Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-dfsvx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T07:33:44.919Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 July 2009

Yujin Nagasawa
Affiliation:
University of Birmingham
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
God and Phenomenal Consciousness
A Novel Approach to Knowledge Arguments
, pp. 147 - 158
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abbruzzese, John E. 1997. ‘The Coherence of Omniscience: A Defense’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 41: 25–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Marilyn McCord, and Adams, Robert Merrihew, ed. 1990. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Akins, Kathleen. 1993a. ‘A Bat Without Qualities?’ In Davies and Humphreys (1993), pp. 258–273.
Akins, Kathleen. 1993b. ‘What Is It Like To Be Boring and Myopic?’ In Dahlbom, Bo, ed., Dennett and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 124–160.Google Scholar
Alston, William. 1987. ‘Does God Have Beliefs?’ Religious Studies 22: 287–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 1998. ‘A Limited Defence of the Knowledge Argument’. Philosophical Studies 90: 35–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 1999. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In A Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind. Http://host.uniroma3.it/progetti/kant/field/ka.html.Google Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2001. ‘Know-How, Ability, and the Ability Hypothesis’. Theoria 67: 229–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2002a. ‘Nagel on Imagination and Physicalism’. Journal of Philosophical Research 27: 143–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2002b. ‘On Two Alleged Conflicts Between Divine Attributes’. Faith and Philosophy 19: 47–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2006. ‘The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism’. In Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Http://www.iep.utm.edu/k/know-arg.htm.Google Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2007. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In Velmans, Max and Schneider, Susan, eds., The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 396–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin, and Walter, Sven. 2006. Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, C. Anthony. 1984. ‘Divine Omnipotence and Impossible Tasks: An Intensional Analysis’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 15: 109–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1967 (originally 1265–1274). Summa theologiae, Thomas Gilby, trans. London: Eyre and Spottiswoode.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1975 (originally 1258–1264). Summa contra gentiles, James F. Anderson trans. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. Excerpt reprinted in Stump, Eleonore and Murray, Michael J., eds., Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), pp. 7–9. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1997 (originally the 13th century). Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Pegis, Anton C., ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Balog, Katalin. 1999. ‘Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind-Body Problem’. Philosophical Review 108: 497–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bealer, George. 2002. ‘Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance’. In Gendler, Tamar Szabó and Hawthorne, John, eds., Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 71–125.Google Scholar
Beall, J. C. 2000. ‘A Neglected Response to the Grim Result’. Analysis 60: 38–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaty, Michael, and Taliaferro, Charles. 1990. ‘God and Concept Empiricism’. Southwest Philosophy Review 6: 97–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beyer, Jason A. 2004. ‘A Physicalist Rejoinder to Some Problems with Omniscience; or How God Could Know What We Know’. Sophia 43: 5–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beyer, Jason A. 2006. ‘Reply to Nagasawa’. Sophia 45: 127–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, John, and Pargetter, Robert. 1990. ‘Acquaintance with Qualia’. Theoria 61: pp. 129–147. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 179–195.Google Scholar
Bishop, John. 1993. ‘Evil and the Concept of God’. Philosophical Papers 22: 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, John. 1998. ‘Can There Be Alternative Concepts of God?’ NoÛs 98: 174–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1992. ‘Filling in Space’. Analysis 50: 62–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Ned, and Stalnaker, Robert. 1999. ‘Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap’. Philosophical Review 108: 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Ned, Flanagan, Owen, and Güven Güzeldere, , eds. 1997. The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Blumenfeld, David. 1978. ‘On the Compossibility of the Divine Attributes’. Philosophical Studies 34: 91–103. Reprinted in Morris, Thomas V., ed., The Concept of God(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 201–215. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David. 2003. ‘Qualia and Analytical Conditionals’. Journal of Philosophy 100: 111–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Jackson, Frank. 1996. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bringsjord, Selmer. 1989. ‘Grim on Logic and Omniscience’. Analysis 49: 186–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Campbell, and Nagasawa, Yujin. 2005. ‘Anything You Can Do God Can Do Better’. American Philosophical Quarterly 42: 221–227.Google Scholar
Burke, Michael B. 1987. ‘Theodicy with a God of Limited Power: A Reply to McGrath’. Analysis 47: 57–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cain, James. 1989. ‘The Doctrine of the Trinity and the Logic of Relative Identity’. Religious Studies 25: 141–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, Peter. 2005. Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Richard. 1987. ‘On the Logical Problem of the Trinity’. In Cartwright, Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: MIT Press), pp. 187–200.Google Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri. 1967. ‘Omniscience and Indexical Reference’. Journal of Philosophy 64: 203–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1995. ‘The Puzzle of Conscious Experience’. Scientific American 237: 80–86. Reprinted in Inwagen, Peter and Zimmerman, Dean W., eds., Metaphysics: The Big Questions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), pp. 333–341. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1999. ‘Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Studies 59: 473–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 2002a. ‘Consciousness and Its Place in Nature’. In Stich, Stephen and Warfield, Ted, eds., Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 102–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 2002b. ‘Imagination, Indexicality and Intensions’. Http://www.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/papers/perry.html.
Chalmers, David J. 2004. ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 269–298.
Churchland, Paul M. 1985a. ‘Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States’. Journal of Philosophy 82: 8–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1985b. ‘Review of Robinson's Matter and Sense’. Philosophical Review 94: 117–120.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1989. ‘Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson’. In Churchland, , A Neurocomputational Perspective (Cambridge: MIT Press), pp. 67–76. Reprinted in Block et al. (1997), pp. 571–577. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1996. Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Conee, Earl. 1991. ‘The Possibility of Power Beyond Possibility’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 5: Philosophy of Religion (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview).Google Scholar
Conee, Earl. 1994. ‘Phenomenal Knowledge’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72: 136–50. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 197–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Côté, Antoine. 1998. ‘God and the Principle of Non-Contradiction’. International Philosophical Quarterly 38: 285–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim. 1993. ‘A Definition of Physicalism: Reply to Pettit’. Analysis 53: 224–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim, and Mellor, D. H.. 1990. ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’. Mind 99: 185–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Creel, Richard E. 1986. Divine Impassibility: An Essay in Philosophical Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger 1986. ‘The Avoidance of the Problem of Evil: A Reply to McGrath’. Analysis 46: 160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daly, Chris. 1998. ‘Modality and Acquaintance with Properties’. The Monist 81: 44–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1987. ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60: 441–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin, and Humphreys, Glyn W., eds. 1993. Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davis, Stephen T. 1983. Logic and the Nature of God. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 2006. ‘What RoboMary Knows’. In Alter and Walter (2006).
