Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T23:16:12.774Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

45 - Noncognitivism: From the Vienna Circle to the Present Day

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 December 2017

Sacha Golob
Affiliation:
King's College London
Jens Timmermann
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews, Scotland
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ayer, A.J. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic, 2nd edn. London: Victor Gollancz.Google Scholar
Ayer, A.J. 1984. Freedom, Morality and Other Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Björklund, F., Björnsson, G., Eriksson, J., Francén Olinder, R., and Strandberg, C. 2012. “Recent Work: Motivational Internalism,” Analysis 72: 124–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Björnsson, G. 2002. “How Emotivism Survives Immoralists, Irrationality, and Depression,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 40: 327–44.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G., and McPherson, T. 2014. “Moral Attitudes for Non-Cognitivists: Solving the Specification Problem,” Mind 123: 138.*CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1971. “Moral Realism,” reprinted in Blackburn 1993: 111–29.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1984. Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1988. “Attitudes and Contents,” reprinted in Blackburn 1993: 182–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1993. Essays in Quasi-Realism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1998. Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 1988. “How to Be a Moral Realist,” in Sayre-McCord, G. (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 181228.Google Scholar
Brink, D.O. 1989. Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Broad, C.D. 1933–4. “Is ‘Goodness’ a Name of a Simple Non-natural Quality?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 34: 249–68.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1935. Philosophy and Logical Syntax. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., and Railton, P. 1992. “Toward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends,” Philosophical Review 101: 115–89.*Google Scholar
Dreier, J. 2004. “Meta-Ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism,” Philosophical Perspectives 18 (Ethics): 2344.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eriksson, J. 2009. “Homage to Hare: Ecumenism and the Frege–Geach Problem,” Ethics 120: 835.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eriksson, J. 2014. “Elaborating Expressivism: Moral Judgments, Desires and Motivation,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 243–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eriksson, J. 2016. “Expressivism, Attitudinal Complexity and Two Senses of Disagreement in Attitude,” Erkenntnis 81: 775–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankena, W.K. 1939. “The Naturalistic Fallacy,” Mind 48: 464–77.Google Scholar
Geach, P. 1960. “Ascriptivism,” Philosophical Review 69: 221–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. 1965. “Assertion,” Philosophical Review 74: 449–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1993. “Reply to Sinnot-Armstrong,” Philosophical Studies 69: 315–28.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hägerström, A. 1911. “On the Truth of Moral Propositions,” in Philosophy and Religion, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1964, pp. 7796.Google Scholar
Hale, B. 1993. “Can there Be a Logic of Attitudes?” in Haldane, J. and Wright, C. (eds.), Reality, Representation, and Projection. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 337–63.Google Scholar
Hale, B. 2002. “Can Arboreal Knotwork Help Blackburn Out of Frege’s Abyss?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 144–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, R.M. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, R.M. 1970. “Meaning and Speech Acts,” Philosophical Review 79: 324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T., and Timmons, M. 1992a. “Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The ‘Open Question Argument’ Revived,” Philosophical Papers 21: 153–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T., and Timmons, M. 1992b. “Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness Revived,” Syntheses 92: 224–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T., and Timmons, M. 2006. “Cognitivist Expressivism,” in Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (eds.), Metaethics after Moore. Oxford University Press, pp. 255–98.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 1990. Truth. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1739–1740. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Norton, D.F. and Norton, M.J.. Oxford University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia Ethica, ed. Baldwin, T.. Cambridge University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Ogden, C.K., and Richards, I.A. 1923. The Meaning of Meaning: A Study of the Influence of Language upon Thought and of the Science of Symbolism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 2011. On What Matters. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Perry, R.B. 1926. General Theory of Value: Its Meaning and Basic Principles Construed in Terms of Interest. New York: Longmans, Green and Co.Google Scholar
Prichard, H.A. 1912. “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?Mind 81: 2137.Google Scholar
Ridge, M. 2006. “Ecumenical Expressivism: Finessing Frege,” Ethics 116: 302–37.Google Scholar
Ridge, M. 2013. “Disagreement,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86: 4163.Google Scholar
Ridge, M. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W.D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W.D. 1939. Foundations of Ethics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1935. Religion and Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Satris, S. 1987. Ethical Emotivism. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2008. Being For: Evaluating the Semantic Program of Expressivism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2009. “Hybrid Expressivism: Virtues and Vices,” Ethics 119: 257309.Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2010. Noncognitivism in Ethics. London: Routledge.*Google Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2013. “Tempered Expressivism,” in Shafer-Landau, R., ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 8, Oxford University Press, pp. 283314.Google Scholar
Schueler, G.F. 1988. “Modus Ponens and Moral Realism,” Ethics 98: 492500.Google Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1962. “Meaning and Speech Acts,” Philosophical Review 71: 423–32.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 2002. “Evaluation, Uncertainty, and Motivation,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5: 305320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, C.L. 1937. “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms,” reprinted in Stevenson 1963: 1031.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C.L. 1944. Ethics and Language. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C.L. 1963. Facts and Values: Studies in Ethical Analysis. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Tersman, F. 2006. Moral Disagreement. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Toppinen, T. 2013. “Believing in Expressivism,” in Shafer-Landau, R., ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 8, Oxford University Press, pp. 253–82.Google Scholar
Unwin, N. 1999. “Quasi-Realism, Negation and the Frege–Geach Problem,” Philosophical Quarterly 49: 337–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unwin, N. 2001. “Norms and Negation: A Problem for Gibbard’s Logic,” Philosophical Quarterly 51: 6075.Google Scholar
Urmson, J.O. 1968. The Emotive Theory of Ethics. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
van Roojen, M. 1996. “Expressivism and Irrationality,” Philosophical Review 105: 311–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Roojen, M. 2015. Metaethics: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge.*Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×