum 5: 394–404Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1974b. “Newton's Third Rule of Philosophizing: A Role for Logic in Historiography.” Isis 65: 66–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1977a. “Galileo's Philosophy of Science, Part I: A Case Study of the Role of Judgment and of Philosophizing in Science.” Scientia 112: 95–118Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1977b. “Logic and Rhetoric in Lavosier's Sealed Note: Toward a Rhetoric of Science.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 10: 111–122Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1978a. Review of Brown's Perception, Theory and Commitment. Isis 69: 602–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1978b. “Rhetoric and Scientific Rationality.” In PSA 1978, ed. Hacking, I. and Asquith, P. D., 235–46. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science AssociationGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1979a. “Methodological Criticism and Critical Methodology.” Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 10: 363–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1979b. “The Psychological Explanation of Reasoning: Logical and Methodological Problems.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9: 277–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1980a. “The Concept of Judgment and Huygens' Theory of Gravity.” Epistemologia 3: 185–218Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1980b. Galileo and the Art of Reasoning: Rhetorical Foundations of Logic and Scientific Method. Boston: ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1980c. Review of Johnstone's Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument. Review of Metaphysics 34: 143–44Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1981. “Fallacies and the Evaluation of Reasoning.” American Philosophical Quarterly 18: 13–22Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1983. “Judgment and Argument in The Communist Manifesto.” Philosophical Forum 14: 135–56Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1984a. “Croce as Seen in a Recent Work on Gramsci.” Rivista di studi crociani 21: 139–54Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1984b. “Informal Logic and the Theory of Reasoning.” Informal Logic 6(2): 3–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1984c. “The Labyrinth of Gramscian Studies and Femia's Contribution.” Inquiry 27: 291–310CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1986a. “Marxism, Science, and Religion in Gramsci: Recent Trends in Italian Scholarship.” Philosophical Forum 17: 127–55Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1986b. “The Methodological Background to Galileo's Trial.” In Reinterpreting Galileo, ed. Wallace, W. A., 241–72. Washington: Catholic University of America PressGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1987a. “An Historical Approach to the Study of Argumentation.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 81–91
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1987b. Review of D. N. Walton's Arguer's Position. Philosophy and Rhetoric 20: 63–65Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1987c. “Six Types of Fallaciousness: Toward a Realistic Theory of Logical Criticism.” Argumentation 1: 263–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1988a. “Empiricism, Judgment, and Argument: Toward an Informal Logic of Science.” Argumentation 2: 313–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1988b. “Galileo's Copernicanism and the Acceptability of Guiding Assumptions.” In Scrutinizing Science, ed. Donovan, A., Laudan, L., and Laudan, R., 49–67. Dordrecht: KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1988c. Gramsci and the History of Dialectical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1988d. Gramsci critico e la critica. Rome: Armando EditoreGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A., ed. and trans. 1989a. The Galileo Affair: A Documentary History. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1989b. “Methodological Problems in Empirical Logic.” Communication and Cognition 22: 313–35Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1989c. “Siegel on Critical Thinking.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19: 483–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1989d. “Fetishism, Argument, and Judgment in Capital.” Studies in Soviet Thought 38: 237–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1990a. “Cognitive Asymmetries and Argumentation Theory.” Paper presented at the Second International Conference on Argumentation, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1990b. “Critical Thinking and Thinking Critically.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 20: 462–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1991. “Induction and Intuition in the Normative Study of Reasoning.” In Eells and Maruszewski 1991, 81–95
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1992a. “Asymmetries in Argumentation and Evaluation.” In Eemeren et al. 1992, 62–72
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1992b. “Logic, Politics, and Gramsci.” In Barth and Krabbe 1992, 25–43
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1994a. “The Positive versus the Negative Evaluation of Arguments.” In Johnson and Blair 1994, 21–35