Descartes, René. 1970 (originally the 17th century. Philosophical Letters, Kenny, Anthony, ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Downey, James Patrick. 1993. ‘On Omniscience’. Faith and Philosophy 10: 230–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Eccles, J. C. 1985. ‘Mental Summation: The Timing of Voluntary Intentions by Cortical Activity’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8: 542–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eccles, J. C. 1994. How the Self Controls Its Brain. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Endicott, Ronald P. 1995. ‘Refutation by Analogous Ectoqualia’. Southern Journal of Philosophy 33: 19–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etzkorn, Gerald, and Kelly, Francis, eds. 1979. Ockham: Opera Theologica, vol. 4. St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute.Google Scholar
Fiddes, Paul S. 1992. The Creative Suffering of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, Owen. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Flint, Thomas P., and Alfred J. Freddoso. 1983. ‘Maximal Power’. In Freddoso, Alfred J., ed., The Existence and Nature of God (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press), pp. 81–113.Google Scholar
Forrest, Peter. 1994. ‘Inherited Responsibility, Karma and Original Sin’. Sophia 33: 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, Peter. 2007. Developmental Theism: From Pure Will to Unbounded Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foss, Jeff E. 1989. ‘On the Logic of What It Is Like To Be a Conscious Subject’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67: 305–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foss, Jeff E. 1993. ‘Subjectivity, Objectivity, and Nagel on Consciousness’. Dialogue 32: 725–736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, John. 1991. Immaterial Self. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Francks, Richard. 1979. ‘Omniscience, Omnipotence and Pantheism’. Philosophy 54: 395–399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1964. ‘The Logic of Omnipotence’. Philosophical Review 73: 262–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1977. ‘Descartes on the Creation of the Eternal Truths’. Philosophical Review 86: 36–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, Richard. 2004. ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance vs. Description’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2004 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/knowledge-acquaindescrip.
Gale, Richard M. 1991. On the Nature of Existence of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gale, Richard M. 2003. ‘A Response to My Critics’. Philo 6: 132–165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, Peter. 1973. ‘Omnipotence’. Philosophy 48: 7–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, Peter. 1977. Providence and Evil. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabo, and Hawthorne, John, eds. 2002. Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gertler, Brie. 2003. ‘Self-Knowledge’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2003 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/self-knowledge.
Goldstick, D. 1990. ‘Could God Make a Contradiction True?’ Religious Studies 26: 377–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorman, Michael. 2005. ‘Nagasawa vs. Nagel: Omnipotence, Pseudo-Task, and a Recent Discussion of Nagel's Doubt About Physicalism’. Inquiry 48: 436–447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1983. ‘Some Neglected Problems of Omniscience’. American Philosophical Quarterly 20: 265–276.Google Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1984. ‘There Is No Set of All Truths’. Analysis 44: 206–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1985. ‘Against Omniscience: The Case from Essential Indexicals’. NoÛs 19: 151–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1986. ‘On Sets and Worlds: A Reply to Menzel’. Analysis 46: 186–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1990. ‘On Omniscience and a “Set of All Truths”: A Reply to Bringsjord’. Analysis 50: 271–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1991. The Incomplete Universe: Totality, Knowledge and Truth. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 2000. ‘The Being That Knew Too Much’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 47: 141–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 2007. ‘Impossibility Arguments’. In Martin, M., eds., Cambridge Companion to Atheism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 199–214.Google Scholar
Groarke, Louis. 2001. ‘Reconsidering Absolute Omnipotence’. The Heythrop Journal 42: 13–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haksar, Vinit. 1981. ‘Nagel on Subjective and Objective’. Inquiry 24: 105–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1969. ‘Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets’. In Morgenbesser, Sidney, Suppes, Patrick, and White, Morton, eds., Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel (New York: St. Martin's Press), pp. 179–199.Google Scholar
Hill, Daniel. 1998. ‘What's New in Philosophy of Religion?’ Philosophy Now 21: 30–33.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary. 1980. ‘What an Omnipotent Agent Can Do’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11: 1–19.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 1984. ‘Swinburne on Omnipotence’. Sophia 23: 36–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 1988. ‘Omnipotence Redux’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49: 283–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 2002. The Divine Attributes. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Gary S. Rosenkrantz. 2006. ‘Omnipotence’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2006 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/omnipotence.
Horgan, Terence. 1984. ‘Jackson on Physical Information and Qualia’. Philosophical Quarterly 34: 147–52. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 301–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, David. 2000. ‘Omniscience and Cognitive Power’. Unpublished manuscript.
Hutcheson, Peter. 1992. ‘Omniscience and the Problem of Evil’. Sophia 31: 53–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1982. ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’. Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 39–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1986. ‘What Mary Didn't Know’. Journal of Philosophy 83: 291–295. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), 51–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1995. ‘Postscript’. In Moser, Paul K. and Trout, J. D., eds., Contemporary Materialism (London: Routledge), pp. 184–189. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 409–415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998a. From Metaphysics to Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998b. ‘Postscript on Qualia’. In Jackson, Mind, Method and Conditionals (London: Routledge), pp. 76–79. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 417–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 2003. ‘Mind and Illusion’. In O'Hear (2003), pp. 251–271.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 2004. ‘Looking Back on the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 421–442.
Johnston, Mark. 1992. ‘How to Speak of the Colors’. Philosophical Studies 68: 221–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, Mark. 1996. ‘Mind-Body Problem at the Surface of Objects’. Philosophical Issues 7: 219–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John. 1977. ‘Physicalism and Subjectivity’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37: 533–536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. 1979. The God of the Philosophers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Khamara, E. J. 1978. ‘In Defense of Omnipotence’. Philosophical Quarterly 28: 215–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, Robet. 2005. Zombies and Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knight, Gordon. 2005. ‘The Theological Significance of Subjectivity’. The Heythrop Journal 46: 1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman. 1966. ‘Omniscience and Immutability’. Journal of Philosophy 63: 409–421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan. 1986. The Possibility of An All-Knowing God. New York: St. Martin's Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachs, John. 1963a. ‘Omniscience’. Dialogue 1: 400–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachs, John. 1963b. ‘Professor Prior on Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 361–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1977. ‘The Hidden Assumption in the Paradox of Omnipotence’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38: 125–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1978. ‘Failing to Define “Omnipotence”. Philosophical Studies 34: 219–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1984. ‘Descartes on God's Ability to Do the Logically Impossible’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14: 455–475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae. 1998. Kantian Humility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Langton, Rae. 2004. ‘Elusive Knowledge of Things in Themselves’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 129–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, Gottfried. 1966 (originally 1710). Theodicy, E. M. Huggard, trans. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Levine, Joseph. 2001. Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1979. ‘Attitudes De Dicto and De Se’. Philosophical Review 88: 513–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. ‘Postscript to “Mad Pain and Martian Pain”’. In Lewis, , Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1988. ‘What Experience Teaches’. In Copley-Coltherart, J., ed., Proceedings of the Russellian Society (Sydney: University of Sydney). Reprinted in Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 447–461. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1997. ‘Finkish Dispositions’. Philosophical Quarterly 47: 143–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 2001. ‘Ramseyan Humility’. Preprint Series 1/01. Department of Philosophy, University of Melbourne.Google Scholar
Lloyd, A. C. 1970. ‘Non-Discursive Thought: An Enigma of Greek Philosophy’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 70: 261–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, Brian. 1990. ‘Phenomenal States’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 4: Action Theory and the Philosophy of Mind (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview), pp. 81–108.Google Scholar
Loar, Brian. 1997. ‘Phenomenal States (Revised Version)’. In Block et al. (1997), pp. 597–616. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 219–239.
