Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-03T23:57:18.307Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

3 - G. W. Leibniz: Monadology

Douglas Burnham
Affiliation:
Staffordshire University
John Shand
Affiliation:
Open University
Get access

Summary

Introduction

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz wrote the Monadology in 1714, near the end of his life. It was a life of considerable accomplishment. He was born in Leipzig in 1646 and although the son of a professor of moral philosophy, and educated in the law, Leibniz chose neither of these as a career. Instead, he became an intellectual all-rounder at the court of the Duke of Hanover, working as librarian, official historian, legal advisor and, frequently enough, international diplomat. In these capacities he travelled often and widely in Europe, giving him ample opportunity to meet the foremost intellectuals of the day, including the philosopher Spinoza. Leibniz was a polymath, who made significant contributions in many areas of physics, logic, history, librarianship and, of course, philosophy and theology, while also working on ideal languages, mechanical clocks, mining machinery, and a host of other projects. Among other achievements in mathematics, he invented the mathematical technique of calculus independently of, but at around the same time as, Newton, setting off a long-running, nationalistic controversy.

It is little wonder, then, that he published relatively little. What he often called his philosophical “system” was more or less completed by the 1680s when he wrote the “Discourse on Metaphysics” (1686). Like many others of his works, this was not published in his lifetime, and only appeared in print more than 250 years later. After the “Discourse”, over the next 30 years or so, Leibniz worked out additional details and implications of this system, changed the emphasis here and there, and invented new terms to describe and arguments to defend his position, but many key points of the “system” remained substantially the same.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×