Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T13:11:02.625Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A context principle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2017

Reinhard Kähle
Affiliation:
Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal
Get access

Summary

Abstract. Starting from any language provided with sentence meanings and a grammar, and using the principle that the meaning of a phrase is what it contributes to the meanings of sentences containing it, we derive a semantics for the whole language. The semantics is necessarily compositional and carries a structure of semantic categories. With a further assumption on the grammatical heads of phrases, we can assume that the meanings of head words are functions from meanings to meanings, in the Frege style. The paper sketches these results and considers how far the semantics of Husserl, Frege and Tarski can be seen as examples of this pattern.

When Alfred Tarski wrote his famous definition of truth [20] (1933) for a formal language, he had several stated aims. His chief aim was to define truth of sentences. Giving correct meanings of other expressions of the language was nowhere in his list of aims at all; it was a happy accident that a general semantics fell out of his truth definition.

So the following facts, all very easily proved, came to me as a surprise. Given any notion of meaning for sentences (for example, a specification of when they are true and when not), and assuming some simple book-keeping conditions, there is a canonical way of extending this notion to a semantics for the whole language. I call it the fregean extension; it is determined up to the question which pairs of expressions have the same meaning. Tarski's semantics for first-order logic is the fregean extension of the truth conditions for sentences. Afewmore book-keeping conditions guarantee that the fregean extension can be chosen to have good functional properties of the kind often associated with Frege and with type-theoretic semantics.

Tarski himselfwas certainly interested in the question howfar his solution of his problem was canonical, and we can learn useful things from his discussion of the issue. But the main results below on fregean extensions come closer to the linguistic and logical concerns of Frege and Husserl, a generation earlier than Tarski. Husserl has been unjustly neglected by logicians, and Frege's innovations in linguistics deserve to be better known.

Type
Chapter
Information
Intensionality , pp. 42 - 59
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Yehoshua, Bar-Hillel, On categorial and phrase structure grammars, Language and information, Addison-Wesley, Reading Mass., 1964, pp. 99–115.
[2] Richard, Baum, Dependenzgrammatik, Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tübingen, 1976.
[3] Johann Gustav Friedrich, Billroth, Lateinische Schulgrammatik für die obern Klassen gelehrter Schulen, Leipzig, 1832.
[4] Gottlob, Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Koebner, Breslau, 1884.
[5] Gottlob, Frege, Grundgesetze der Arithmetik I, Hermann Pohle, Jena, 1893.
[6] Gottlob, Frege, Ü ber Sinn und Bedeutung, Gottlob Frege, Kleine Schriften (I., Angelelli, editor), Georg Olms, Hildesheim, 1967, pp. 143–162.
[7] Gottlob, Frege, Begriffsschrift, Georg Olms Verlag, Hildesheim, 1998, (original 1879).
[8] Haim, Gaifman, Dependency systems and phrase-structure systems, Information andControl, vol. 8 (1965), pp. 304–337.Google Scholar
[9] Zellig S., Harris, Co-occurrence and transformation in linguistic structure, Language, vol. 33 (1957), pp. 283–340.Google Scholar
[10] Jaakko, Hintikka and Gabriel, Sandu, Game-theoretical semantics, Handbook of logic and language (Johan van, Benthem and Alice ter, Meulen, editors), Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1996, pp. 361–410.
[11] Wilfrid, Hodges, Compositional semantics for a language of imperfect information, Logic Journal of the IGPL, vol. 5 (1997), pp. 539–563.Google Scholar
[12] Wilfrid, Hodges, Some strange quantifiers, Structures in logic and computer science (J., Mycielski et al., editors),Lecture Notes in Computer Science 1261,Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1997, pp. 51–65.
[13] Wilfrid, Hodges, Formal features of compositionality, Journal of Logic, Language and Information, vol. 10 (2001), pp. 7–28.
[14] Edmund, Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen II/1, Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tübingen, 1993, (originally published 1900); trans. by J. N., Findlay as Logical Investigations Vol. II, Humanity Books, Amherst, New York, 2000.
[15] Shalom, Lappin and W., Zadrozny, Compositionality, synonymy, and the systematic representation of meaning, Preprint, 2000.
[16] Alfonso, Maier `u, The grammar of the Modistae, History of linguistics: II, classical and medieval linguistics (Giulio, Lepschy, editor), Longman, London, 1994, pp. 288–302.
[17] Walter, J. Ong, Ramus: Method, and the decay of dialogue, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1958.
[18] Jonathan, Owens, The foundations of grammar: an introduction to medieval Arabic grammatical theory, John Benjamins, Amsterdam, 1988.
[19] Jan, Pinborg, Speculative grammar, The Cambridge history of later medieval philosophy (Norman Kretzmann et al., editors),CambridgeUniversity Press,Cambridge, 1982, pp. 254–269.
[20] Alfred, Tarski, The concept of truth in formalized languages, Logic, semantics, metamathematics (J., Corcoran, editor), Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis, 1983, pp. 152–278.
[21] Lucien, Tesnieŕe, É lÉments de syntaxe structurale, Klincksieck, Paris, 1959.
[22] Dag, Westerståhl, On the compositional extension problem, Journal of Philosophical Logic (to appear).
[23] W., Zadrozny, From compositional to systematic semantics, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 17 (1994), pp. 329–342.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×