Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T19:48:32.780Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - The semantics of terms

from IV - Logic in the high middle ages: semantic theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

Two senses of ‘term’

Medieval philosophers and logicians used the word ‘term’ (terminus) in several senses, two of which are especially pertinent to this discussion. Strictly speaking, a term is what is subjected to the predicate or predicated of the subject in an ordinary categorical proposition – the subject term or the predicate term, the two ends (termini) of the proposition. In this sense whole phrases may be terms, but only certain sorts of words – nouns, adjectives, and verbs – can serve by themselves as terms. Less strictly, and in the later Middle Ages more prevalently, a term is any word at all, regardless of propositional context. In this discussion ‘term’ will be used in the less strict sense unless otherwise noted.

Signification as a psychological and causal property of terms

There are two basic properties for the medieval semantics of terms: signification and supposition. Signification is a psychologico-causal property of terms – a fact responsible for many disagreements and tensions in medieval semantics. The main source for the notion of signification was Boethius' translation of De interpretatione 3, 16b 19: ‘[Verbs] spoken in isolation are names and signify something. For he who speaks [them] establishes an understanding and he who hears [them] rests’. Hence ‘to signify’ something was ‘to establish an understanding’ of it. The psychological overtones of ‘to signify’ are similar to those of the modern ‘to mean’. Nevertheless, signification is not meaning. A term signifies that of which it makes a person think, so that, unlike meaning, signification is a species of the causal relation.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 188 - 196
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, Robert M. (1977). ‘Middle Knowledge and the Problem of Evil’, American Philosophical Quarterly 14:.Google Scholar
Albert, Saxony (1496). Quaestiones super artem veterem, in Expositio aurea et admodum utilis super artem veterem edita per venerabilem inceptorem fratrem Gullielmum de Ockham cum quaestionibus Alberti parvi de Saxonia, BolognaGoogle Scholar
Albert, Saxony (1522). Perutilis logica, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Augustine, (1877). De magistro, PL 32Google Scholar
Boehner, Philotheus (1946). ‘The Realistic Conceptualism of William Ockham’, Traditio 4:.Google Scholar
Boehner, Philotheus (1951b). ‘Does Ockham Know of Material Implication?’, Franciscan Studies 11:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boehner, Philotheus (1952). Medieval Logic: An Outline of Its Development from 1250–c. 1400, Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
Boethius, (1877). Commentarii in librum Aristotelis ΠEPI EPMHNEIAΣ pars prior versionem continuam et primam editionem continens, ed. Meiser, Carl, TeubnerGoogle Scholar
Boethius, (1880). Commentarii in librum Aristotelis ΠEPI EPMHNEIAΣ pars posterior secundam editionem et indices continens, ed. Meiser, Carl, TeubnerGoogle Scholar
Boethius, (1918). De trinitate in Tractates, De consolatione philosophiae, ed. Stewart, H. F. and Rand, E. K. (Loeb Classical Library), William Heinemann, LtdGoogle Scholar
Brown, Stephen F. (1972). ‘Walter Burleigh's Treatise De suppositionibus and Its Influence on William of Ockham’, Franciscan Studies 32:.Google Scholar
Brown, Stephen F. (1973) ‘Walter Burleigh's Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Perihermeneias’, Franciscan Studies 33 :Google Scholar
Brown, Stephen F. (1974). ‘Walter Burley's Quaestiones in librum Perihermeneias’, Franciscan Studies 34:Google Scholar
Buridan, (1957) ‘Giovanni Buridano: “Tractatus de suppositionibus”‘, ed. Reina, Maria Elena, Rivista critica di storia delta filosqfia 12: ;Google Scholar
Ferrer, Vincent (1909). De suppositionibus dialecticis (Oeuvres de Saint Vincent Ferrier, Fages, H. (ed.), Vol. 1), A. Picard et filsGoogle Scholar
Ferrer, Vincent (1977). Tractatus de suppositionibus, Trentman, J. A. (ed.) (Grammatica speculativa, 2), Frommann-HolzboogGoogle Scholar
Grabmann, Martin (1937). Bearbeitungen und Auslegungen der aristotelischen Logik aus der Zeit von Peter Abaelard bis Petrus Hispanus. Mitteilungen aus Handschriften deutscher Bibliotheken (Abhandlungen der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-hist. Klasse, 5)Google Scholar
Henry, Desmond Paul (1964). The De grammatico of St Anselm: Theory of Paronymy (Publications in Mediaeval Studies, 18), University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Henry, Desmond Paul (1967). The Logic of Saint Anselm, Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Henry, Ghent (1974). ‘The absolute and the ordained powers of the pope’, ed. Marrone, John, Mediaeval Studies 36:Google Scholar
John, Buridan (1966). Sophisms on Meaning and Truth, tr. Scott, T. K., Appleton-Century-CroftsGoogle Scholar
John, Buridan (1977). Johannes Buridanus: Sophismata, ed. Scott, T. K. (Grammatica Speculativa, 1), Frommann-HolzboogGoogle Scholar
John, Duns Scotus (1639a). Opera omnia, ed. Wadding, L. (12 vols.). Lyons (Reprinted Georg Olms 1968)Google Scholar
