Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-15T11:56:49.982Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Expression

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Richard Eldridge
Affiliation:
Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

Feelings about subject matters in life: Wordsworth, Tolstoy, and Collingwood

Against the idea that works of art present a subject matter and the idea that works of art embody pleasing formal arrangements, it can seem important to emphasize that works of art are products of human action – made things, not just either imitations or forms. Without this emphasis artworks can seem either too much like gratuitous reproductions of reality (like mirrors or reflections in ponds) or too much like objects of idle pleasure and amusement (like pretty decorations). When we instead focus on works of art as things that human beings make, then these misemphases can be corrected. Though they do present a subject matter and please through arrangement, works of art are also made in order somehow to communicate something – an attitude, a point of view, or a feeling about a subject matter – that lies in some sense “in” the maker. Audiences typically approach a work with an interest not only in what it asserts but also in what it more broadly communicates, that is, with an interest in which attitudes and emotions toward its subject matter on the part of its maker it makes manifest. It is natural therefore to think that artworks are expressive objects and that it is distinctive of artistic representations and formal arrangements – in contrast with scientific treatises and decorations – that they have as a central function the expression of attitudes and emotions toward their subject matters. Only by attending to art as expression can we properly engage with its distinctive kind of significance: the communication of emotion and attitude, above and beyond simple assertion.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Eldridge, Richard, Literature, Life, and Modernity (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008), pp. 75–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tolstoy, Leo, What is Art?, trans. Maude, Aylmer (Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1960), p. 51.Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G., The Principles of Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1938), p. 41.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. Knox, T. M., 2 vols. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), vol. I, p. 7.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley, “Aesthetic Problems of Modern Philosophy,” in Cavell, S., Must We Mean What We Say? (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1969), p. 73.Google Scholar
Gethmann-Siefert, Annemarie, Einführung in Hegel’s Asthetik (Stuttgart: Uni-Taschenbuch, 2005)Google Scholar
Rutter, Benjamin, Hegel on the Modern Arts (Cambridge University Press, 2010), p. 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danto, Arthur, “Learning to Live with Pluralism,” in A. Danto, The Wake of Art: Criticism, Philosophy, and the Ends of Taste, ed. Horowitz, Gregg and Huhn, Tom (Amsterdam: Overseas Publishers Association, 1998), pp. 81–95 at p. 95.Google Scholar
Freeland, Cynthia, But is it Art? (Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 58.Google Scholar
Eliot, T. S., “The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock,” in The Norton Anthology of English Literature, 3rd edn, ed. Abrams, M. H. et al. (New York: W. W. Norton, 1974), vol. II, pp. 2164–67 at p. 2167, lines 120–25.Google Scholar
Kivy, Peter, The Chorded Shell: Reflections of Musical Expression (Princeton University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Davies, Stephen, Musical Meaning and Expression (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
Sircello, Guy, Mind and Art: An Essay on the Varieties of Expression (Princeton University Press, 1972), p. 39.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, The Brown Book, in Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books (New York: Harper & Row, 1958), p. 158.Google Scholar
Hagberg, G. L., Art as Language: Wittgenstein, Meaning, and Aesthetic Theory (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995), pp. 103–09.Google Scholar
Lyas, Colin, Aesthetics (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1997), p. 102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Stephen, “Artistic Expression and the Hard Case of Pure Music,” in Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art, ed. Kieran, Matthew (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), pp. 179–91 at p. 181.Google Scholar
Robinson, Jenefer, “Expression Theories,” in The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music, eds. Gracyk, Theodore and Kania, Andrew (London: Routledge, 2011), pp. 201–11 at pp. 202–03.Google Scholar
Levinson, Jerrold, Contemplating Art (Oxford University Press, 2006), p. 93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Jerrold, “Musical Expressiveness,” in The Pleasures of Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2006), pp. 90–125 at p. 125.Google Scholar
Green, Mitchell, Self-Expression (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), pp. 204, 202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Jenefer, Deeper than Reason: Emotion and its Role in Literature, Music, and Art (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), pp. 41, 61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kivy, Peter, “Critical Study: Deeper than Emotion,” British Journal of Aesthetics 46, 3 (July 2006), pp. 287–311 at pp. 302–03.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spackman, John, “Expressiveness, Ineffability, and Nonceptuality,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70, 3 (summer 2012), pp. 303–314 at p. 312B.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eldridge, Richard, “Hegel on Music,” in Hegel and the Arts, ed. Houlgate, Stephen (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2007), pp. 119–45.Google Scholar
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, “Self-Reliance,” in Selections from Ralph Waldo Emerson, ed. Whicher, Stephen E. (Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1957), pp. 147–68 at p. 147.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Expression
  • Richard Eldridge, Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
  • Book: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107300538.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Expression
  • Richard Eldridge, Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
  • Book: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107300538.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Expression
  • Richard Eldridge, Swarthmore College, Pennsylvania
  • Book: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107300538.005
Available formats
×