Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T04:23:34.308Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - The public of the intellectuals – from Kant to Lyotard

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2013

William Rasch
Affiliation:
Indiana University
Nicholas Boyle
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Liz Disley
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
John Walker
Affiliation:
Birkbeck College, University of London
Get access

Summary

Democracies corrode quite fast…They corrode because most people don't care very much about them. The difficulty of sustaining voluntary interest in the business of choosing the people who will rule over you is well attested. And the reason why we need intellectuals, as well as all the good journalists we can find, is to fill the space that grows between the two parts of democracy: the governed and the governors.

– Tony Judt

Tony Judt's vision of democracy is justifiably bleak; not only because he was dying when he composed these words but also because, despite its apparent near universal victory, democracy seems to be dying as well. Referring to the ‘business of choosing the people who will rule over you’ and identifying the ‘two parts of democracy’ as ‘the governed and the governors’ certainly falls far short of the democratic ideal. Are not the ruled also the rulers, the rulers the ruled, temporarily elevated? Admittedly, direct democracy in which all the people are assembled to make collective decisions has become impossible for all but the smallest of communities (the cynic might say: for all but the solitary individual); but even within representative democracy are not the representatives said to be of the people, carrying with them the trust and good will (or even a specific mandate) of the majority? What then is the ‘space that grows’ between the people and the people's representatives? Some have pointed to the routinised business of politics as a profession, creating the politician who lives less (if at all) for politics (as a calling) and more from politics, as a job like any other. Others have emphasised political parties and the oligarchic machinery that eventually transforms them. Both claims could easily be seen as the necessary result of the vast complexity of modern society, a complexity that precludes overview and transparency and therefore calls for blind trust in ‘expert’ knowledge. These and other, similar symptoms point to the fundamental structural divide that inheres in modern, liberal democracy, namely the welcome severance of the private from the public sphere. No longer participating actively in the public duty of collective decision making, the people dissolve into people, a collection of individuals pursuing private interests.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Impact of Idealism
The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought
, pp. 26 - 50
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Judt, Tony, with Snyder, Timothy, Thinking the Twentieth Century (New York: Penguin, 2012), 306–7Google Scholar
Weber, Max, The Vocation Lectures, ed. Owen, David and Strong, Tracy B., trans. Rodney Livingstone (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2004), 40Google Scholar
Michels, Robert, Political Parties: a sociological study of the oligarchical tendencies of modern democracy, trans. Eden Paul and Cedar Paul (New York: Free Press, 1962), esp. 333–71Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas, Observations on Modernity, trans. William Whobrey (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), 75–112Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: an inquiry into a category of bourgeois society, trans. Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence (1965; Cambridge, MA: MIT Press and Cambridge: Polity Press, 1989), 102–17Google Scholar
Calhoun, Craig (ed.), Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992)
Midgley, David and Emden, Christian (eds.), Beyond Habermas: democracy, knowledge, and the public sphere (New York: Berghahn, 2012)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, ‘On the common saying: that may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice’, in Practical Philosophy, ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 279–309Google Scholar
Schriften über Religion und Aufklärung, ed. Thom, Martina (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1989), 415
Kant, Immanuel, ‘Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim’, trans. Allen Wood, in Anthropology, History, and Education, ed. Zöller, Günther and Louden, Robert B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 108–20Google Scholar
Wood, Allen, ‘Kant's historical materialism’, in Kneller, Jane and Axinn, Sidney (eds.), Autonomy and Continuity: readings in contemporary Kantian philosophy (Albany: SUNY Press, 1998), 15–37Google Scholar
Kant, I., ‘Conjectural beginning of human history’, trans. Allen Wood, in Anthropology, History, and Education, ed. Zöller, Günther and Louden, Robert B., 163–75
Kant, I., ‘What is enlightenment?’, in Practical Philosophy, ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor, 17–22
Foucault, Michel, The Government of Self and Others: lectures at the Collège de France 1982–1983, ed. Frédéric Gros, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011), 29Google Scholar
Kant, I., The Conflict of the Faculties: Der Streit der Fakultäten, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Lincoln: Nebraska University Press, 1992), 25Google Scholar
Boyle, Nicholas, ‘Inventing the intellectual: Schiller and Fichte at the University of Jena’, Publications of the English Goethe Society 81, no. 1 (2012), 39–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fichte, J. G., Early Philosophical Writings, ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988), 159Google Scholar
Marquard, Odo, Schwierigkeiten mit der Geschichtsphilosophie (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1982)Google Scholar
Transzendentaler Idealismus, Romantische Naturphilosophie, Psychoanalyse (Cologne: Verlag für Philosophie Jürgen Dinter, 1987), 77–83
English, ‘Unburdenings: theodicy motives in modern philosophy’, in In Defense of the Accidental: philosophical studies, trans. Wallace, Robert M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 8–28Google Scholar
‘Indicted and unburdened man in eighteenth-century philosophy’, in Farewell to Matters of Principle: philosophical studies, trans. Wallace, Robert M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 38–63Google Scholar
Marquard, Odo, ‘Das Über-Wir: Bemerkungen zur Diskursethik’, in Individuum und Gewaltenteilung: philosophische Studien (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2004), 39–67Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen, Der gespaltene Westen (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2004), 110Google Scholar
Bohman, James and Lutz-Bachmann, Matthias (eds.), Perpetual Peace: essays on Kant's cosmopolitan ideal (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), 113–53
Habermas, Jürgen, ‘On the public use of history’, in The New Conservatism: cultural criticism and the historians’ debate, ed. and trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 229–40Google Scholar
Lyotard, Jean-François, The Postmodern Explained: correspondence 1982–1985, ed. and trans. Julian Pefanis and Morgan Thomas (Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press, 1993), 24Google Scholar
Lyotard, Jean-François, ‘The Sign of history’, in The Lyotard Reader, ed. Benjamin, Andrew (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), 393–411Google Scholar
Kant, I., Werke in sechs Bänden, Weischedel, W. (ed.), (Wiesbaden: Insel, 1956–62)Google Scholar
Fichte, J. G., Von den Pflichten der Gelehrten: Jenaer Vorlesungen 1794/95, ed. Lauth, Reinhard, Jacob, Hans and Schneider, Peter K. (Hamburg: Meiner, 1971), 19Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×