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1994b. “Two Empirical Approaches to the Study of Reasoning.” Informal Logic 16: 1–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1995a. “Criticism, Reasoning and Judgment in Science.” In Critical Rationalism, Metaphysics and Science, ed. Jarvie, I. C. and Laor, N. 1: 169–91. Boston: KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1995b. “The Dialectical Approach to Interpretation and Evaluation.” In Eemeren et al. 1995b, 183–95
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1995c. “Empirische Ansätze zur Erforshung des Argumentierens: Experiment, Induktion, historische Textanalyse.” Zeitschrift für Semiotik 17: 257–83Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1996a. “Critical Thinking, Critical Reasoning, and Methodological Reflection.” Inquiry: Critical Thinking across the Disciplines 15: 66–79Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1996b. “Reasoning about Reasoning.” In Practical Reasoning, ed. Gabbay, D. M. and Ohlbach, H. J., 167–77. New York: SpringerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A., ed. and trans. 1997a. Galileo on the World Systems: A New Abridged Translation and Guide. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1997b. “The Port-Royal Logic's Theory of Argument.” Argumentation 11: 393–410CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 1999. “A Critique of the Dialectical Approach, Part II.” In Eemeren et al. 1999, 195–99
Finocchiaro, M. A. 2001. “Valid Ad Hominem Arguments in Philosophy: Johnstone's Metaphilosophical Informal Logic.” Informal Logic 21: 11–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 2002. “Elementary Logic from an Advanced Standpoint.” Informal Logic, Teaching Supplement, vol. 22, no. 2, summer, pp. TS9–TS22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. A. 2003. “Dialectics, Evaluation, and Argument.” Informal Logic 23: 19–49Google Scholar
Fisher, A. 1988. The Logic of Real Arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Fisher, A. 1992. “Critical Study: Dialectics and the Macrostructure of Arguments by James B. Freeman.” Informal Logic 14: 193–204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, A., and Scriven, M.. 1997. Critical Thinking: Its Definition and Assessment. Point Reyes, Calif.: Edgepress; Norwich, U.K. : Centre for Research in Critical ThinkingGoogle Scholar
Flew, A., and MacIntyre, A., eds. 1955. New Essays in Philosophical Theology. London: SCMGoogle Scholar
Fogelin, R. J. 1978. Understanding Arguments: An Introduction to Informal Logic. New York: Harcourt Brace JovanovichGoogle Scholar
Freeman, J. B. 1991. Dialectics and the Macrostructure of Arguments. New York: ForisCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frisch, O. R. 1979. What Little I Remember. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Gabbay, D. V., Johnson, R. H., Holbach, H. J., and Woods, J., eds. 2002. Handbook of the Logic of Argument and Inference. Amsterdam: ElsevierGoogle Scholar
Galilei, G. 1632. Dialogo. In Galilei 1890–1909, vol. 7
Galilei, G. 1890–1909. Le Opere di Galileo Galilei. 20 vols. National Edition by Favaro, A.. Florence: Barbèra. Rpt. in 1929–1939 and 1968Google Scholar
Galilei, G. 1914. Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences. Trans. H. Crew and A. De Salvio. Rpt., New York: DoverGoogle Scholar
Galilei, G. 1953. Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems. Trans. S. Drake. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Galilei, G. 1966. The Controversy on the Comets of 1618. Trans. S. Drake and C. D. O'Malley. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania PressGoogle Scholar
Galilei, G. 1967. Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems. Trans. S. Drake. 2nd rev. ed. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Galilei, G. 1974. Two New Sciences. Trans. S. Drake. Madison: University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar
George, R. 1983. “A Postscript on Fallacies.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 12: 319–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Germino, D. 1990. Antonio Gramsci: Architect of a New Politics. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University PressGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. Jr. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis 23: 121–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glaser, E. M. 1941. An Experiment in the Development of Critical Thinking. New York: Bureau of Publications, Teachers College, Columbia UniversityGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 1994. “Argumentation and Social Epistemology.” Journal of Philosophy 94: 27–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: ClarendonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goosens, W. K. 1980. “Galileo's Response to the Tower Argument.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 11: 215–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Govier, T. 1982. “Who Says There Are No Fallacies?Informal Logic Newsletter, vol. , no. ⅰ, pp. 2–10Google Scholar
Govier, T. 1985. “Logical Analogies.” Informal Logic 7: 27–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Govier, T. 1989. “Critical Thinking as Argument Analysis.” Argumentation 3: 115–26Google Scholar
Govier, T. 1998. “Arguing Forever?” In Hansen et al. 1998
Govier, T. 1999a. The Philosophy of Argument. Newport News, Va.: ValeGoogle Scholar
Govier, T. 1999b. “Progress and Regress on the Dialectical Tier.” In Govier 1999a, 223–40
