Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-03T19:18:06.121Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

3 - Grotius and the Civilian

from Part I - Suffering, Reconciliation and Values in the Seventeenth Century

Colm McKeogh
Affiliation:
University of Waikato
Erica Charters
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Eve Rosenhaft
Affiliation:
University of Liverpool
Hannah Smith
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

An enemy, then, who wishes to show respect not for what human laws permit him to do but for what is his duty and what is right and godly, will spare the blood of his adversary. He will sentence no one to death unless by so doing he escapes death himself or something like it, or because his enemy has committed crimes which measure up to capital offences. And even to some who deserve such punishment he will extend pardon, either in full or from the death penalty, moved perhaps by the promptings of humanity, perhaps by other good reasons…

As for the killing of persons who are slaughtered incidentally, without intention, we must maintain what we said above, that mercy, even if not justice, requires that except for grave reasons affecting the safety of multitudes, nothing should be done that may threaten the destruction of innocent people.

Hugo Grotius (1583–1645) has long been regarded as a founding figure of modern international law. In particular he is credited with the secularisation of the natural-law approach: ‘Grotius finally excised theology from international law,’ writes Shaw, ‘and emphasised the irrelevance in such a study of any conception of a divine law.’ More recently he has been studied as a seminal political theorist of the early modern period who began the investigation of violence and accountability that was to be continued by Thomas Hobbes and John Locke: ‘seventeenth-century social contract theory is better seen as a conversation among Grotian thinkers than as a quarrel between “Leviathan” and constitutionalism’, suggests Baumgold.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Liverpool University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×