Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T16:25:10.264Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Idealism and the origins of analytic philosophy1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2013

Peter Hylton
Affiliation:
University of Illinois
Nicholas Boyle
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Liz Disley
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Karl Ameriks
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Analytic philosophy is widely, and with good reason, thought of as having two points of origin. First, in the work of Gottlob Frege: with his systematic presentation of modern logic, his use of that logic to give an account of arithmetic, and his articulation of the philosophical views he takes to be required by his logic; second, in the work of Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore at the very end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth. Russell and Moore put forward a metaphysical view incorporating a strong form of realism and developed their philosophical views on that basis. Russell formulated modern logic and used it to account for mathematics; in both of these matters his view resembles Frege's, but was initially worked out independently; he subsequently sought to apply the same principles to an understanding of empirical knowledge. Moore put forward a strongly realist view of ethics and developed a conception of philosophical analysis.

So we may distinguish the British origins of analytic philosophy from its German origins. Under the former head we shall confine ourselves to discussion of Russell and Moore. Under the latter, however, we shall consider figures other than Frege. Frege's work was confined to logic, the philosophy of mathematics, and to what he took to be the philosophical implications of these subjects. Crucially, he makes no attempt at a systematic treatment of empirical knowledge. Furthermore, his direct influence was quite limited. (Although the philosophers who were directly influenced by him include Russell, Wittgenstein and Carnap.) For these reasons, even the most cursory account of the German origins of analytic philosophy must take some account of later thinkers who played a role in the development of Logical Empiricism (also known as Logical Positivism), especially Carnap, who had the most influence of any of the Logical Empiricists on the subsequent development of analytic philosophy.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Impact of Idealism
The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought
, pp. 323 - 346
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Sluga, Hans says: ‘Following common practice, I take analytic philosophy as originating in the work of Frege, Russell, Moore, and Wittgenstein’, ‘Frege on meaning’ in Glock, H.-J., The Rise of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1997), 17–34Google Scholar
Hacker, Peter, Wittgenstein's Place in Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1996), 5Google Scholar
Stirling's, H. book The Secret of Hegel (London: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts and Green, 1865)Google Scholar
Pucelle, Jean, L’Idéalisme en Angleterre (Neuchâtel: Éditions de la Baconnière, Boudry, 1955)Google Scholar
Passmore, John A., A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London: Duckworth, 1957)Google Scholar
Works of Thomas Hill Green, ed. Nettleship, R. L. (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 3rd edn, 1894), iii, 137
Lotze, Sigwart, Green, Bradley, Bosanquet, James and Dewey, , and which in their tenets all derive from Hegel's re-statement of Kant's logical doctrines.’ A Commentary to Kant's ‘Critique of Pure Reason’ (London: Macmillan, 1918; 2nd edn, 1923), 36Google Scholar
Köhnke, Klaus Christian, The Rise of Neo-Kantianism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael, The Parting of the Ways (Chicago and LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 2000)Google Scholar
Carus, André speaks of Kant's ‘ambivalence with respect to enlightenment and scientific thinking’, and of his ‘two legacies’. Carnap and Twentieth Century Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummett, Michael, who describes Frege as ‘a realist in revolt against the prevailing idealism of his day’; Frege: Philosophy of Language (London: Duckworth, 1973), 197Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans D., ‘Frege and the rise of analytic philosophy’, Inquiry 18 (1975), 471–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schirn, M. (ed.), Studies on Frege (Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 1976), i, 27–47
Frege, Gottlob, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1968Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Nachgelassene Schriften, ed. Hermes, Hans et al. (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1969), 286–94 and 298–303Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Posthumous Writings, ed. Hermes, Hans et al. (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press, 1979), 267–74 and 278–81Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Kleine Schriften, ed. Angelli, Ignacio (Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag, 1990; 1st edn 1967), 1–49Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Collected Papers, ed. McGuiness, Brian (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), 1–55Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel, ed. Gabriel, Gottfried et al. (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1976), 163Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, ed. Gabriel, Gottfried et al. (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 100Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans, Frege (London: Routledge, 1980), ch. II, §2Google Scholar