Govier, T. 2000. “Critical Review: Johnson's Manifest Rationality.” Informal Logic 20: 281–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1958. Scritti giovanili (1914–1918). Turin: EinaudiGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1965. Lettere dal carcere. Ed. Caprioglio, S. and Fubini, E.. Turin: EinaudiGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Ed. and trans. Hoare, Q. and Nowell-Smith, G.. New York: InternationalGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1973. Letters from Prison. Ed. and trans. Lawner, L.. New York: HarperGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1975. Quaderni del carcere. 4 vols. Critical edition by Gerratana, V.. Turin: EinaudiGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1982. La città futura (1917–1918). Ed. Caprioglio, S.. Turin: EinaudiGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1985. Selections from Cultural Writings. Ed. Forgacs, D. and Nowell-Smith, G., trans. W. Boelhower. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Gramsci, A. 1988. A Gramsci Reader. Ed. Forgacs, D.. New York: SchockenGoogle Scholar
Griggs, R. A. 1983. “The Role of Problem Content in the Selection Task and in the THOG Problem.” In Evans 1983c, 16–43
Groarke, L. 2002. “Johnson on the Metaphysics of Argument.” Argumentation 16: 277–286CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grootendorst, R. 1987. “Some Fallacies about Fallacies.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 331–42
Guerlac, H. 1961. Lavoisier – the Crucial Year. Ithaca: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. 1975. The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamblin, C. L. 1970. Fallacies. London: Methuen. Rpt., Newport News, Va.: Vale, 1986Google Scholar
Hansen, H. V. 2002. “An Exploration of Johnson's Sense of ‘Argument.’Argumentation 16: 263–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansen, H. V., Pinto, R. C., Tindale, C. W., Blair, J. A., and Johnson, R. H., eds. 2002. Argumentation and Its Applications. Windsor: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. CD-ROM. ISBN 0-9683461-2-XGoogle Scholar
Hansen, H. V., Tindale, C. W., and Colman, A. V., eds. 1998. Argumentation and Rhetoric. St. Catharines: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. CD-ROM. ISBN 0-9683461-0-3Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1984. “Logic and Reasoning.” Synthese 60: 107–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1986. Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Heisenberg, W. 1955. “The Development of the Interpretation of the Quantum Theory.” In Niels Bohr and the Development of Physics, ed. Pauli, W., 12–29. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Henle, M. 1962. “On the Relation between Logic and Thinking.” Psychological Review 69: 376–82CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henle, M. 1978. “Foreword.” In Revlin and Mayer 1978, pp. ⅹⅲ–ⅹⅷ
Henle, M. 1981. “Another Vote for Rationality.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 339CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hiebert, E. N. 1981. “Boltzmann's Conception of Theory Construction.” In Hintikka et al. 1981, 2: 175–98
Hintikka, J. 1974. “Quantifiers vs. Quantification Theory.” Linguistic Inquiry 5: 153–77Google Scholar
Hintikka, J., Gruender, D., and Agazzi, E., eds. 1981. Theory Change, Ancient Axiomatics, and Galileo's Methodology. 2 vols. Dordrecht: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, D. 1987. “Enthymematic Arguments.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 289–98
Hitchcock, D. 1989. “A General Theory of Good Inference?” Paper presented at the Third International Symposium on Informal Logic, University of Windsor, Canada
Hitchcock, D. 1994. “Validity in Conductive Arguments.” In Johnson and Blair 1994, 58–66
Hitchcock, D. 2002a. “The Practice of Argumentative Discussion.” Argumentation 16: 287–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, D. 2002b. “Sampling Scholarly Arguments: A Test of a Theory of Good Inference.” In Hansen et al. 2002
Hockenos, W. J. 1968. “An Examination of Reductio ad Absurdum and Argumentum ad Hominem Arguments in the Philosophies of Gilbert Ryle and Henry W. Johnstone, Jr.” Ph. D. dissertation, Boston University
Holton, G. 1973. Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Holton, G. 1978. The Scientific Imagination. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1911. Treatise of Human Nature. London: J. M. Dent & SonsGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1935. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Ed. N. K. Smith. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1955. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. New York: Liberal ArtsGoogle Scholar
Huygens, C. 1690. Traité de la Lumiere avec un Discours de la Cause de la Pesanteur. Leiden. Facsimile reprint, London: Dawson, 1966Google Scholar
Ingard, U., and Kraushaar, W. L.. 1960. Introduction to Mechanics, Matter, and Waves.Reading, Mass.: Addison-WesleyGoogle Scholar
Inhelder, B., and Piaget, J.. 1958. The Growth of Logical Thinking. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Jardine, N. 1976. “Galileo's Road to Truth and Demonstrative Regress.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 7: 277–318CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. 1967. Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 1981a. “Charity Begins at Home.” Informal Logic Newsletter, vol. , no. 3, pp. 4–9Google Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 1981b. “Toulmin's Bold Experiment.” Informal Logic Newsletter, vol. , no. 2, pp. 16–27; and vol. , no. 3, pp. 13–19Google Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 1987. “Logic Naturalized.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 47–56
