Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-01T01:43:25.641Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 16 - Divine winds

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 September 2011

Brent D. Shaw
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

After following a long and sometimes contradictory path, Augustine was finally to condemn the taking of one's own life as an absolute sin, an inexpiable crime against God. Born at Mondovi, a village only some 12 miles south of Augustine's Hippo Regius, Albert Camus began his Le mythe de Sisyphe with the declaration:

There is only one serious philosophical problem: it is suicide. To judge whether life is or is not worth the pain of living is to answer the fundamental question of philosophy. All the rest – if the world has three dimensions [we must admit that Camus was not a physicist], if the soul has nine or a dozen categories – all these follow. This is the game. We must make a reply.

But Camus’ suicide was very different from Augustine's. For Camus, suicide is provoked, ultimately, by a growing sense of the absurdity of existence. He construed a typical scenario as follows. The stage props of a person's life are present on each ordinary day: “Get up, catch the train, four hours at the office or workshop, dinner, streetcar, four more hours of work, eat, sleep, Monday, Tuesday, Wednesday, Thursday, Friday, Saturday, according to the same rhythm. This path is easily followed most of the time. Only, one day, a ‘why’ arises.” A process of the disintegration of the familiar stage-sets of one's life begins, life becomes a stranger to the one living it, and all normal meaning drains from existence.

This is the pathology of one type of self-killing – a peculiar kind of modern despair. But it is not my suicide problem. Nor was it Augustine's. Camus, who wrote his master's dissertation at the University of Algiers on Augustine and Plotinus, examined by no less a figure than Louis Gernet, knew this too. His novel La mort heureuse – A Happy Death – shows that he was alert to these differences, indeed opposites, between his world and that of Augustine – the contrast with the latter's De beata vita. Perhaps because of this awareness, Camus appended a footnote to his text, admitting that his problem of suicide was, after all, historically contingent: “We will not miss the opportunity,” he says, “to note the specific character of this essay. Suicide can in fact be linked to more honorable considerations. One example: political suicides of protest.” It is precisely this type of suicide, relegated by Camus to a footnote, that is our concern here: a kind of honorable self-killing that was motivated not by a sense of “the absurd” or by the meaninglessness of existence, but rather by the precise opposite. It was a self-inflicted death that was interpreted as full of meaning and one that embraced life, indeed a better one without end.

Type
Chapter
Information
Sacred Violence
African Christians and Sectarian Hatred in the Age of Augustine
, pp. 721 - 770
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Camus, A.Le mythe de Sisyphe: essai sur l'absurdeParisGallimard 1942 17
Thody, P.Albert CamusLondonMacmillan 1989 1
McBride, J.Albert Camus: Philosopher and LittérateurNew YorkSt. Martin's Press 1992
Todd, O.Albert Camus: une vieParisGallimard 1996
Giddens, A.DurkheimLondonFontana 1978 47
Bonnardière, A.-M.Quelques remarques sur les citations scripturaires de REAug 9 1963 82Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Divine winds
  • Brent D. Shaw, Princeton University, New Jersey
  • Book: Sacred Violence
  • Online publication: 07 September 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762079.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Divine winds
  • Brent D. Shaw, Princeton University, New Jersey
  • Book: Sacred Violence
  • Online publication: 07 September 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762079.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Divine winds
  • Brent D. Shaw, Princeton University, New Jersey
  • Book: Sacred Violence
  • Online publication: 07 September 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762079.018
Available formats
×