Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-05T15:58:49.251Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Technical details

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 December 2009

J. Roger Hindley
Affiliation:
University of Wales, Swansea
Get access

Summary

To avoid interrupting the main lines of thought in the earlier chapters some concepts were defined there only in outline and their main properties were stated without proof. This chapter gives the full definitions and proofs. It should be read only as required to follow the arguments in the other chapters. Its sections are largely independent of each other.

The structure of a term

From the viewpoint of logical order this section is best read between 1A3 and 1A4.

As remarked in 1A4, a subterm of a term may have more than one occurrence. The present section introduces a precise notation to distinguish such different occurrences; it is rather clumsy and the reader should avoid using it whenever possible, but in some proofs its precision will be vital. The first step is to define a set of expressions called positions that can be assigned to different occurrences of a subterm to show where they occur.

Definition (Positions) A positionp = i1im is any finite (perhaps empty) string of symbols such that i1, …, im are integers and im is either an integer or an asterisk, *. Its length is m, and if m = 0 we say p = Ø.

  1. If m ≥ 1 and im = 1 we call p a function position;

  2. If m ≥ 1 and im = 2 we call p an argument position;

  3. if m ≥ 1 and im = 0 we call p a body position; and

  4. if m ≥ 1 and im = * we call p an abstractor position.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Technical details
  • J. Roger Hindley, University of Wales, Swansea
  • Book: Basic Simple Type Theory
  • Online publication: 02 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511608865.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Technical details
  • J. Roger Hindley, University of Wales, Swansea
  • Book: Basic Simple Type Theory
  • Online publication: 02 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511608865.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Technical details
  • J. Roger Hindley, University of Wales, Swansea
  • Book: Basic Simple Type Theory
  • Online publication: 02 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511608865.010
Available formats
×