Lockwood, Michael. 1989. Mind, Brain, and the Quantum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ludlow, Peter. 1995. ‘Indexical Knowledge and the Possibility of an Omniscient Being’. In Stewart, M. and Clandenon, D., eds., Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Religion (Moscow: Progress Press).Google Scholar
Ludlow, Peter, Nagasawa, Yujin, and Stoljar, Daniel. 2004. There's Something About Mary: Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson's Knowledge Argument. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 2003. ‘Perspectival Representation and the Knowledge Argument’. In Smith, Quentin and Jokic, Aleksandar, eds., Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Clarendon Press), pp. 384–395.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1955. ‘Evil and Omnipotence’. Mind 64: 200–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism: Arguments for and Against the Existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Macnamara, John, Reyes, Marie, and Reyes, Gonzalo. 1994. ‘Logic and the Trinity’. Faith and Philosophy 11: 3–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mander, William J. 2002. ‘Does God Know What It Is Like to Be Me?’ The Heythrop Journal 43: 430–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, William E. 1975. ‘The Divine Attributes’. American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 151–159.Google Scholar
Mar, Gary. 1993. ‘Why ‘Cantorian’ Arguments Against the Existence of God Do Not Work’. International Philosophical Quarterly 33: 429–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Michael. 1970. ‘A Disproof of God's Existence’. Darshana 10: 22–26.Google Scholar
Martin, Michael. 1974. ‘A Disproof of the God of the Common Man’. Question 7: 115–124. Reprinted in Martin and Monnier (2003), pp. 232–241. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Martin Michael. 1990. ‘Conflicts Between the Divine Attributes’. In Martin, , Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Philadelphia: Temple University Press). Reprinted in Martin and Monnier (2003), pp. 242–257. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Martin, Michael. 2000. ‘Omniscience and Incoherency’. In Holmstrom-Hintikka, Ghita, ed., Medieval Philosophy and Modern Times (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic), pp. 17–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Michael, and Monnier, Ricki, eds. 2003. The Impossibility of God. Amherst and New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1963. ‘Some Puzzles Concerning Omnipotence’. Philosophical Review 72: 221–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1977. ‘Defining Omnipotence’. Philosophical Studies 32: 191–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1988. ‘How Does God Know the Things He Knows’. In Morris, Thomas V., ed., Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism (Ithaca, N. Y., Cornell University Press), pp. 345–361.Google Scholar
Mawson, T. J. 2002. ‘Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection Are Compatible: A Reply to Morriston’. Religious Studies 38: 215–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, Grover. 1979. ‘Rigid Designators and Mind-Brain Identity’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9: 365–403.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1989. ‘Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?’ Mind 98: 349–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1991. The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Toward a Resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1999. Mysterious Flame. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 2004. Consciousness and Its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, P. J. 1986. ‘Evil and the Existence of a Finite God’. Analysis 46: 63–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, P. J. 1987. ‘Children of a Lesser God?: A Reply to Burke and Crisp’. Analysis 47: 236–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullen, Carolyn. 1985. ‘“Knowing What It's Like” and the Essential Indexical’. Philosophical Studies 48: 211–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, John Ellis. 1906. Some Dogmas of Religion. London: Edward Arnold.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1993. ‘Nothing Like Experience’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 63: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menzel, Christopher. 1986. ‘On Set Theoretic Possible Worlds’. Analysis 46: 68–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Leonard G. 1957. ‘Descartes, Mathematics, and God’. Philosophical Review 66. 451–465.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montero, Barbara. 2006. ‘Physicalism in an Infinitely Decomposable World’. Erkenntnis 64: 177–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, A. W. 1997. Points of View. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. 2003. ‘The Knowledge Argument Revisited’. International Journal for Philosophical Quarterly 43: 219–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1986a. The Logic of God Incarnate. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1986b. ‘Reduplication and Representational Christology’. Modern Theology 2: 319–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1991. Our Idea of God: An Introduction to Christian Theology. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press.Google Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2001a. ‘Omnipotence and the Anselmian God’. Philo 4: 7–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2001b. ‘Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection: Are They Compatible?’ Religious Studies 37: 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2002. ‘Omnipotence and the Power to Choose: A Reply to Wielenberg’. Faith and Philosophy 19: 358–367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2003. ‘Are Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection Compatible?: Reply to Mawson: Are They Compatible?’ Religious Studies 39: 441–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mozley, J. K. 1926. The Impassibility of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, Nancy. 2006. Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2002. ‘The Knowledge Argument Against Dualism’. Theoria 68: 205–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003a. ‘Divine Omniscience and Experience: A Reply to Alter’. Ars Disputandi 3. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000098/index.html.Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003b. ‘Divine Omniscience and Knowledge De Se’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 53: 73–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003c. ‘God's Point of View: A Reply to Mander’. The Heythrop Journal 44: 60–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003d. ‘Thomas vs. Thomas: A New Approach to Nagel's Bat Argument’. Inquiry 46: 377–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2006. ‘Physicalism and Omniscience: A Reply to Beyer’. Sophia 44: 55–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2007a. ‘A Further Reply to Beyer on Omniscience’. Sophia 46: 65–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2007b. ‘The “Most Powerful” Response to the Knowledge Argument’. Unpublished manuscript, University of Birmingham.
Nagasawa, Yujin. Forthcoming. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In Tim Bayne, Axel Cleeremans, and Patrick Wilken, eds., The Oxford Companion to Consciousness.
Nagel, Thomas. 1974. ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat’. Philosophical Review 83: 435–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nemirow, Lawrence. 1980. ‘Review of Nagel's Mortal Questions’. Philosophical Review 89: 473–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nemirow, Lawrence. 1990. ‘Physicalism and the Cognitive Role of Acquaintance’. In Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Ngien, Dennis. 1997. ‘The God Who Suffers’. Christian Today, February 3.Google Scholar
O'Hear, Anthony, ed. 2003. Mind and Persons: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David. 2002. Thinking About Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, Derek. 1994. ‘Bats, Brain Scientists, and the Limitation of Introspection’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 315–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, John. 1979. ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’. NoÛs 13: 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, John. 2001. Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Peterson, Michael L., ed. 1992. The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1993. ‘A Definition of Physicalism’. Analysis 53: 213–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2004. ‘Motion Blindness and the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 105–142.
