Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-11T15:37:28.705Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - Selection Type Theories with Joseph A. Cain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 August 2009

Lindley Darden
Affiliation:
University of Maryland, College Park
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

This chapter discusses abstract characterizations of selection theories. Finding such abstractions is a task in a larger research program, which is based on the assumption that some scientific theories are representative of types of theories that solve types of problems. Natural selection, clonal selection for antibody production, and selective theories of higher brain function are examples of selection type theories. Selection theories solve adaptation problems by specifying a process through which one thing comes to be adapted to another thing.

When Darwin elaborated his theory of natural selection in 1859, he provided a new type of theory for explaining adaptation problems. Others, such as Burnet (1957) in immunology, argued by analogy from Darwinian natural selection for selection processes in other fields. One analysis of analogy is that two analogues share a common abstraction (Genesereth 1980). Thus, an analysis of natural selection and its analogues aids in the development of an abstraction for selection theories. The selection literature in philosophy of biology includes several discussions of natural selection that provide help in this task. The abstraction for natural selection extracted from these discussions will then be used in analyzing clonal selection for antibody production in immunology and selective theories for higher brain function in neurobiology. Before beginning the analysis of selection theories, however, we will briefly discuss the concept of an abstraction.

THE CONCEPT OF AN ABSTRACTION

An abstraction provides a schematic outline that can be filled in or “instantiated” to give an actual theory.