Johnson, R. H. 1989. “Massey on Fallacy and Informal Logic.” Synthese 80: 407–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 1996. The Rise of Informal Logic. Newport News, Va.: ValeGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 1998. “Response to Govier's ‘Arguing Forever? Or: Two Tiers of Argument Appraisal.’” In Hansen et al. 1998
Johnson, R. H. 2000a. Manifest Rationality: A Pragmatic Theory of Argument. Mahwah, N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 2000b. “More on Arguers and Dialectical Obligations.” In Tindale et al. 2000
Johnson, R. H. 2002a. “Manifest Rationality Reconsidered.” Argumentation 16: 311–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R. H. 2002b. “More on Arguers and Their Dialectical Obligations.” In Hansen et al. 2002
Johnson, R. H. 2003. “The Dialectical Tier Revisited.” In Eemeren et al. 2003, 561–66
Johnson, R. H., and J. A. Blair. 1980. “The Recent Development of Informal Logic.” In Blair and Johnson 1980, 3–28
Johnson, R. H., and Blair, J. A.. 1985. “Informal Logic: The Past Five Years 1978–1983.” American Philosophical Quarterly 22: 181–96Google Scholar
Johnson, R. H., and Blair, J. A., eds. 1994. New Essays in Informal Logic. Windsor, Ontario: Informal LogicGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. 1983a. Mental Models. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. 1983b. “Thinking as a Skill.” In Evans 1983c, 164–96
Johnson-Laird, P. N., and Wason, P. C., eds. 1977. Thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, H. W. Jr. 1952. “Philosophy and Argumentum ad Hominem.” Journal of Philosophy 49: 489–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, H. W. Jr. 1959. Philosophy and Argument. University Park: Pennsylvania State University PressGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, H. W. Jr. 1978. Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument. University Park, Pa.: Dialogue Press of Man & WorldGoogle Scholar
Johnstone, H. W. Jr. 1989. “Argumentation and Formal Logic in Philosophy.” Argumentation 3: 5–15Google Scholar
Johnstone, H. W. Jr. 1997. “A Bibliography, 1948–1997.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 31: 6–19Google Scholar
Jonsen, A., and Toulmin, S. E.. 1988. The Abuse of Casuistry. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Kahane, H. 1971. Logic and Contemporary Rhetoric. Belmont, Calif.: WadsworthGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A., eds. 1982. Judgment under Uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalish, D., and Montague, R.. 1964. Logic. New York: Harcourt, Brace & WorldGoogle Scholar
Kalish, D., Montague, R., and Mar, G.. 1980. Logic. 2nd ed. New York: Harcourt Brace JovanovichGoogle Scholar
Kanouse, D. E., and L. R. Hanson, Jr. 1971. “Negativity in Evaluations.” In Attribution: Perceiving the Causes of Behavior, ed. Jones, E.., 47–62. Morristown, N.J. : General LearningGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. 1950. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. New York: Liberal ArtsGoogle Scholar
Kaufmann, W. 1951. “The Hegel Myth and Its Method.” Philosophical Review 60: 459–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitchener, K. S. 1983a. “Cognition, Metacognition, and Epistemic Cognition.” Human Development 26: 222–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitchener, K. S. 1983b. “Educational Goals and Reflective Thinking.” Educational Forum 48(1): 7–95Google Scholar
Kitchener, K. S., and K. W. Fisher. 1990. “A Skill Approach to the Development of Reflective Thinking.” In Developmental Perspectives on Teaching and Learning Thinking Skills, ed. Kuhn, D., 48–62. Basel, Switzerland: KargerGoogle Scholar
Kittel, C., Knight, W. D., and Ruderman, M. A.. 1962. Mechanics: Berkeley Physics Course, vol. 1. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Klayman, J., and Ha, Y.-W.. 1987. “Confirmation, Disconfirmation and Information in Hypothesis Testing.” Psychological Review 94: 211–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koertge, N. 1974. “Bartley's Theory of Rationality.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4: 75–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koestler, A. 1964. The Act of Creation. New York: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Kohler, R. E. Jr. 1972. “The Origin of Lavoisier's First Experiments on Combustion.” Isis 63: 349–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koyré, A. 1939. Etudes Galiléennes. 3 vols. Rpt. Paris: Hermann, 1966Google Scholar
Koyré, A. 1965. Newtonian Studies. London: Chapman & HallCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krabbe, E. C. W. 1998. “Comment on J. Anthony Blair's Paper.” In Hansen et al. 1998
Krabbe, E. C. W. 2000. “In Response to Ralph H. Johnson's ‘More on Arguers and Dialectical Obligations.’” In Tindale et al. 2000
Krabbe, E. C. W. 2002. “Profiles of Dialogue as a Dialectical Tool.” In Eemeren 2002, 153–67
Kreyche, R. J. 1970. Logic for Undergraduates. 3rd ed. New York: Holt, Rinehart and WinstonGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1957. The Copernican Revolution. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1970a. “Reflections on my Critics.” In Lakatos and Musgrave 1970, 231–78
