Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-06T05:38:27.202Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

13 - Verificationism and transcendental arguments

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Stephen Leach
Affiliation:
Keele University
James Tartaglia
Affiliation:
Keele University
Get access

Summary

Many admirers of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations and of Strawson’s Individuals have taken the theme of both books to be an analysis of philosophical skepticism and their distinctive contribution to be a new way of criticizing the skeptic. This new way is summed up in a familiar passage from Strawson:

He [the skeptic] pretends to accept a conceptual scheme, but at the same time quietly rejects one of the conditions of its employment Thus, his doubts are unreal, not simply because they are logically irresoluble doubts, but because they amount to the rejection of the whole conceptual scheme within which alone such doubts make sense.

In an earlier period of analytic philosophy, the standard reply to the skeptic had been of the phenomenalistic Hume–Berkeley type. That is, the skeptic’s suggestion that what were usually taken to be material objects or other persons might merely be the content of his own consciousness – his own representations – was met with the reply that to have such-and-such representations just was to be seeing a material object or another person. This if-you-can’t-beat-him-join-him strategy, however, always (a) got shaky when “was” was questioned (did it mean “entailed”? “confirmed”?) and (b) had an unpleasant air of idealism about it, no matter how much it was claimed to be a “logical” rather than a “metaphysical” point. So when, on the heels of Austin’s attack on “the ontology of the sensible manifold,” Strawson revived the distinctively Kantian anti-idealist thesis that “inner experience requires outer experience,” the shift in strategy was welcomed. Strawson’s points about persons and material objects fitted together nicely with Wittgenstein’s “private-language argument” to suggest that the skeptics’ notion of a world of pure experience – a world containing nothing but representations – did not really make sense.

Type
Chapter
Information
Mind, Language, and Metaphilosophy
Early Philosophical Papers
, pp. 260 - 270
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Strawson, P. F., Individuals (London, 1959), p. 35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, , “Private Languages,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 1 (1964), pp. 20–31Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart, ed., The Philosophy of Mind (New York, 1966), pp. 116–43Google Scholar
Stroud, , “Transcendental Arguments,” Journal of Philosophy, 65 (1968), pp. 241–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saunders, John Turk and Henze, Donald F., The Private-Language Problem (New York, 1967)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, , Philosophical Investigations (3rd edn., New York, 1958)Google Scholar
Chisholm, Roderick, “Philosophers and Ordinary Language,” Philosophical Review, 60 (1951), pp. 317–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, “The Significance of Der Logische Aufbau der Welt,” in Schilpp, P. A., ed., The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap [La Salle, 1963], pp. 545–58Google Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. E., “Strawson and Ontological Priority,” in Butler, R. J., ed., Analytical Philosophy, ii (Oxford, 1965), esp. pp. 114–19Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×