Type
Chapter
Information
Reasoning in Biological Discoveries
Essays on Mechanisms, Interfield Relations, and Anomaly Resolution
, pp. 182 - 206
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ada, G. L. and Gustav, N. (1987), “The Clonal Selection Theory,” Scientific American 257: 62–69.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arnold, A. J. and Fristrup, K. (1982), “The Theory of Evolution by Natural Selection: A Hierarchical Expansion,” Paleobiology 8: 113–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayala, F. J. and Dobzhansky, T. (eds.) (1974), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, John (1980), “What's Wrong with the Received View of Evolutionary Theory?” in Asquith, P. D. and Giere, R. N. (eds.), PSA 1980, v. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 397–426.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1980), “A Structural Description of Evolutionary Theory,” in Asquith, P. D. and Giere, R. N. (eds.), PSA 1980, v. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 427–439.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1990), Adaptation and Environment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Burian, Richard (1983), “Adaptation,” in Grene, Marjorie (ed.), Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 287–314.Google Scholar
Burnet, F. M. (1957), “A Modification of Jerne's Theory of Antibody Production Using the Concept of Clonal Selection,” The Australian Journal of Science 20: 67–69.Google Scholar
Cain, Joseph A. and Darden, Lindley (1988). “Hull and Selection,” Biology and Philosophy 3: 165–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Changeux, J. P. (1985), Neuronal Man: The Biology of Mind. New York: Pantheon, Random House.Google Scholar
Conrad, M. (1976), “Complementary Molecular Models of Learning and Memory,” BioSystems 8: 119–138.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darden, Lindley (1976), “Reasoning in Scientific Change: Charles Darwin, Hugo de Vries, and the Discovery of Segregation,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 7: 127–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley (1980), “Theory Construction in Genetics,” in Nickles, T. (ed.), Scientific Discovery: Case Studies. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 151–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley (1982a), “Artificial Intelligence and Philosophy of Science: Reasoning by Analogy in Theory Construction,” in Nickles, T. and Asquith, P. (eds.), PSA 1982, v. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 147–165.Google Scholar
Darden, Lindley (1983), “Reasoning by Analogy in Scientific Theory Construction,” in Michalski, R. S. (ed.), Proceedings of the 1983 International Machine Learning Workshop. Urbana, IL: Department of Computer Science, University of Illinois, pp. 32–40.Google Scholar
Darden, Lindley (1986), “Reasoning in Theory Construction: Analogies, Interfield Connections, and Levels of Organization,” in Weingartner, P. and Dorn, G. (eds.), Foundations of Biology. Vienna, Austria: Holder-Picher-Tempsky, pp. 99–107.Google Scholar
Darden, Lindley (1987), “Viewing the History of Science as Compiled Hindsight,” AI Magazine 8 (2): 33–41.Google Scholar
Darwin, Charles ([1859] 1966), On the Origin of Species, A Facsimile of the First Edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Edelman, Gerald and Mountcastle, V. (1978), The Mindful Brain: Cortical Organization and the Group Selective Theory of Higher Brain Function. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Genesereth, Michael (1980), “Metaphors and Models,” Proceedings of the First Annual National Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Menlo Park, CA: American Association for Artificial Intelligence, pp. 208–211.Google Scholar
Gentner, Dedre (1983), “Structure Mapping – A Theoretical Framework for Analogy,” Cognitive Science 7: 155–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golub, E. (1981), The Cellular Basis of Immune Response, 2nd ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen J. and Vrba, Elisabeth S. (1982), “Exaptation – A Missing Term in the Science of Form,” Paleobiology 8: 4–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greiner, Russell (1985), “Learning by Understanding Analogies,” Ph.D. Dissertation, Department of Computer Science, Stanford University, Stanford, CA.
Hanson, Norwood Russell ([1961] 1970), “Is There a Logic of Scientific Discovery?” in Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. (eds.), Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Reprinted in Brody, B. (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, pp. 620–633.Google Scholar
Holland, John H. (1975), Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Holyoak, Keith J. and Thagard, Paul (1995), Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hull, David (1980), “Individuality and Selection,” Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 11: 311–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David ([1981] 1984), “Units of Evolution: A Metaphysical Essay,” in Jensen, U. L. and Harré, R. (eds.), The Philosophy of Evolution. Brighton: Harvester Press, pp. 23–44. Reprinted in R. N. Brandon and R. M. Burian (eds.), Genes, Populations, and Organisms: Controversies over the Units of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 142–160.Google Scholar
Jerne, Niels K. (1955), “The Natural-Selection Theory of Antibody Formation,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 41: 849–857.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jerne, Niels K. (1966), “The Natural Selection Theory of Antibody Formation: Ten Years Later,” in Cairns, J., Stent, G. S., and Watson, J. D. (eds.), Phage and the Origins of Molecular Biology. Cold Spring Harbor, NY: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory of Quantitative Biology, pp. 301–312.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1981), “Explanatory Unification,” Philosophy of Science 48: 507–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1987), “Ghostly Whispers: Mayr, Ghiselin, and the ‘Philosophers’ on the Ontological Status of Species,” Biology and Philosophy 2: 184–192.Google Scholar
Korf, R. E. (1985), “An Analysis of Abstraction in Problem Solving,” in Pottmyer, J. J. (ed.), Proceedings of the 24th Annual Technical Symposium. Gaithersburg, MD: Washington, DC Chapter of the ACM, June 20, 1985, pp. 7–9.Google Scholar
Lederberg, Joshua ([1959]1961), “Genes and Antibodies,” Science 129: 1649–1653. Reprinted with a postscript in Stanford Medical Bulletin 19: 53–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C. (1970), “The Units of Selection,” Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth (1984), “A Semantic Approach to the Structure of Population Genetics,” Philosophy of Science 51: 242–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pauling, Linus (1940), “A Theory of the Structure and Process of Formation of Antibodies,” Journal of the American Chemical Society 62: 2643–2657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piattelli-Palmarini, M. (1986), “The Rise of Selection Theories: A Case Study and Some Lessons from Immunology,” in Demopoulos, W. and Marras, A. (eds.), Language Learning and Concept Acquisition: Foundational Issues. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Co., pp. 117–130.Google Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth (1974a), “Logic of Discovery and Justification in Regulatory Genetics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 4: 349–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth (1980), “Theory Structure in the Biomedical Sciences,” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 5: 57–97.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shapere, Dudley (1974b), “On the Relations Between Compositional and Evolutionary Theories,” in Ayala, F. J. and Dobzhansky, T. (eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology. London: Macmillan, pp. 187–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, Dudley (1977), “Scientific Theories and Their Domains,” in Suppe, F. (ed.), Structure of Scientific Theories, 2nd ed. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, pp. 518–562.Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley and Gerald Edelman (1974), “A Note on the Concept of Selection,” in Ayala, F. J. and Dobzhansky, T. (eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology. London: Macmillan, pp. 202–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, Frederick (1979), “Theory Structure,” in Asquith, P. and Kyburg, H. (eds.), Current Research in Philosophy of Science. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 317–338.Google Scholar
Talmadge, D. W. (1957), “Allergy and Immunology,” Annual Review of Medicine 8: 239–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talmadge, D. W. (1986), “The Acceptance and Rejection of Immunological Concepts,” Annual Review of Immunology 8: 239–256.Google Scholar
Thompson, Paul (1983), “The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: A Semantic Approach,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 14: 215–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vrba, Elisabeth S. and Gould, Stephen J. (1986), “The Hierarchical Expansion of Sorting and Selection: Sorting and Selection Cannot Be Equated,” Paleobiology 12: 217–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vries, Hugo ([1903–04] [1909–1910] 1969), The Mutation Theory. 2 vols. Translated by J. B. Farmer and A. D. Darbishire. New York: Kraus Reprint Company.Google Scholar
Williams, Mary (1970), “Deducing the Consequences of Evolution: A Mathematical Model,” Journal of Theoretical Biology 29: 343–385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×