Kuhn, T. S. 1970b. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. 1977. “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In idem, The Essential Tension, 320–39. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Lakatos, I. 1963–64. “Proofs and Refutations.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14: 1–25, 129–139, 221–243, and 296–342CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I., and Musgrave, A., eds. 1970. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I., and E. Zahar. 1975. “Why Did Copernicus's Research Program Supersede Ptolemy's?” In The Copernican Achievement, ed. Westman, R. S., 354–83. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G. 1970. “Linguistics and Natural Logic.” Synthese 22: 151–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leff, M. 2000. “Rhetoric and Dialectic in the Twenty-first Century.” Argumentation 14: 241–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonard, H., and Goodman, N.. 1940. “The Calculus of Individuals and Its Uses.” Journal of Symbolic Logic 5: 45–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, J. 1988. “Must Reasons Be Rational?Philosophy of Science 55: 199–217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, P., ed. 1982. In Pursuit of Truth. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : HumanitiesGoogle Scholar
Lewicka, M. 1988. “On Subjective and Objective Anchoring of Cognitive Acts.” In Recent Trends in Theoretical Psychology, ed. Baker, W.. New York: Springer VerlagCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindsay, B., and Margenau, H.. 1957. Foundations of Physics. New York: DoverGoogle Scholar
Lipman, M. 1988a. “The Critical Thinker: The Concept of Critical Thinking.” Teaching Thinking and Problem Solving 10(3): 5–7Google Scholar
Lipman, M. 1988b. “Critical Thinking – What Can It Be?Educational Leadership 46(1): 38–43Google Scholar
Locke, J. 1959. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Fraser, A. C., 2 vols. New York: DoverGoogle Scholar
Losee, J. 1980. An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Lupoli, A. 1986. “Il Dialogo e la filosofia implicita di Galilei.” Rivista di storia della filosofia 41: 75–89Google Scholar
Mach, E. 1960. The Science of Mechanics. Trans. T. J. MacCormack. Open Court, Ill.: La SalleGoogle Scholar
Mahoney, M. S. 1980. “Christiaan Huygens: The Measurement of Time and Longitude at Sea.” In Bos et al. 1980, 234–70
Malcolm, N. 1942. “Moore and Ordinary Language.” In The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. Schilpp, P. A., 343–68. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University PressGoogle Scholar
Mancosu, P. 1996. Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice in the Seventeenth Century. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Margolis, H. 1988. Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1970. Understanding Symbolic Logic. New York: HarperGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1975a. “Are There Good Arguments That Bad Arguments Are Bad?Philosophy in Context 4: 61–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1975b. “In Defense of the Asymmetry.” Philosophy in Context 4(Suppl.): 44–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1976. “Tom, Dick, and Harry, and All the King's Men.” American Philosophical Quarterly 13: 89–107Google Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1980. “Logic and Linguistics.” In Modern Logic – A Survey, ed. Agazzi, E., 311–29. Dordrecht: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1981a. “The Fallacy behind Fallacies.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6: 489–500CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1981b. “The Pedagogy of Logic.” Teaching Philosophy 4: 303–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, G. J. 1987. “Asymmetry, Fallacy, and Indeterminacy.” Paper presented at the Symposium on “Informal Logic: Asymmetry and Fallacy,” American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, San Francisco
Mates, B. 1972. Elementary Logic. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Matlin, M., and Stang, D. J.. 1978. The Pollyanna Principle. Cambridge, Mass.: SchenkmanGoogle Scholar
Matson, W. I. 1965. The Existence of God. Ithaca, N.Y. : Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
McGuinness, C. 1990. “Talking about Thinking.” In Lines of Thinking, vol. 2: Skills, Emotion, Creative Processes, Individual Differences and Teaching Thinking, ed. Kilhooly, K. J.., 301–12. New York: John WileyGoogle Scholar
McGuire, J. E. 1968. “The Origin of Newton's Doctrine of Essential Qualities.” Centaurus 12: 233–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKay, T. J. 1984. “On Showing Invalidity.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14: 97–101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKay, T. J. 1987. “Shifting the Burden of Proof.” Paper presented at the Symposium on “Informal Logic: Asymmetry and Fallacy,” American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, San Francisco
McKie, D. 1952. Antoine Lavoisier. New York: Henry Schuman
McMullin, E. 1978. “The Conception of Science in Galileo's Work.” In New Perspectives on Galileo, ed. Butts, R. E. and Pitt, J., 209–57. Dordrecht: ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
McPeck, J. E. 1981. Critical Thinking and Education. New York: St. Martin'sGoogle Scholar
Meichenbaum, D. 1986. “Metacognitive Methods of Instruction.” In Facilitating Cognitive Development, ed. Schwebel, M. and Maher, C. A., 23–32. New York: HaworthGoogle Scholar
Meisel, J. H., ed. 1965. Pareto and Mosca. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1965. Essential Works. Ed. Lerner, M.. New York: Bantam BooksGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. 1982. “Conjectural Knowledge.” In Levinson 1982, 17–49