Pike, Nelson. 1969. ‘Omnipotence and God's Ability to Sin’. American Philosophical Quarterly 6: 208–216.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1967. God and Other Minds. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1980a. Does God Have a Nature?Milwaukee, Wisc.: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1980b. God, Freedom and Evil. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1989. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, and Grim, Patrick. 1993. Philosophical Studies 71: 267–306.CrossRef
Post, John F.. 2003. ‘Omniscience, Weak PSR and Method’. Philo 6: pp. 33–48. Http://www.vanderbilt.edu/~postjf/OmWpsrMeth7.02nc.htm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Post, John F. 2004. ‘Reply to Gale and Pruss’. Philo 7: 114–121. Http://www.vanderbilt.edu/~postjf/gale&pruss.htm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1962. ‘The Formalities of Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 114–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1963. ‘Rejoinder to Professor Lachs on Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 365–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pruss, Alexander R. 2003. ‘Post's Critiques of Omniscience and of Talk of “All True Propositions”’. Philo 6: pp. 49–58. Http://www.georgetown.edu/faculty/ap85/papers/QuantifyingOverAllTruths.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Bruce R. 1980. ‘Mavrodes on Omnipotence’. Philosophical Studies 37: 211–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Howard. 1982. Matter and Sense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Howard. 1993. ‘The Anti-Materialist Strategy and the “Knowledge Argument”’. In Robinson, , ed., Objections to Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 159–183.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin A. 2000. Perfect Being Theology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, James F. 1969. Philosophical Theology. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Rowe, William L., ed. 2001. God and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Sarot, Marcel. 1992. God, Passibility, and Corporeality. Kampen, The Netherlands: Kok Pharos Publishing.Google Scholar
Sarot, Marcel. 2001. ‘Does God Suffer?: A Critical Discussion of Thomas G. Weinandy's Does God Suffer?’. Ars Disputandi 1. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000018/index.html.Google Scholar
Savage, C. Wade. 1967. ‘The Paradox of the Stone’. Philosophical Review 76: 74–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2003. ‘Is There a Fundamental Level?’ NoÛs 37: 498–517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Shestov, Leon. 1962. ‘In Memory of a Great Philosopher: Edmund Husserl’, George L. Kline, trans. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, Keith. 1993. ‘On an Argument Against Omniscience’. NoÛs 44: 22–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, Jordan Howard. 2004. Logic and Theism: Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sommers, Tamler. 2002. ‘Of Zombies, Color Scientists, and Floating Iron Bars’. Psyche 8. Http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v8/psyche-8–22-sommers.html.Google Scholar
Sorabji, Richard. 1983. Time, Creation, and the Continuum. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason, and Williamson, Timothy. 2001. ‘Knowing How’. Journal of Philosophy 98: 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2000. ‘Physicalism and Necessary A Posteriori’. Journal of Philosophy 97: 33–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001a. ‘The Conceivability Argument and Two Conceptions of the Physical’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 15: Metaphysics (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing), pp. 393–413.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001b. ‘Physicalism’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2001 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2001/entries/physicalism.
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001c. ‘Two Conceptions of the Physical’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 253–281. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 309–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2005. ‘Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts’. Mind and Language 20: 469–494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2006. Ignorance and Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel, and Yujin Nagasawa. 2004. ‘Introduction’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 1–36.
Strawson, Galen. 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Thomas D. 1991. ‘Omniscience, Immutability, and the Divine Mode of Knowing’. Faith and Philosophy 8: 21–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard. 1973. ‘Omnipotence’. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 231–237.Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard. 1977. The Coherence of Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taliaferro, Charles. 1985. ‘Divine Cognitive Power’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 18: 133–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Textor, Mark. 2001. ‘“Portraying” a Proposition’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 137–161.Google Scholar
Tilghman, B. R. 1991. ‘What Is It Like to Be an Aardvark?’ Philosophy 66: 325–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomberlin, James E., and McGuinness, Frank. 1977. ‘God, Evil and the Free Will Defense’. Religious Studies 13: 455–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trakakis, Nick. 1997. ‘The Absolute Theory of Omnipotence’. Sophia 36: 55–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, Michael. 1999. ‘Phenomenal Consciousness: The Explanatory Gap as Cognitive Illusion’. Mind 108: 705–725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, Michael. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tye, Michael. 2003. ‘A Theory of Phenomenal Concepts’. In O'Hear (2003), pp. 91–105.
Unger, Peter. 1966. ‘On Experience and the Development of the Understanding’. American Philosophical Quarterly 3: 1–9.Google Scholar
Ujvári, Márta. 1997. ‘Omniscience and Essential Indexicals’. In Meggle, Georg, ed., Proceedings of the 2nd Conference ‘Perspectives in Analytic Philosophy’, vol. 1, Philosophy of Language and Metaphysics (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter), pp. 466–473.Google Scholar
Gulick, Robert. 1985. ‘Physicalism and the Subjectivity of the Mental’. Philosophical Topics 13: 51–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gulick, Robert. 1993. ‘Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?’ In Davies, and Humphreys, (1993). Reprinted in Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 447–461. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Van Gulick, Robert. 2004. ‘So Many Ways of Saying No to Mary’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 365–405.
Inwagen, Peter. 1978. ‘The Possibility of Resurrection’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9: 114–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vierkant, Tillmann. 2002. ‘Zombie-Mary and the Blue Banana: On the Compatibility of the “Knowledge Argument” with the Argument from Modality’. Psyche 8. Http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v8/psyche-8–19-vierkant.html.Google Scholar
Weinandy, Thomas G. 2000. Does God Suffer?Edinburgh: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Weinandy, Thomas G. 2002. ‘Does God Suffer?’ Ars Disputandi 2. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000023/index.html.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Alan R. 1982. The Nature of Knowledge. Totowa, N.J.: Rowan and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wielenberg, Erik J. 2000. ‘Omnipotence Again’. Faith and Philosophy 17: 26–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wierenga, Edward R. 1983. ‘Omnipotence Defined’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43: 363–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wierenga, Edward R. 1988. ‘Omniscience and Knowledge De Se Et De Praesenti’. In Austin, David F., ed., Philosophical Analysis: A Defence by Example (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic).Google Scholar
Wierenga, Edward. 1989. The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Yandell, Keith E. 1994. ‘A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency’. Sophia 33: 30–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeis, John. 1993. ‘A Trinity on a Trinity on a Trinity’. Sophia 32: 45–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Abbruzzese, John E. 1997. ‘The Coherence of Omniscience: A Defense’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 41: 25–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Marilyn McCord, and Adams, Robert Merrihew, ed. 1990. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Akins, Kathleen. 1993a. ‘A Bat Without Qualities?’ In Davies and Humphreys (1993), pp. 258–273.
