Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T13:23:57.683Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Irrelevance of Aesthetics and the De-Theorizing of the Self in “Classical” Weimar

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2013

Benjamin Bennett
Affiliation:
University of Virginia
Simon J. Richter
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

In 1750, in the first paragraph of his Aesthetica, Frankfurt professor Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten (1714–62) defines this brand-new intellectual discipline as “scientia cognitionis sensitivae” (the science of sensate knowledge). But unfortunately — at least for those who value neatness in history — most of the major thinkers who follow (Kant being the notable exception) either forget or neglect or simply discard this definition, concentrating instead on a pair of important, but subordinate concepts in Baumgarten's system — art and beauty — which are understood henceforward as the true content of “aesthetics.” Once this deetymologizing move has been made (aistheta, in Greek, are simply things perceived by the physical senses), the historical situation is also muddied, and the brand-new discipline is henceforth regarded as an age-old discipline, traceable at least as far back as Plato and Aristotle.

Needless to say, there are possibilities for confusion here, as well as for development; but the one possibility that is definitely excluded is that “aesthetics” should cohere as a single scientific discipline with a well-defined scope. (Do art and beauty even really belong together as objects of study?) This essay will, in fact, suggest that aesthetics is best understood not as an area of inquiry in the first place, but as a specific cultural project in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Europe. For the time being, however, we can get a feel for what aesthetics does by considering the various issues it raises.

With respect to art, the opposition between imitative and expressive theories (traced back to the supposed founding instances of Aristotle and pseudo-Longinus) becomes increasingly important toward the end of the eighteenth century.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Boydell & Brewer
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×