Kneale, William and Martha, (1962). The Development of Logic, Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Lambert, Auxerre (1971). Logica (Summa Lamberti), ed. Alessio, F. (Pubblicazioni della facoltà di lettere e filosofta dell'Università di Milano, 59), La Nuova Italia EditriceGoogle Scholar
Maierù, A.(1972). Terminologia logica della tarda scolastica (Lessico intellettuale europeo, 8), Edizioni dell' AteneoGoogle Scholar
Moody, Ernest A. (1935). The Logic of William of Ockham, Sheed & WardGoogle Scholar
Moody, Ernest A. (1953) Truth and Consequence in Mediaeval Logic (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics), North-HollandGoogle Scholar
Nuchelmans, Gabriel (1973). Theories of the Proposition: Ancient and Medieval Conceptions of the Bearers of Truth and Falsity (North-Holland Linguistic Series, 8), North-HollandGoogle Scholar
Paul, Pergula (1961). Logica and Tractatus de sensu composito et diviso, ed. Brown, Mary Anthony (Franciscan Institute Text Series, 13) The Franciscan InstituteGoogle Scholar
Peter, Abelard (1919–27). Logica ‘Ingredientibus’, ed. Geyer, Bernhard in Peter Abaelards Philosophische Schriften (BGPM, XXI), AschendorffGoogle Scholar
Peter, Abelard (1970a). Dialectica, ed. Rijk, L. M. (Wijsgerige teksten en studies, 1) (2nd ed.), Van GorcumGoogle Scholar
Peter, Ailly (1489). Tractatus de arte obligandi, ParisGoogle Scholar
Peter, Ailly (1980). Concepts and Insolubles: An Annotated Translation, Spade, Paul Vincent (tr.) (Synthese Historical Library, vol. 19), D. ReidelGoogle Scholar
Priscian, (1855–9). Institutionsgrammaticae, ed. Hertz, Martin (Grammatici Latini), Teubner (Reprinted Georg Olms 1961)Google Scholar
Reina, Maria Elena (1959). ‘Il problema del linguaggio in Buridano I: Voci e concetti’, Rivista critica di storia della filosofia 14:.Google Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1962–7). Logica modernorum: A contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic. I: On the Twelfth Century Theories of Fallacy (1962); II, 1: The Origin and Early Development of the Theory of Supposition; II, 2: Texts and Indices (1967), Van GorcumGoogle Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1971–3). ‘The Development of Suppositio naturalis in Mediaeval Logic’, Vivarium 9:.; 11:.Google Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1972). Peter of Spain (Petrus Hispanus Portugalensis) Tractatus called afterwards ‘Summule Logicales’, Van GorcumGoogle Scholar
Roger, Bacon (1940). Sumule dialectices, ed Steele, Robert, in Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi, fasc. 15, Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Schepers, H. (1972). ‘Holkot contra dicta Crathorn II: Das “significatum per propositionem”. Aufbau und Kritik einer nominalistischen Theorie über den Gegenstand des Wissens’, Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Görres-Gesellschaft 79:.Google Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1974a). ‘Five Logical Tracts by Richard Lavenham’, in O'Donnell, J. Reginald (ed.), Essays in Honour of Anton Charles Pegis, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval StudiesGoogle Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1974b). ‘Ockham on Self-Reference’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1974c). ‘Ockham's Rule of Supposition: Two Conflicts in His Theory’, Vivarium 12:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1975b). ‘Notes on Some Manuscripts of Logical and Physical Works by Richard Lavenham’, Manuscripta 19:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1975c). ‘Ockham's Distinctions between Absolute and Connotative Terms’, Vivarium 13:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swiezawski, S. (1934). ‘Les intentions premiers et les intentions secondes chez Jean Duns Scot’, Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 9:Google Scholar
Swiniarski, John J. (1970). ‘A New Presentation of Ockham's Theory of Supposition with an Evaluation of Some Contemporary Criticisms’, Franciscan Studies 30:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walter, Burley (1955). De Puritate Artis Logicae Tractatus Longior, ed. Boehner, P. (Franciscan Institute Publications, Text series, No. 9), The Franciscan InstituteGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1974a). Opera philosophica [OP] I: Summa logicae, ed. Boehner, P., Gál, G., and Brown, S., in Ockham, William 1967–Google Scholar
William, Ockham (1974c). Consultatio de causa matrimoniali, ed. Offler, H. S., Guillelmi de Ockham Opera politica, 1 (rev. edn.), Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1974e). Ockham's Theory of Terms: Part 1 of the Summa logicae, translated with introduction and essays by Loux, Michael J., University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
William, Ockham (1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, tr. with introduction and notes by Kretzmann, Norman, University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
William, Sherwood (1937), Introductiones in logicam, ed. Grabmann, M. (Sitzungsberichte der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-hist. Abteilung 1937, 10), Verlag der Bayerischen Akademie der WissenschaftenGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×