Akins, Kathleen. 1993b. ‘What Is It Like To Be Boring and Myopic?’ In Dahlbom, Bo, ed., Dennett and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 124–160.Google Scholar
Alston, William. 1987. ‘Does God Have Beliefs?’ Religious Studies 22: 287–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 1998. ‘A Limited Defence of the Knowledge Argument’. Philosophical Studies 90: 35–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 1999. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In A Field Guide to the Philosophy of Mind. Http://host.uniroma3.it/progetti/kant/field/ka.html.Google Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2001. ‘Know-How, Ability, and the Ability Hypothesis’. Theoria 67: 229–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2002a. ‘Nagel on Imagination and Physicalism’. Journal of Philosophical Research 27: 143–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2002b. ‘On Two Alleged Conflicts Between Divine Attributes’. Faith and Philosophy 19: 47–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2006. ‘The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism’. In Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Http://www.iep.utm.edu/k/know-arg.htm.Google Scholar
Alter, Torin. 2007. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In Velmans, Max and Schneider, Susan, eds., The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 396–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alter, Torin, and Walter, Sven. 2006. Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, C. Anthony. 1984. ‘Divine Omnipotence and Impossible Tasks: An Intensional Analysis’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 15: 109–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1967 (originally 1265–1274). Summa theologiae, Thomas Gilby, trans. London: Eyre and Spottiswoode.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1975 (originally 1258–1264). Summa contra gentiles, James F. Anderson trans. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. Excerpt reprinted in Stump, Eleonore and Murray, Michael J., eds., Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), pp. 7–9. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1997 (originally the 13th century). Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Pegis, Anton C., ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Balog, Katalin. 1999. ‘Conceivability, Possibility, and the Mind-Body Problem’. Philosophical Review 108: 497–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bealer, George. 2002. ‘Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance’. In Gendler, Tamar Szabó and Hawthorne, John, eds., Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 71–125.Google Scholar
Beall, J. C. 2000. ‘A Neglected Response to the Grim Result’. Analysis 60: 38–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaty, Michael, and Taliaferro, Charles. 1990. ‘God and Concept Empiricism’. Southwest Philosophy Review 6: 97–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beyer, Jason A. 2004. ‘A Physicalist Rejoinder to Some Problems with Omniscience; or How God Could Know What We Know’. Sophia 43: 5–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beyer, Jason A. 2006. ‘Reply to Nagasawa’. Sophia 45: 127–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, John, and Pargetter, Robert. 1990. ‘Acquaintance with Qualia’. Theoria 61: pp. 129–147. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 179–195.Google Scholar
Bishop, John. 1993. ‘Evil and the Concept of God’. Philosophical Papers 22: 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, John. 1998. ‘Can There Be Alternative Concepts of God?’ NoÛs 98: 174–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1992. ‘Filling in Space’. Analysis 50: 62–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Ned, and Stalnaker, Robert. 1999. ‘Conceptual Analysis, Dualism, and the Explanatory Gap’. Philosophical Review 108: 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, Ned, Flanagan, Owen, and Güven Güzeldere, , eds. 1997. The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Blumenfeld, David. 1978. ‘On the Compossibility of the Divine Attributes’. Philosophical Studies 34: 91–103. Reprinted in Morris, Thomas V., ed., The Concept of God(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 201–215. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David. 2003. ‘Qualia and Analytical Conditionals’. Journal of Philosophy 100: 111–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Jackson, Frank. 1996. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bringsjord, Selmer. 1989. ‘Grim on Logic and Omniscience’. Analysis 49: 186–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Campbell, and Nagasawa, Yujin. 2005. ‘Anything You Can Do God Can Do Better’. American Philosophical Quarterly 42: 221–227.Google Scholar
Burke, Michael B. 1987. ‘Theodicy with a God of Limited Power: A Reply to McGrath’. Analysis 47: 57–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cain, James. 1989. ‘The Doctrine of the Trinity and the Logic of Relative Identity’. Religious Studies 25: 141–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, Peter. 2005. Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Richard. 1987. ‘On the Logical Problem of the Trinity’. In Cartwright, Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: MIT Press), pp. 187–200.Google Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri. 1967. ‘Omniscience and Indexical Reference’. Journal of Philosophy 64: 203–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1995. ‘The Puzzle of Conscious Experience’. Scientific American 237: 80–86. Reprinted in Inwagen, Peter and Zimmerman, Dean W., eds., Metaphysics: The Big Questions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), pp. 333–341. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 1999. ‘Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Studies 59: 473–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 2002a. ‘Consciousness and Its Place in Nature’. In Stich, Stephen and Warfield, Ted, eds., Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 102–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David J. 2002b. ‘Imagination, Indexicality and Intensions’. Http://www.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/papers/perry.html.
Chalmers, David J. 2004. ‘Phenomenal Concepts and the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 269–298.
Churchland, Paul M. 1985a. ‘Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States’. Journal of Philosophy 82: 8–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1985b. ‘Review of Robinson's Matter and Sense’. Philosophical Review 94: 117–120.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1989. ‘Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson’. In Churchland, , A Neurocomputational Perspective (Cambridge: MIT Press), pp. 67–76. Reprinted in Block et al. (1997), pp. 571–577. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1996. Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Conee, Earl. 1991. ‘The Possibility of Power Beyond Possibility’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 5: Philosophy of Religion (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview).Google Scholar
Conee, Earl. 1994. ‘Phenomenal Knowledge’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72: 136–50. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 197–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Côté, Antoine. 1998. ‘God and the Principle of Non-Contradiction’. International Philosophical Quarterly 38: 285–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim. 1993. ‘A Definition of Physicalism: Reply to Pettit’. Analysis 53: 224–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim, and Mellor, D. H.. 1990. ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’. Mind 99: 185–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Creel, Richard E. 1986. Divine Impassibility: An Essay in Philosophical Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger 1986. ‘The Avoidance of the Problem of Evil: A Reply to McGrath’. Analysis 46: 160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daly, Chris. 1998. ‘Modality and Acquaintance with Properties’. The Monist 81: 44–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1987. ‘Knowing One's Own Mind’. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60: 441–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin, and Humphreys, Glyn W., eds. 1993. Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davis, Stephen T. 1983. Logic and the Nature of God. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 2006. ‘What RoboMary Knows’. In Alter and Walter (2006).