Miller, D. 1987. “A Critique of Good Reasons.” In Agassi and Jarvie 1987, 343–58
Millman, A. B. 1976. “The Plausibility of Research Programs.” In PSA 1976: Proceedings of the 1976 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Suppe, F. and Asquith, P. D., 140–48. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science AssociationGoogle Scholar
Mosca, G. 1939. The Ruling Class. Trans. H. D. Kahn, ed. Livingston, A.. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Naess, A. 1966. Communication and Argument. Totowa, N.J. : BedminsterGoogle Scholar
Naess, A. 1982a. “An Application of Empirical Argumentation Analysis to Spinoza's ‘Ethics.’” In Barth and Martens 1982, 245–56
Naess, A. 1982b. “A Necessary Component of Logic: Empirical Argumentation Analysis.” In Barth and Martens 1982, 9–22
Natanson, M., and Johnstone, Jr H. W.., eds. 1965. Philosophy, Rhetoric, and Argumentation. University Park: Pennsylvania State University PressGoogle Scholar
Naylor, R. 1990. “Galileo's Method of Analysis and Synthesis.” Isis 81: 695–707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newell, A. 1973. “You Can't Play 20 Questions with Nature and Win.” In Visual Information Processing, ed. Chase, W. G.. New York: AcademicGoogle Scholar
Newton, I. 1726. Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. Rpt., Geneva: Barillot, 1767Google Scholar
Newton, I. 1934. Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. A. Motte's translation revised by F. Cajori. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. 1980. “Introductory Essay.” In Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, ed. Nickles, T., 1–59. Dordrecht: ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R., and Ross, L.. 1980. Human Inference. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Northrop, F. S. C. 1951. “Einstein's Conception of Science.” In Schilpp 1951, 385–408
Novak, M. 1989. “The Gramscists Are Coming.” Forbes, 20 March, p. 54Google Scholar
Ogden, C. K., and Richards, I. A.. 1946. The Meaning of Meaning. New York: Harcourt Brace JovanovichGoogle Scholar
Oliver, J. W. 1967. “Formal Fallacies and Other Invalid Arguments.” Mind 76: 463–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ozell, J., ed. and trans. 1717. Logic; or, the Art of Thinking. LondonGoogle Scholar
Paggi, L. 1984. Le strategie del potere in Gramsci. Rome: RiunitiGoogle Scholar
Pareto, V. 1925. “Risposta ad una inchiesta.” In Inchiesta sulla massoneria ed. Brodero, E., 182–85. Milan: MondadoriGoogle Scholar
Paris, S. G., and P. Winograd. 1990. “How Metacognition Can Promote Academic Learning and Instruction.” In Dimensions of Thinking and Cognitive Instruction, ed. Jones, B. F. and Idol, L., 15–51. Hillsdale, N.J. : Lawrence ErlbaumGoogle Scholar
Pascal, B. 1952. The Provincial Letters, Pensées, Scientific Treatises. Chicago: Encyclopedia BritannicaGoogle Scholar
Passmore, J. 1961. Philosophical Reasoning. London: DuckworthGoogle Scholar
Paul, R. W. 1982. “Teaching Critical Thinking in the ‘Strong’ Sense.” Informal Logic Newsletter 4(2): 2–7Google Scholar
Paul, R. W. 1984. “Critical Thinking: Fundamental to Education for a Free Society.” Educational Leadership, September, pp. 4–14Google Scholar
Paul, R. W. 1985. “The Critical-Thinking Movement.” National Forum 65(1): 2–4Google Scholar
Peeters, G. 1971. “The Positive-Negative Asymmetry.” European Journal of Social Psychology 1: 455–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peeters, G. 1974. “Patterns of Information Implied in Interpersonal Relations.” Nederlands Tijdschrift voor de Psychologie 29: 505–34Google Scholar
Peeters, G. 1986. “Good and Evil as Softwares of the Brain.” Ultimate Reality and Meaning 9: 210–31Google Scholar
Peeters, G. 1987. “Positivity Bias and Negative Effect in Social Cognition.” Paper presented at the Small Group Meeting on Social Judgment, Jena, DDR
Pera, M. 1982. Apologia del metodo. Bari: LaterzaGoogle Scholar
Pera, M. 1987. “From Methodology to Dialectics.” In PSA 1986: Proceedings of the 1986 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Fine, A. and Machamer, P., 2: 359–74. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science AssociationGoogle Scholar
Pera, M. 1988. “Breaking the Link between Methodology and Rationality.” In Theory and Experiment, ed. Batens, D. and Bendegen, J. P., 259–76. Dordrecht: KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pera, M. 1991. Scienza e retorica. Bari: LaterzaGoogle Scholar
Perelman, Ch., and Olbrechts-Tyteca, L.. 1958. La Nouvelle Rhetorique: Traité de l'Argumentation. Paris: PUF.Google Scholar
Perelman, Ch., and Olbrechts-Tyteca, L.. 1969. The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation. Trans. J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver. Notre Dame: University of Notre DameGoogle Scholar
Perkins, D. N. 1985. “Reasoning as Imagination.” Interchange 16: 14–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perkins, D. N. 1986. Knowledge as Design. Hillsdale, N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Perkins, D. N. 1989. “Reasoning as It Is and as It Could Be: An Empirical Perspective.” In Thinking across Cultures, ed. Topping, D. N., Crowell, D. C., and Kobayashi, V. N., 175–94. Hillsdale, N.J. : Lawrence Erlbaum AssociatesGoogle Scholar
Perkins, D. N. 2002. “Standard Logic as a Model of Reasoning.” In Gabbay et al. 2002, 187–224
Perkins, D. N., R. Allen, and J. Hafner. 1983. “Difficulties in Everyday Reasoning.” In Thinking, the Expanding Frontier, ed. Maxwell, W., 177–89. Philadelphia: Franklin InstituteGoogle Scholar
