Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-05T05:16:22.577Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

15 - Implicatures

from Part VIII - Implying and (Pre)supposing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Daniel Altshuler
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

In a seminal contribution, Paul Grice took what he called the ‘total signification of an utterance’ (i.e. the complete content someone communicates by a linguistic signal) and divided it in two, distinguishing between ‘what the speaker says’ versus ‘what the speaker implies’. However, recent developments have served to throw doubt on Grice’s taxonomy, with both sides of his divide coming under fire. I examine these challenges to Grice’s framework, but argue that they do not show that Grice’s notion of implicature is ill-founded, nor that his ’favoured sense’ of what is said is unnecessary. What they do serve to highlight is a peculiar tension in Grice’s original account. For it seems Grice merged two distinct features when defining what the speaker says versus what the speaker implicates: the idea of a content dictated by word meaning and structure alone, on the one hand, and the idea of an asserted or directly expressed proposition on the other. Yet once we resolve this tension it is possible to deliver an account of the total signification of an utterance which is both (fairly) faithful to Grice’s original account and which is able to do a great deal of explanatory work.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bach, K. (1994). Semantic slack: What is said and more. In Tsohatzidis, S. (Ed.), Foundations of Speech Act Theory: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives (pp. 267291). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bach, K. (1999). The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22, 327366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, E. (2004). Minimal Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Borg, E. (2007). Minimalism versus contextualism in semantics. In Preyer, G. & Peter, G. (Eds.), Context-Sensitivity and Semantic Minimalism: New Essays on Semantics and Pragmatics (pp. 546571). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in M. Ezcurdia & R. Stainton (Eds.), (2013), The Semantics–Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. New York: Broadview.Google Scholar
Borg, E. (2012). Pursuing Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Borg, E. (2016). Exploding explicatures. Mind & Language, 31, 335355.Google Scholar
Borg, E. (2017). Explanatory roles for minimal content. Nous. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, E., Scarafone, A., Shardimgaliev, M. 2021. ‘Meaning and Communication’, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/meaning-and-communication/Google Scholar
Borg, E., & Connolly, P. (2022). Exploring linguistic liability. In Lepore, E. & Sosa, D. (Eds), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Language, Vol. 2 (pp. 126). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Camp, E. (2006). Contextualism, metaphor, and what is said. Mind & Language, 21, 280309.Google Scholar
Camp, E. (2012). Sarcasm, pretense, and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Nous, 46, 587634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and Utterances. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Carston, R., & Hall, A. (2012). Implicature and explicature. In Schmid, H. J. (Ed.), Cognitive Pragmatics, Vol. 4 (pp. 4784). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Collins, J. (2007). Syntax, more or less. Mind, 116, 805850.Google Scholar
Danzer, L. (2020). The explanatory project of Gricean pragmatics. Mind & Language, 36, 683706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, W. (1998). Implicature: Intention, Convention, and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldberg, S. (2015). Assertion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Green, M. (2018). Showing, expressing and figuratively meaning. In Preyer, G. (Ed.), Beyond Semantics and Pragmatics (pp. 157173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haugh, M. (2013). Implicature, inference and cancellability. In Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., & Carapezza, M. (Eds.), Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Hirschberg, J. (1991). A Theory of Scalar Implicature. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Horn, L. (1972). On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators in English. PhD thesis, University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Ladusaw, W. (1979). Polarity as Inherent Scope Relations. PhD thesis, University of Texas at Austin.Google Scholar
Martí, L. (2006). Unarticulated constituents revisited. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29(2), 135166.Google Scholar
Potts, C. (2005). The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2014). Imagination and Convention: Distinguishing Grammar and Inference in Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Michaelson, E. (2016). The lying test. Mind & Language, 31, 470499.Google Scholar
Neale, S. (2007). Heavy hands, magic, and scene-reading traps. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3, 77132.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (2010). Truth-Conditional Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rett, J. (2020). Manner implicatures and how to spot them. International Review of Pragmatics, 12, 4479.Google Scholar
Rothschild, D., & Segal, G. (2009). Indexical predicates. Mind & Language, 24, 467493.Google Scholar
Saul, J. (2001). Wayne Davis, “Implicature: Intention, Convention, and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory” (Book Review). Nous, 35, 630641.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saul, J. (2013). Lying, Misleading, and the Role of What Is Said. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1980). The background of meaning. In Searle, J., Keifer, F., & Bierwisch, M. (Eds.), Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics (pp. 221232). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Soames, S. (2009). Philosophical Essays, Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D.. (1986). Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stainton, R., & Viger, C. (2018). Two questions about interpretive effects. In Preyer, G. (Ed.), Semantics, Pragmatics and Interpretation (pp. 931). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. (2002). Making it articulated. Mind & Language, 17, 149168.Google Scholar
Stanley, J., & Gendler Szabó, Z. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind & Language, 15, 219261.Google Scholar
Sullivan, A. (2017). Evaluating the cancellability test. Journal of Pragmatics, 121, 162174.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. (2012). The case for compositionality. In Hinzen, W., Machery, E., & Werning, M. (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook on Compositionality (pp. 6480). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. (2016). In defense of indirect communication. Inquiry, 59, 163174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Travis, C. (1996). Meaning’s role in truth. Mind, 105, 451466.Google Scholar
Travis, C. (1997). Pragmatics. In Hale, B. & Wright, C. (Eds.), Companion to the Philosophy of Language (pp. 87107). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Txurruka, I. G. (2003). The natural language conjunction and. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 255285.Google Scholar
von Fintel, Kai (1994). Restrictions on Quantifier Domains. PhD Dissertation, Graduate Student Linguistics Association (GLSA), University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Weiner, M. (2006). Are all conversational implicatures cancellable? Analysis, 66, 127130.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Implicatures
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.024
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Implicatures
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.024
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Implicatures
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.024
Available formats
×