Descartes, René. 1970 (originally the 17th century. Philosophical Letters, Kenny, Anthony, ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Downey, James Patrick. 1993. ‘On Omniscience’. Faith and Philosophy 10: 230–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Eccles, J. C. 1985. ‘Mental Summation: The Timing of Voluntary Intentions by Cortical Activity’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8: 542–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eccles, J. C. 1994. How the Self Controls Its Brain. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Endicott, Ronald P. 1995. ‘Refutation by Analogous Ectoqualia’. Southern Journal of Philosophy 33: 19–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etzkorn, Gerald, and Kelly, Francis, eds. 1979. Ockham: Opera Theologica, vol. 4. St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute.Google Scholar
Fiddes, Paul S. 1992. The Creative Suffering of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, Owen. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Flint, Thomas P., and Alfred J. Freddoso. 1983. ‘Maximal Power’. In Freddoso, Alfred J., ed., The Existence and Nature of God (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press), pp. 81–113.Google Scholar
Forrest, Peter. 1994. ‘Inherited Responsibility, Karma and Original Sin’. Sophia 33: 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, Peter. 2007. Developmental Theism: From Pure Will to Unbounded Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foss, Jeff E. 1989. ‘On the Logic of What It Is Like To Be a Conscious Subject’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67: 305–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foss, Jeff E. 1993. ‘Subjectivity, Objectivity, and Nagel on Consciousness’. Dialogue 32: 725–736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, John. 1991. Immaterial Self. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Francks, Richard. 1979. ‘Omniscience, Omnipotence and Pantheism’. Philosophy 54: 395–399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1964. ‘The Logic of Omnipotence’. Philosophical Review 73: 262–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 1977. ‘Descartes on the Creation of the Eternal Truths’. Philosophical Review 86: 36–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, Richard. 2004. ‘Knowledge by Acquaintance vs. Description’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2004 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2004/entries/knowledge-acquaindescrip.
Gale, Richard M. 1991. On the Nature of Existence of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gale, Richard M. 2003. ‘A Response to My Critics’. Philo 6: 132–165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, Peter. 1973. ‘Omnipotence’. Philosophy 48: 7–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, Peter. 1977. Providence and Evil. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabo, and Hawthorne, John, eds. 2002. Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gertler, Brie. 2003. ‘Self-Knowledge’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2003 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/self-knowledge.
Goldstick, D. 1990. ‘Could God Make a Contradiction True?’ Religious Studies 26: 377–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorman, Michael. 2005. ‘Nagasawa vs. Nagel: Omnipotence, Pseudo-Task, and a Recent Discussion of Nagel's Doubt About Physicalism’. Inquiry 48: 436–447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1983. ‘Some Neglected Problems of Omniscience’. American Philosophical Quarterly 20: 265–276.Google Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1984. ‘There Is No Set of All Truths’. Analysis 44: 206–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1985. ‘Against Omniscience: The Case from Essential Indexicals’. NoÛs 19: 151–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1986. ‘On Sets and Worlds: A Reply to Menzel’. Analysis 46: 186–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1990. ‘On Omniscience and a “Set of All Truths”: A Reply to Bringsjord’. Analysis 50: 271–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 1991. The Incomplete Universe: Totality, Knowledge and Truth. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 2000. ‘The Being That Knew Too Much’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 47: 141–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grim, Patrick. 2007. ‘Impossibility Arguments’. In Martin, M., eds., Cambridge Companion to Atheism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 199–214.Google Scholar
Groarke, Louis. 2001. ‘Reconsidering Absolute Omnipotence’. The Heythrop Journal 42: 13–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haksar, Vinit. 1981. ‘Nagel on Subjective and Objective’. Inquiry 24: 105–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1969. ‘Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets’. In Morgenbesser, Sidney, Suppes, Patrick, and White, Morton, eds., Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel (New York: St. Martin's Press), pp. 179–199.Google Scholar
Hill, Daniel. 1998. ‘What's New in Philosophy of Religion?’ Philosophy Now 21: 30–33.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary. 1980. ‘What an Omnipotent Agent Can Do’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11: 1–19.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 1984. ‘Swinburne on Omnipotence’. Sophia 23: 36–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 1988. ‘Omnipotence Redux’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49: 283–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Rosenkrantz, Gary S.. 2002. The Divine Attributes. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Joshua, and Gary S. Rosenkrantz. 2006. ‘Omnipotence’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2006 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/omnipotence.
Horgan, Terence. 1984. ‘Jackson on Physical Information and Qualia’. Philosophical Quarterly 34: 147–52. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 301–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, David. 2000. ‘Omniscience and Cognitive Power’. Unpublished manuscript.
Hutcheson, Peter. 1992. ‘Omniscience and the Problem of Evil’. Sophia 31: 53–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1982. ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’. Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 39–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1986. ‘What Mary Didn't Know’. Journal of Philosophy 83: 291–295. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), 51–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1995. ‘Postscript’. In Moser, Paul K. and Trout, J. D., eds., Contemporary Materialism (London: Routledge), pp. 184–189. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 409–415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998a. From Metaphysics to Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998b. ‘Postscript on Qualia’. In Jackson, Mind, Method and Conditionals (London: Routledge), pp. 76–79. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 417–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 2003. ‘Mind and Illusion’. In O'Hear (2003), pp. 251–271.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 2004. ‘Looking Back on the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 421–442.
Johnston, Mark. 1992. ‘How to Speak of the Colors’. Philosophical Studies 68: 221–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, Mark. 1996. ‘Mind-Body Problem at the Surface of Objects’. Philosophical Issues 7: 219–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John. 1977. ‘Physicalism and Subjectivity’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37: 533–536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. 1979. The God of the Philosophers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Khamara, E. J. 1978. ‘In Defense of Omnipotence’. Philosophical Quarterly 28: 215–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, Robet. 2005. Zombies and Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knight, Gordon. 2005. ‘The Theological Significance of Subjectivity’. The Heythrop Journal 46: 1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman. 1966. ‘Omniscience and Immutability’. Journal of Philosophy 63: 409–421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan. 1986. The Possibility of An All-Knowing God. New York: St. Martin's Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachs, John. 1963a. ‘Omniscience’. Dialogue 1: 400–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lachs, John. 1963b. ‘Professor Prior on Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 361–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1977. ‘The Hidden Assumption in the Paradox of Omnipotence’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38: 125–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1978. ‘Failing to Define “Omnipotence”. Philosophical Studies 34: 219–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croix, Richard R. 1984. ‘Descartes on God's Ability to Do the Logically Impossible’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14: 455–475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae. 1998. Kantian Humility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Langton, Rae. 2004. ‘Elusive Knowledge of Things in Themselves’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 129–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leibniz, Gottfried. 1966 (originally 1710). Theodicy, E. M. Huggard, trans. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Levine, Joseph. 2001. Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1979. ‘Attitudes De Dicto and De Se’. Philosophical Review 88: 513–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. ‘Postscript to “Mad Pain and Martian Pain”’. In Lewis, , Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1988. ‘What Experience Teaches’. In Copley-Coltherart, J., ed., Proceedings of the Russellian Society (Sydney: University of Sydney). Reprinted in Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 447–461. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1997. ‘Finkish Dispositions’. Philosophical Quarterly 47: 143–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 2001. ‘Ramseyan Humility’. Preprint Series 1/01. Department of Philosophy, University of Melbourne.Google Scholar
Lloyd, A. C. 1970. ‘Non-Discursive Thought: An Enigma of Greek Philosophy’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 70: 261–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, Brian. 1990. ‘Phenomenal States’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 4: Action Theory and the Philosophy of Mind (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview), pp. 81–108.Google Scholar
Loar, Brian. 1997. ‘Phenomenal States (Revised Version)’. In Block et al. (1997), pp. 597–616. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 219–239.