Piaget, J. 1972a. “Intellectual Evolution from Adolescence to Adulthood.” Human Development 15: 1–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piaget, J. 1972b. The Principles of Genetic Epistemology. London: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Pollock, J. 1986. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Totowa, N.J. : Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1962. Conjectures and Refutations. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1963. The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. 2. New York: HarperGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1970. “Normal Science and Its Dangers.” In Lakatos and Musgrave 1970, 51–58
Popper, K. R. 1972. Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: ClarendonGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1974. “Reply to My Critics.” In Schilpp 1974, 961–1197
Price, D. J. de S. 1959. “Contra-Copernicus.” In Critical Problems in the History of Science, ed. Clagett, M., 197–218. Madison: University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1961. From a Logical Point of View. 2nd ed. New York: Harper & RowGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1974. “On Popper's Negative Methodology.” In Schilpp 1974, 218–20
Reed, C. 2000. “Building Monologue.” In Tindale et al. 2000
Reed, C., and D. Long. 1998. “Persuasive Monologue.” In Hansen et al. 1998
Rees, M. A. van. 2001. “Review of Johnson's Manifest Rationality.” Argumentation 15: 231–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Revlin, R., and Mayer, R. E., eds. 1978. Human Reasoning. New York: WileyGoogle Scholar
Robinson, J. A. T. 1963. Honest to God. Philadelphia: WestminsterGoogle Scholar
Rossiter, C., ed. 1961. The Federalist Papers. New York: Mentor BooksGoogle Scholar
Rowland, R. C. 1987. “On Defining Argument,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 20: 140–59Google Scholar
Rubin, R. 1977. “Descartes' Validation of Clear and Distinct Apprehension.” Philosophical Review 86: 197–208CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1945. A History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon and SchusterGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1959. The Problems of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1960. Our Knowledge of the External World. New York: New American LibraryGoogle Scholar
Ryle, G. 1954. “Formal and Informal Logic.” In idem, Dilemmas, 111–29. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Sakellariadis, S. 1982. “Descartes's Use of Empirical Data to Test Hypotheses.” Isis 73: 68–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. 1973. Logic. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. 1984. Logic. 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, I. 1973. Reason and Teaching. New York: Bobbs-MerrillGoogle Scholar
Schilpp, P. A., ed. 1951. Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist. Evanston, Ill.: Library of Living PhilosophersGoogle Scholar
Schilpp, P. A., ed. 1974. The Philosophy of Karl Popper. La Salle, Ill.: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Schwab, J. J. 1962. The Teaching of Science as Inquiry. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Scriven, M. 1956a. “A Possible Distinction between Traditional Scientific Disciplines and the Study of Human Behavior.” In Feigl and Scriven 1956, 330–39
Scriven, M. 1956b. “A Study of Radical Behaviorism.” In Feigl and Scriven 1956, 88–130
Scriven, M. 1958. “Definitions, Explanations, and Theories.” In Feigl et al. 1958, 99–195
Scriven, M. 1959. “Truisms as the Grounds for Historical Explanations.” In Theories of History, ed. Gardiner, P., 443–75. Glencoe, Ill.: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Scriven, M. 1962a. “Explanations, Predictions, and Laws.” In Feigl and Maxwell 1962, 170–230
Scriven, M. 1962b. “The Frontiers of Psychology: Psychoanalysis and Parapsychology.” In Colodny 1962, 79–129
Scriven, M. 1966. Primary Philosophy. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Scriven, M. 1968. “Science: The Philosophy of Science.” In International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences 14: 83–92Google Scholar
Scriven, M. 1976. Reasoning. New York: McGraw-HillGoogle Scholar
Scriven, M. 1987. “Probative Logic.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 7–32
Scriven, M. 1989. “The Philosophy of Ordinary Logic.” Paper presented at the Third International Symposium on Informal Logic, University of Windsor, Canada
Settle, T., Agassi, J., and Jarvie, I. C.. 1974. “Towards a Theory of Openness to Criticism.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4: 83–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. 1964. “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” Philosophical Review 73: 383–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. 1984. Reason and the Search for Knowledge. Boston: ReidelGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. 1988a. “Doppelt Crossed.” Philosophy of Science 55: 134–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. 1988b. “Rationalism and Empiricism.” Argumentation 2: 299–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, H. 1985. “What Is the Question Concerning the Rationality of Science?Philosophy of Science 52: 517–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, H. 1988. Educating Reason: Rationality, Critical Thinking, and Education. New York: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
