Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-11T01:14:51.659Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Terminist logic

from II - Logic and language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2014

E. Jennifer Ashworth
Affiliation:
University of Waterloo
Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Christina van Dyke
Affiliation:
Calvin College, Michigan
Get access

Summary

Terminist logic is a specifically medieval development. It is named from its focus on terms as the basic unit of logical analysis, and so it includes both supposition theory, together with its ramifications, and the treatment of syncategorematic terms. It also includes other areas of investigation not directly linked with Aristotelian texts, notably obligations, consequences, and insolubles (see Chapters 10, 13, and 14).

Logic was at the heart of the arts curriculum, for it provided the techniques of analysis and much of the vocabulary found in philosophical, scientific, and theological writing. Moreover, it trained students for participation in the disputations that were a central feature of medieval instruction, and whose structure, with arguments for and against a thesis, followed by a resolution, is reflected in many written works. This practical application affected the way in which logic developed. While medieval thinkers had a clear idea of argumentation as involving formal structures, they were not interested in the development of formal systems, and they did not see logic as in any way akin to mathematics. Logic involved the study of natural language, albeit a natural language (Latin) that was often regimented to make formal points, and it had a straightforwardly cognitive orientation. The purpose of logic was to separate the true from the false by means of argument, and to lead from known premises to a previously unknown conclusion. In this process, the avoidance of error was crucial, so there was a heavy emphasis on the making of distinctions and on the detection of fallacies. The procedures involved often have the appearance of being ad hoc, and modern attempts to draw precise parallels between medieval theories as a whole and the results of contemporary symbolic logic are generally doomed to failure, even though there are many fruitful partial correlations.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ashworth, E. J., The Tradition of Medieval Logic and Speculative Grammar from Anselm to the End of the Seventeenth Century. A Bibliography from 1836 Onwards (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1978)
Pironet, Fabienne, The Tradition of Medieval Logic and Speculative Grammar from Anselm to the End of the Seventeenth Century. A Bibliography (1977–1994) (Turnhout: Brepols, 1997)
de Rijk, L. M., Logica modernorum: A Contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1962–7) vol. I: On the Twelfth-Century Theories of Fallacy, and vol. II: The Origin and Early Development of the Theory of Supposition
Kretzmann, N. and Stump, E. (eds.) The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. 1: Logic and the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)
Lewry, P. Osmund, “Grammar, Logic and Rhetoric 1220–1320,” in Catto, J. (ed.) The History of the University of Oxford, vol. I: The Early Oxford Schools (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1984) 401–33
Kretzmann, Norman et al. (eds.) The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy: From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism. 1100–1600 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)
Gilbert, Neal, “Ockham, Wyclif, and the ‘Via Moderna’,” Miscellanea Mediaevalia 9 (1974) pp. 111–15Google Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G., “School Philosophy and Philosophical Schools: The Semantic-Ontological Views in the Cologne Commentaries on Peter of Spain, and the ‘Wegestreit’,” Miscellanea Mediaevalia 20 (1989) esp. pp. 1–2 and 6Google Scholar
d’Ors, Angel, “Petrus Hispanus O.P., Auctor Summularum,” Vivarium 35 (1997) 21–71, 39 (2001) 209–54, 41 (2003) 249–303Google Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G., “English Tracts on Syncategorematic Terms from Robert Bacon to Walter Burley,” in Braakhuis, H. A. G. et al. (eds.) English Logic and Semantics from the End of the Twelfth Century to the Time of Ockham and Burleigh (Nijmegen: Ingenium Publishers, 1981) pp. 138–40
Ashworth, E. J. and Spade, Paul, “Logic in Late Medieval Oxford,” in Catto, J. I. and Evans, R. (eds.) The History of the University of Oxford, vol. II: Late Medieval Oxford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992) 35–64
Kretzmann, et al., The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, p. 188
Kretzmann, and Stump, , in Cambridge Translations, vol. I, p. 105; ed. Alessio, p. 206
Helias, Peter, Summa super Priscianum, ed. Reilly, p. 891
Ebbesen, Sten, “Early Supposition Theory (12th–13th Century),” Histoire Epistémologie Langage 3 (1981) 35–48Google Scholar
Kneepkens, C. H., “‘Suppositio’ and ‘supponere’ in 12th-Century Grammar,” in Jolivet, J. and de Libera, A. (eds.) Gilbert de Poitiers et ses contemporains: aux origines de la Logica modernorum (Naples: Bibliopolis, 1987) 325–51
Panaccio, Claude and Perini-Santos, Ernesto, “Guillaume d’Ockham et la suppositio materialis,” Vivarium 42 (2004) 202–24Google Scholar
Bacon, Roger, Summulae II (ed. de Libera, p. 266); Lambert, Logica, p. 209
Malcolm, John, “A Reconsideration of the Identity and Inherence Theories of the Copula,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 17 (1979) 383–400Google Scholar
de Libera, Alain, “Supposition naturelle et appellation: aspects de la sémantique parisienne au XIIIe siècle,” Histoire Epistémologie Langage 3 (1981) 63–77Google Scholar
Asztalos, M. (ed.) The Editing of Theological and Philosophical Texts from the Middle Ages (Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell International, 1986) 213–44
Spade, Paul, “The Logic of the Categorical: The Medieval Theory of Descent and Ascent,” in Kretzmann, N. (ed.) Meaning and Inference in Medieval Philosophy (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988) 187–224
Read, Stephen, “Thomas of Cleves and Collective Supposition,” Vivarium 29 (1991) 50–84Google Scholar
Ashworth, E. J., Studies in Post-Medieval Semantics (London: Variorum Reprints, 1985)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Terminist logic
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Terminist logic
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Terminist logic
  • Edited by Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Edited in association with Christina van Dyke, Calvin College, Michigan
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHO9781107446953.015
Available formats
×