Gabriel, Gottfried, ‘Frege, Lotze, and the continental roots of early analytic philosophy’, in Reck, Erich H. (ed.), Frege to Wittgenstein (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 39–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, , ‘Autobiography’, in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. Schilpp, P. A. (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court: 1963), 11Google Scholar
Russell, , An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1897)Google Scholar
Hylton, Peter, Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990)Google Scholar
Griffin, Nicholas, Russell's Idealist Apprenticeship (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Smith, Norman Kemp (London: Macmillan, 1968
Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans. Haldane, E. S. and Simon, Francis H. (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1955; 1st edn 1892), iii, 431; cf. also 432f
Moore, G. E., Early Philosophical Writings, ed. Baldwin, Thomas and Preti, Consuelo (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)
Mind, n.s. 12 (1903), 433–53
Moore, G. E., Philosophical Studies (London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co, 1922), 2–30Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, Problems of Philosophy (London: Oxford University Press, Home University Library, 1952, 1st edn 1912)Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. M. (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, 3 vols (New York, NY: Macmillan, 1901–1905), vol. 2, 450–52
(Hegel, , Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Miller, A. V., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, 46)Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), 10Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, The Principles of Mathematics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), xvGoogle Scholar
Bradley, F. H., Principles of Logic (London: Oxford University Press, 1922, 1st edn 1883),Google Scholar
Russell, , Mysticism and Logic (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1918) 209–32Google Scholar
The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vi, ed. Slater, John G. (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1992), 148–61
Mind, n.s. 40 (1931), 195
Baldwin, Thomas, G. E. Moore (London: Routledge, 1990), 193Google Scholar
Lectures on Philosophy, ed. Lewy, C. (London: Allen and Unwin, 1966), 133f
Schilpp, P. A. (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (Evanston and Chicago, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1942), 664
Ricketts, Thomas, ‘Truth and propositional unity in early Russell’, in Floyd, Juliet and Shieh, Sanford (eds), Future Pasts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 101–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hylton, Peter, ‘The nature of the proposition and the revolt against Idealism’, in Rorty, R. et al. (eds). Philosophy in History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 375–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hylton, Peter, Propositions, Functions, and Analysis (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 9–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinong's theory of complexes and assumptions’, Mind n.s. 13 (1904)
The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell vol. 4, ed. Urquhart, Alistair (London: Routledge, 1994), 432–72
‘On the nature of truth and falsehood’ in Russell, Bertrand, Philosophical Essays (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1966
The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, vii, ed. Eames, Elizabeth Ramsden (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1984)
Dolnick, Alexander, Russell's Multiple Relation Theory: evolution and demise, unpublished PhD dissertation, University of Illinois, Chicago, 2012Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, The Analysis of Mind (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1971; 1st edn 1921)Google Scholar
Sluga, Hans and Stern, David (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 59–99CrossRef
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, with en face translation by Pears, D. F. and McGuiness, B. F. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf, Logische Syntax der Sprache (Vienna: Julius Springer Verlag, 1934CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smeaton, Amethe as Logical Syntax of Language (London: Kegan Paul Trench, Trubner & Co., 1937)Google Scholar
Griffin, Nicholas (ed.), The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell v. I (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1992), 202
Mind n.s. 14 (1905), 479–93
Ramsey, F. P., The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays (London: Kegan Paul, 1931), 263Google Scholar
Schilpp, P. A. (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell (Evanston, Ill.: The Library of Living Philosophers Inc., 1946), 175–225
On Scientific Method in Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1914)
Russell, Bertrand, Mysticism and Logic (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1963; first edition 1917), 75–93Google Scholar
Slater, John G. (ed.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell viii (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1986), 55–73
The Monist 28 (1918), 495–527CrossRef

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×