Siegel, H. 1990. “Must Thinking Be Critical to Be Critical Thinking?Philosophy of the Social Sciences 20: 453–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegfried, R. 1972. “Lavoisier's View of the Gaseous State and Its Early Application to Pneumatic Chemistry.” Isis 63: 59–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1966. Choice and Chance: An Introduction to Inductive Logic. Belmont, Calif.: DickensonGoogle Scholar
Smit, P. A. 1987. “An Argumentation-Theoretical Analysis of Lenin's Political Strategies.” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 317–26
Smit, P. A. 1989. “An Argumentation-Analysis of a Central Part of Lenin's Political Logic.” Communication and Cognition 22: 357–74Google Scholar
Smit, P. A. 1992. “The Logic of Lenin's Polemics.” In Barth and Krabbe 1992, 11–23
Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. 1992. Analysing Complex Argumentation. Amsterdam: Sic SatGoogle Scholar
Staal, J. F., ed. 1969. “Formal Logic and Natural Language Argumentation (A Symposium).” Foundations of Language 5: 256–84Google Scholar
Stich, S. P. 1981. “Inferential Competence.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 353–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P. 1985. “Could Man Be an Irrational Animal?Synthese 64: 115–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P., and Nisbett, R. E.. 1980. “Justification and the Psychology of Human Reasoning.” Philosophy of Science 47: 188–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1952. Introduction to Logical Theory. London: MethuenGoogle Scholar
Tannen, D. 1998. The Argument Culture. New York: Random HouseGoogle Scholar
Tarski, A. 1965. Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences. 3rd ed. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Thomas, S. N. 1986. Practical Reasoning in Natural Language. 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.J. : Prentice-HallGoogle Scholar
Tindale, C. 2002. “A Concept Divided.” Argumentation 16: 299–309CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tindale, C., Hansen, H. V., and Sveda, E., eds. 2000. Argumentation at the Century's Turn. Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. CD-ROM. ISBN 0-9683461-1-1Google Scholar
Togliatti, P. 1979. On Gramsci and Other Writings. London: Lawrence and WishartGoogle Scholar
Toulmin, S. 1958. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Turing, A. M. 1950. “Computing Machinery and Intelligence.” Mind 59: 433–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D.. 1971. “The Belief in the Law of Small Numbers.” Psychological Bulletin 76: 105–110CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D.. 1973. “Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Frequency and Probability.” Cognitive Psychology 5: 207–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vignaux, G. 1976. L'Argumentation. Geneva: Librairie DrozGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1981. “The Fallacy of Many Questions.” Logique et Analyse 24: 291–313Google Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1985. Arguer's Position: A Pragmatic Study of Ad Hominem Attack, Criticism, Refutation, and Fallacy. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood PressGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1987. “What Is a Fallacy?” In Eemeren et al. 1987, 323–30
Walton, D. N. 1989a. Informal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1989b. Question-Reply Argumentation. New York: Greenwood PressGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1990. “What Is Reasoning? What Is an Argument?Journal of Philosophy 87: 399–419CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 1992. “Questionable Questions in Question Period.” In Barth and Krabbe 1992, 87–95
Walton, D. N. 1996. Argument Structure: A Pragmatic Theory. Toronto: University of Toronto PressGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N. 2004. “A New Dialectical Theory of Explanation.” Philosophical Explorations 7: 71–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D., and Krabbe, E. C. W.. 1995. Commitment in Dialogue. Albany: State University of New YorkGoogle Scholar
Wartofsky, M. 1978. “Scientific Judgment.” Dialectics and Humanism 5: 35–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wason, P. C. 1983. “Realism and Rationality in the Selection Task.” In Evans 1983c, 44–75
Wason, P. C., and Johnson-Laird, P. N.. 1972. Psychology of Reasoning. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Watkins, J. W. N. 1970. “Against ‘Normal Science.’” In Lakatos and Musgrave 1970, 25–38
Weizenbaum, J. 1976. Computer Power and Human Reason: From Judgment to Calculation. San Francisco: W. H. FreemanGoogle Scholar
Westman, R. S. 1980. “Huygens and the Problem of Cartesianism.” In Bos et al. 1980, 83–103
Whately, R. 1838. Elements of Logic. New YorkGoogle Scholar
Willard, C. A. 1983. Argumentation and the Social Grounds of Knowledge. University: University of Alabama PressGoogle Scholar
Woods, J. 1980. “What Is Informal Logic?” In Blair and Johnson 1980, 57–68
Woods, J., and Walton, D. N.. 1977a. “Post Hoc, Ergo Propter Hoc.” Review of Metaphysics 30: 569–93Google Scholar
Woods, J., and Walton, D. N.. 1977b. “Towards a Theory of Argument.” Metaphilosophy 8: 298–315CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, J., and Walton, D. N.. 1982. Argument: The Logic of Fallacies. Toronto: McGraw-Hill RyersonGoogle Scholar
Woods, J., and Walton, D. N.. 1989. Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982. Dordrecht: ForisGoogle Scholar
Wyatt, N. 2001. “Review of Johnson's Manifest Rationality.” Philosophy in Review 21: 185–87Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×