Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-23T14:38:15.430Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Realism, categories, and the “linguistic turn”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Stephen Leach
Affiliation:
Keele University
James Tartaglia
Affiliation:
Keele University
Get access

Summary

Realist criticism of linguistic philosophy

Among contemporary realistic philosophers there is a tendency to see the history of philosophy from Descartes to Wittgenstein as one continuous process of garnering the wages of sin. One can identify the original sin as the representative theory of perception, as the confusion of noetic being with being as such, or in various other ways. In any case, the dialectical progression which in the course of three centuries has led philosophers away from things to ideas, and away from ideas to words, presents itself as the enactment of an agonizing drama of self-destruction.

Given the initial Cartesian sundering of cognition from the object of cognition, it was only to be expected that epistemology should claim priority over metaphysics. Once this happened, it was only a matter of time before metaphysics shriveled away and died. In due course, epistemology, finding itself unable to function as an autonomous discipline when deprived of metaphysical support, was pushed aside by its ungrateful child, linguistic analysis. The ultimate, foredoomed, result of this development is, according to such neo-Thomist descriptions of recent philosophy as that of Oliver Martin, the total confusion of the theoretic and instrumental orders, and the consequent replacement of philosophic controversy by ideological conflict. Linguistic analysis, Martin says, though not itself an ideology, is at the service of ideology through being “one of the many non-philosophical forms of anti-philosophy.” Probably, Martin continues, “It would not exist were it not for the fact that professors of philosophy who no longer believe in philosophy must do something if they are to continue to receive a salary for doing that which they profess to be impossible.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Mind, Language, and Metaphilosophy
Early Philosophical Papers
, pp. 55 - 68
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Warnock, G. J., Berkeley (London, 1953), pp. 236–47Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter, Individuals (London, 1959), p. 35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toulmin, Stephen, The Uses of Argument (Cambridge, 1958), pp. 299ffGoogle Scholar
Baier, Kurt, The Moral Point of View (Ithaca, 1958)Google Scholar
Ryle, ’s The Concept of Mind (London, 1949)Google Scholar
Husserl, ’s revivification of the realistic thesis of the intentionality of consciousness, in a symposium on “Phenomenology,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 11 (1932), 68ffGoogle Scholar
Geach, Peter, Mental Acts (New York, 1957)Google Scholar
Warnock, , loc. cit., and also his English Philosophy since 1900 (Oxford, 1958), ch. 12.Google Scholar
Johnstone, Henry, Philosophy and Argument (University Park, PA, 1959)Google Scholar
Hall, Everett, Philosophical Systems (Chicago, 1960)Google Scholar
Stace, Walter, The Philosophy of Hegel (New York, 1955), pp. 88ffGoogle Scholar
Hawkins, D. J. B., Wittgenstein and the Cult of Language, Aquinas Society of London: Aquinas Paper No. 27 (London, 1957), p. 4Google Scholar
Waismann, F., “Language-Strata,” in Logic and Language, Second Series, ed. Flew, A. N. (Oxford, 1955), pp. 11–31Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, , Philosophical Investigations (Oxford, 1953), § 116Google Scholar
Flew, A. N., “Philosophy and Language,” in Flew, , ed., Essays in Conceptual Analysis (London, 1956), pp. 1–20, esp. p. 2Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×