Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-19T07:52:05.785Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Mathematics as science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2012

Get access

Summary

Introduction

The great Victorian scientist T. H. Huxley once made the mistake of claiming that mathematics was a deductive science modelled on Euclid in contrast to the natural sciences which were inductive, based on observation, experiment and conjecture. James Sylvester (1814–1897), an equally great mathematician, in a famous address to the British Association for the Advancement of Science in 1869, disagreed:

[Huxley] says ‘mathematical training is almost purely deductive. The mathematician starts with a few simple propositions, the proof of which is so obvious that they are called self-evident, and the rest of his work consists of subtle deductions from them’…we are told [by Huxley] that Mathematics is that study which knows nothing of observation, nothing of experiment, nothing of induction, nothing of causation.

Sylvester was appalled:

I think no statement could have been made more opposite to the undoubted facts of the case, that mathematical analysis is continually invoking the aid of new principles, new ideas and new methods, not capable of being defined by any form of words, but springing directly from the inherent powers and activity of the human mind, and from continually renewed introspection of that inner world of thought of which the phenomena are as varied and require as close attention to discern as those of the outer physical world…that it is unceasingly calling forth the faculties of observation and comparison, that one of its principal weapons is induction, that it has frequent recourse to experimental trial and verification, and that it affords boundless scope for the exercise of the highest efforts of imagination and invention.

Sylvester added that, ‘Induction and analogy are the special characteristics of modern mathematics’ [Midonik 1968 v.2: 370–1].

Type
Chapter
Information
Games and Mathematics
Subtle Connections
, pp. 122 - 130
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×