Lockwood, Michael. 1989. Mind, Brain, and the Quantum. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ludlow, Peter. 1995. ‘Indexical Knowledge and the Possibility of an Omniscient Being’. In Stewart, M. and Clandenon, D., eds., Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Religion (Moscow: Progress Press).Google Scholar
Ludlow, Peter, Nagasawa, Yujin, and Stoljar, Daniel. 2004. There's Something About Mary: Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson's Knowledge Argument. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, William G. 2003. ‘Perspectival Representation and the Knowledge Argument’. In Smith, Quentin and Jokic, Aleksandar, eds., Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Clarendon Press), pp. 384–395.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1955. ‘Evil and Omnipotence’. Mind 64: 200–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism: Arguments for and Against the Existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Macnamara, John, Reyes, Marie, and Reyes, Gonzalo. 1994. ‘Logic and the Trinity’. Faith and Philosophy 11: 3–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mander, William J. 2002. ‘Does God Know What It Is Like to Be Me?’ The Heythrop Journal 43: 430–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, William E. 1975. ‘The Divine Attributes’. American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 151–159.Google Scholar
Mar, Gary. 1993. ‘Why ‘Cantorian’ Arguments Against the Existence of God Do Not Work’. International Philosophical Quarterly 33: 429–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Michael. 1970. ‘A Disproof of God's Existence’. Darshana 10: 22–26.Google Scholar
Martin, Michael. 1974. ‘A Disproof of the God of the Common Man’. Question 7: 115–124. Reprinted in Martin and Monnier (2003), pp. 232–241. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Martin Michael. 1990. ‘Conflicts Between the Divine Attributes’. In Martin, , Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Philadelphia: Temple University Press). Reprinted in Martin and Monnier (2003), pp. 242–257. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Martin, Michael. 2000. ‘Omniscience and Incoherency’. In Holmstrom-Hintikka, Ghita, ed., Medieval Philosophy and Modern Times (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic), pp. 17–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Michael, and Monnier, Ricki, eds. 2003. The Impossibility of God. Amherst and New York: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1963. ‘Some Puzzles Concerning Omnipotence’. Philosophical Review 72: 221–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1977. ‘Defining Omnipotence’. Philosophical Studies 32: 191–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavrodes, George I. 1988. ‘How Does God Know the Things He Knows’. In Morris, Thomas V., ed., Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism (Ithaca, N. Y., Cornell University Press), pp. 345–361.Google Scholar
Mawson, T. J. 2002. ‘Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection Are Compatible: A Reply to Morriston’. Religious Studies 38: 215–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, Grover. 1979. ‘Rigid Designators and Mind-Brain Identity’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9: 365–403.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1989. ‘Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?’ Mind 98: 349–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1991. The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Toward a Resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 1999. Mysterious Flame. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
McGinn, Colin. 2004. Consciousness and Its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, P. J. 1986. ‘Evil and the Existence of a Finite God’. Analysis 46: 63–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, P. J. 1987. ‘Children of a Lesser God?: A Reply to Burke and Crisp’. Analysis 47: 236–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullen, Carolyn. 1985. ‘“Knowing What It's Like” and the Essential Indexical’. Philosophical Studies 48: 211–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, John Ellis. 1906. Some Dogmas of Religion. London: Edward Arnold.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. 1993. ‘Nothing Like Experience’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 63: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menzel, Christopher. 1986. ‘On Set Theoretic Possible Worlds’. Analysis 46: 68–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Leonard G. 1957. ‘Descartes, Mathematics, and God’. Philosophical Review 66. 451–465.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montero, Barbara. 2006. ‘Physicalism in an Infinitely Decomposable World’. Erkenntnis 64: 177–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, A. W. 1997. Points of View. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P. 2003. ‘The Knowledge Argument Revisited’. International Journal for Philosophical Quarterly 43: 219–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1986a. The Logic of God Incarnate. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1986b. ‘Reduplication and Representational Christology’. Modern Theology 2: 319–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. 1991. Our Idea of God: An Introduction to Christian Theology. Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press.Google Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2001a. ‘Omnipotence and the Anselmian God’. Philo 4: 7–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2001b. ‘Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection: Are They Compatible?’ Religious Studies 37: 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2002. ‘Omnipotence and the Power to Choose: A Reply to Wielenberg’. Faith and Philosophy 19: 358–367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morriston, Wes. 2003. ‘Are Omnipotence and Necessary Moral Perfection Compatible?: Reply to Mawson: Are They Compatible?’ Religious Studies 39: 441–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mozley, J. K. 1926. The Impassibility of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, Nancy. 2006. Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2002. ‘The Knowledge Argument Against Dualism’. Theoria 68: 205–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003a. ‘Divine Omniscience and Experience: A Reply to Alter’. Ars Disputandi 3. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000098/index.html.Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003b. ‘Divine Omniscience and Knowledge De Se’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 53: 73–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003c. ‘God's Point of View: A Reply to Mander’. The Heythrop Journal 44: 60–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2003d. ‘Thomas vs. Thomas: A New Approach to Nagel's Bat Argument’. Inquiry 46: 377–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2006. ‘Physicalism and Omniscience: A Reply to Beyer’. Sophia 44: 55–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2007a. ‘A Further Reply to Beyer on Omniscience’. Sophia 46: 65–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Yujin. 2007b. ‘The “Most Powerful” Response to the Knowledge Argument’. Unpublished manuscript, University of Birmingham.
Nagasawa, Yujin. Forthcoming. ‘The Knowledge Argument’. In Tim Bayne, Axel Cleeremans, and Patrick Wilken, eds., The Oxford Companion to Consciousness.
Nagel, Thomas. 1974. ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat’. Philosophical Review 83: 435–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nemirow, Lawrence. 1980. ‘Review of Nagel's Mortal Questions’. Philosophical Review 89: 473–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nemirow, Lawrence. 1990. ‘Physicalism and the Cognitive Role of Acquaintance’. In Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: A Reader (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Ngien, Dennis. 1997. ‘The God Who Suffers’. Christian Today, February 3.Google Scholar
O'Hear, Anthony, ed. 2003. Mind and Persons: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David. 2002. Thinking About Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, Derek. 1994. ‘Bats, Brain Scientists, and the Limitation of Introspection’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 315–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, John. 1979. ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’. NoÛs 13: 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, John. 2001. Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Peterson, Michael L., ed. 1992. The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 1993. ‘A Definition of Physicalism’. Analysis 53: 213–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip. 2004. ‘Motion Blindness and the Knowledge Argument’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 105–142.
