Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-09T01:49:46.893Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

15 - Montesquieu's Pluralized Civil Religion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Ronald Beiner
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Get access

Summary

Christianity…did not establish entirely new virtues; but it changed their relative position. Certain rude and half-savage virtues had been on the top of the list; Christianity put them on the bottom. The milder virtues (such as neighborly love, pity, leniency, the forgetfulness even of injuries) had been on the bottom of the antique list; Christianity placed them above all others.

– Alexis de Tocqueville

Montesquieu begins Book 29 of The Spirit of the Laws with the claim that his book's purpose is to prove that the legislator must embody the spirit of moderation: Political good, he says, is always to be located between two extremes. This Aristotelian idea of virtue as a mean between extremes points us back to the beginning of Book 25, where Montesquieu highlights two extremes in the experience of religion: piety and atheism. Applying the Montesquieuian rule yields the notion that the legislator should aim at splitting the difference between piety and atheism. Piety is defined here as love of religion; atheism is defined as fear of religion. The wise legislator should neither love nor fear religion but should be guided by a third principle, namely the possible utility of religion. Or rather, attending to the utility of religion should combine an appreciation of the advantages that can come with a loving respect for a particular religion established within a given society, with fear of the evils that can arise from the reign of religion at its worst. The prudent legislator is concerned with how to use both the pious man's love for religion and the atheist's fear of religion to secure good political purposes. However, it goes without saying that someone who can think about religion both from the pious person's perspective (surveying the goods of religion) and the atheist's perspective (surveying the evils of religion) can truly inhabit neither perspective, neither that of atheism nor that of piety.

Given how the Rousseauian interpretation of civil religion functions as a hub for the whole of this book, one can hardly avoid relating Montesquieu to the corresponding views in Rousseau. Let us recall the interpretation presented in Part I. The standard reading of Social Contract IV.8 is that Rousseau gives consummate expression to his illiberal politics by ending the book with the highly illiberal project of positing a state religion. Rousseau seems to point in this illiberal direction by radically contrasting the antipolitical character of modern Christianity with the politicizing function of ancient paganism. This, however, is a false impression: Although Rousseau does his utmost to highlight the political deficiencies of Christianity by playing up the civic character of paganism, he ultimately rejects the latter, saying that the “religion of the citizen” leads eventually to cruel intolerance and theocratic imperialism. The “civil religion” that Rousseau lays out at the end of the chapter falls well short of civic religion on the Roman model: Rousseau insists that “there is no longer and can never again be an exclusive national religion.” Rather, Rousseau, no less than Locke, places tolerance at the center of his teaching on the relation between church and state. I do not think it would be an overstatement to say that Rousseau concludes a supposedly antiliberal theory of politics with a celebration of liberalism.

Type
Chapter
Information
Civil Religion
A Dialogue in the History of Political Philosophy
, pp. 189 - 198
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Rousseau, EmileBloom, AllanNew YorkBasic Books 1979 313Google Scholar
Walzer, MichaelThe Revolution of the SaintsNew York 1976 289Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith N.MontesquieuOxfordOxford University Press 1987Google Scholar
Kingston, RebeccaMontesquieu and the Parlement of BordeauxGenevaDroz 1996 146Google Scholar
Pangle, Thomas L.The Theological Basis of Liberal Modernity in Montesquieu's “Spirit of the Laws”ChicagoUniversity of Chicago Press 2010Google Scholar
Locke, JohnA Letter Concerning TolerationTully, James H.IndianapolisHackett 1983 43Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×