Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T11:50:53.515Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intension, intention

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2017

Reinhard Kähle
Affiliation:
Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal
Get access

Summary

Abstract. Intensionality has generally been of more concern to logicians than intentionality. But also the latter merits their interest. This paper, a contribution to the logic of action, involves both concepts—the former implicitly, the latter explicitly.

Informal background. Many logicians and philosophers, the present writer included, are familiar with the term “intension” (with an s) but rather less familiar with the term “intention” (with a t). Outside philosophy and logic the situation is reverse: “intention” is used by all, “intension” by few, if any. A miniature history of the development of the two terms was given by E. J. Lemmon [6]:

The medieval term intentio was originally employed as a translation of the Arabic termma'na, a formin the soul identified with a meaning or a notion, and meant throughout medieval epistemology a natural sign in the soul. Later the Port Royal Logic distinguished between the comprehension and extension of a general term in something of the way in which Mill later distinguished connotation and denotation: whilst the extension is the set of things to which the term applies, its comprehension is the set of attributes which it implies. Sir William Hamilton replaced “comprehension” by “intension”, faultily spelling the word with an “s” by analogy with “extension”. Since then, the term “intentionality” has gone one way, via Brentano to Chisholm, and the word “intensionality” another via Carnap to Quine.

This elegant quotation is offered for what it is worth. It is of some help in explaining philosophers’ terminology, but unfortunately it leaves unexplained the connexion with everyday usage in the context of action. And it is the latter that is of concern in this paper.

We study a system in which one agent (“the agent”) operates in some environment (“the world”). The world may or may not be dynamic, in the sense that things can happen even if the agent does not do anything; when it is, it is convenient to postulate yet another agent, called “Nature”.

Type
Chapter
Information
Intensionality , pp. 174 - 186
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Nuel, Belnap, Michael, Perloff, and Ming, Xu, Facing the future: agents and choices in our indeterministic world, Oxford University Press, New York,.
[2] Michael E., Bratman, Intention, plans, and practical reason, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,MA, 1987.
[3] Philip R., Cohen and Hector J., Levesque, Intention is choice with commitment, Artificial Intelligence, vol. 42 (1990), pp. 213–261.Google Scholar
[4] Donald, Davidson, Essays on actions and events, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1980.
[5] John F., Horty, Agency and deontic logic, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2001.
[6] E. J., Lemmon, An introduction to modal logic, American Philosophical Quarterly monograph series, vol. 11, Oxford, 1977, Written in collaboration with Dana Scott and published posthumously.
[7] Krister, Segerberg, Getting started: beginnings in the logic of action, Studia Logica, vol. 51 (1992), pp. 347–378.Google Scholar
[8] Krister, Segerberg, Results, consequences, intentions, Actions, norms, values: discussion with Georg Henrik vonWright (Georg Meggle, editor),Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, New York, 1999, pp. 147–157.
[9] Krister, Segerberg, Outline of a logic of action, Advances in modal logic. vol. 3 (Frank, Wolter et al., editors), vol. 3, World Scientific Publishing Co., Singapore, 2002, pp. 365–387.
[10] Georg, Henrik von Wright, Norm and action: a logical enquiry, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1963.
[11] Georg, Henrik von Wright, The varieties of goodness, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1963.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×