Pike, Nelson. 1969. ‘Omnipotence and God's Ability to Sin’. American Philosophical Quarterly 6: 208–216.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1967. God and Other Minds. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1980a. Does God Have a Nature?Milwaukee, Wisc.: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1980b. God, Freedom and Evil. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1989. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, and Grim, Patrick. 1993. Philosophical Studies 71: 267–306.CrossRef
Post, John F.. 2003. ‘Omniscience, Weak PSR and Method’. Philo 6: pp. 33–48. Http://www.vanderbilt.edu/~postjf/OmWpsrMeth7.02nc.htm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Post, John F. 2004. ‘Reply to Gale and Pruss’. Philo 7: 114–121. Http://www.vanderbilt.edu/~postjf/gale&pruss.htm.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1962. ‘The Formalities of Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 114–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. N. 1963. ‘Rejoinder to Professor Lachs on Omniscience’. Philosophy 37: 365–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pruss, Alexander R. 2003. ‘Post's Critiques of Omniscience and of Talk of “All True Propositions”’. Philo 6: pp. 49–58. Http://www.georgetown.edu/faculty/ap85/papers/QuantifyingOverAllTruths.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Bruce R. 1980. ‘Mavrodes on Omnipotence’. Philosophical Studies 37: 211–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Howard. 1982. Matter and Sense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Howard. 1993. ‘The Anti-Materialist Strategy and the “Knowledge Argument”’. In Robinson, , ed., Objections to Physicalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 159–183.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin A. 2000. Perfect Being Theology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, James F. 1969. Philosophical Theology. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Rowe, William L., ed. 2001. God and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Sarot, Marcel. 1992. God, Passibility, and Corporeality. Kampen, The Netherlands: Kok Pharos Publishing.Google Scholar
Sarot, Marcel. 2001. ‘Does God Suffer?: A Critical Discussion of Thomas G. Weinandy's Does God Suffer?’. Ars Disputandi 1. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000018/index.html.Google Scholar
Savage, C. Wade. 1967. ‘The Paradox of the Stone’. Philosophical Review 76: 74–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2003. ‘Is There a Fundamental Level?’ NoÛs 37: 498–517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Shestov, Leon. 1962. ‘In Memory of a Great Philosopher: Edmund Husserl’, George L. Kline, trans. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, Keith. 1993. ‘On an Argument Against Omniscience’. NoÛs 44: 22–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, Jordan Howard. 2004. Logic and Theism: Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sommers, Tamler. 2002. ‘Of Zombies, Color Scientists, and Floating Iron Bars’. Psyche 8. Http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v8/psyche-8–22-sommers.html.Google Scholar
Sorabji, Richard. 1983. Time, Creation, and the Continuum. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason, and Williamson, Timothy. 2001. ‘Knowing How’. Journal of Philosophy 98: 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2000. ‘Physicalism and Necessary A Posteriori’. Journal of Philosophy 97: 33–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001a. ‘The Conceivability Argument and Two Conceptions of the Physical’. In Tomberlin, James, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 15: Metaphysics (Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing), pp. 393–413.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001b. ‘Physicalism’. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2001 edition. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2001/entries/physicalism.
Stoljar, Daniel. 2001c. ‘Two Conceptions of the Physical’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 253–281. Reprinted in Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 309–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2005. ‘Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts’. Mind and Language 20: 469–494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel. 2006. Ignorance and Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, Daniel, and Yujin Nagasawa. 2004. ‘Introduction’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 1–36.
Strawson, Galen. 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Thomas D. 1991. ‘Omniscience, Immutability, and the Divine Mode of Knowing’. Faith and Philosophy 8: 21–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard. 1973. ‘Omnipotence’. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 231–237.Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard. 1977. The Coherence of Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taliaferro, Charles. 1985. ‘Divine Cognitive Power’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 18: 133–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Textor, Mark. 2001. ‘“Portraying” a Proposition’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 137–161.Google Scholar
Tilghman, B. R. 1991. ‘What Is It Like to Be an Aardvark?’ Philosophy 66: 325–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomberlin, James E., and McGuinness, Frank. 1977. ‘God, Evil and the Free Will Defense’. Religious Studies 13: 455–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trakakis, Nick. 1997. ‘The Absolute Theory of Omnipotence’. Sophia 36: 55–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, Michael. 1999. ‘Phenomenal Consciousness: The Explanatory Gap as Cognitive Illusion’. Mind 108: 705–725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, Michael. 2000. Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tye, Michael. 2003. ‘A Theory of Phenomenal Concepts’. In O'Hear (2003), pp. 91–105.
Unger, Peter. 1966. ‘On Experience and the Development of the Understanding’. American Philosophical Quarterly 3: 1–9.Google Scholar
Ujvári, Márta. 1997. ‘Omniscience and Essential Indexicals’. In Meggle, Georg, ed., Proceedings of the 2nd Conference ‘Perspectives in Analytic Philosophy’, vol. 1, Philosophy of Language and Metaphysics (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter), pp. 466–473.Google Scholar
Gulick, Robert. 1985. ‘Physicalism and the Subjectivity of the Mental’. Philosophical Topics 13: 51–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gulick, Robert. 1993. ‘Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?’ In Davies, and Humphreys, (1993). Reprinted in Lycan, William G., ed., Mind and Cognition: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 447–461. Page numbers refer to reprint.Google Scholar
Van Gulick, Robert. 2004. ‘So Many Ways of Saying No to Mary’. In Ludlow et al. (2004), pp. 365–405.
Inwagen, Peter. 1978. ‘The Possibility of Resurrection’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9: 114–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vierkant, Tillmann. 2002. ‘Zombie-Mary and the Blue Banana: On the Compatibility of the “Knowledge Argument” with the Argument from Modality’. Psyche 8. Http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v8/psyche-8–19-vierkant.html.Google Scholar
Weinandy, Thomas G. 2000. Does God Suffer?Edinburgh: T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Weinandy, Thomas G. 2002. ‘Does God Suffer?’ Ars Disputandi 2. Http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000023/index.html.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Alan R. 1982. The Nature of Knowledge. Totowa, N.J.: Rowan and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Wielenberg, Erik J. 2000. ‘Omnipotence Again’. Faith and Philosophy 17: 26–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wierenga, Edward R. 1983. ‘Omnipotence Defined’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43: 363–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wierenga, Edward R. 1988. ‘Omniscience and Knowledge De Se Et De Praesenti’. In Austin, David F., ed., Philosophical Analysis: A Defence by Example (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic).Google Scholar
Wierenga, Edward. 1989. The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Yandell, Keith E. 1994. ‘A Gross and Palpable Contradiction?: Incarnation and Consistency’. Sophia 33: 30–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeis, John. 1993. ‘A Trinity on a Trinity on a Trinity’. Sophia 32: 45–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Yujin Nagasawa, University of Birmingham
  • Book: God and Phenomenal Consciousness
  • Online publication: 23 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498961.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Yujin Nagasawa, University of Birmingham
  • Book: God and Phenomenal Consciousness
  • Online publication: 23 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498961.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Yujin Nagasawa, University of Birmingham
  • Book: God and Phenomenal Consciousness
  • Online publication: 23 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498961.010
Available formats
×