Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T10:03:47.708Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 24 - Public Health Values and Evidence-Based Practice

from Section 4 - Scaffolding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 June 2019

Richard Williams
Affiliation:
University of South Wales
Verity Kemp
Affiliation:
Healthplanning Ltd.
S. Alexander Haslam
Affiliation:
University of Queensland
Catherine Haslam
Affiliation:
University of Queensland
Kamaldeep S. Bhui
Affiliation:
Queen Mary University of London
Susan Bailey
Affiliation:
Centre for Mental Health
Daniel Maughan
Affiliation:
Oxford Health NHS Foundation Trust
Get access

Summary

The foci of this book are on the social determinants of health, and the importance to our health of our social connectedness and social support that turn on shared social identities. In Chapter 23, Reicher surveys these matters and makes three important concluding points. First, shared social identity in groups creates bonds between people and converts those bonds into social capital. Second, he asserts that the key to a new social model of mental and physical health lies in understanding how to support people in building and consolidating their own social groups. But, importantly, he also points out that social identity can work for good outcomes but also for those that are seen as less positive.

Type
Chapter
Information
Social Scaffolding
Applying the Lessons of Contemporary Social Science to Health and Healthcare
, pp. 227 - 243
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Academy of Medical Sciences (2015). Exploring a new social contract for medical innovation. See https://acmedsci.ac.uk/file-download/38377-5673dcc2f036b.pdf.Google Scholar
Academy of Medical Sciences (2017). Enhancing the use of scientific evidence to judge the potential benefits and harms of medicines. See https://acmedsci.ac.uk/file-download/44970096.Google Scholar
Buccieri, K. & Gaetz, S (2013). Ethical vaccine distribution planning for pandemic influenza: Prioritizing homeless and hard-to-reach populations. Public Health Ethics, 6: 185196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, P., Laurie, G. T. & Dixon-Woods, M. (2015). The social licence for research: Why care.data ran into trouble. Journal of Medical Ethics, 41: 404409; doi: 10.1136/medethics-2014-102374.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coggon, J. (2012). What Makes Health Public? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coggon, J., Syrett, K. & Viens, A. M. (2017). Public Health Law: Ethics, Governance and Regulation. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Daniels, N. (2000). Accountability for reasonableness. British Medical Journal, 321: 13001301.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Daniels, N. (2008). Just Health: Meeting Health Needs Fairly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dawson, A. (2011). Resetting the parameters public health as the foundation for public health ethics. In Dawson, A., editor, Public Health Ethics: Key Concepts and Issues in Policy and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 119.Google Scholar
Dawson, A. (2016). Snakes and ladders: State interventions and the place of liberty in public health policy. Journal of Medical Ethics, 42: 510513.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dawson, A. & Verweu, M. (2012). Solidarity: A Moral Concept in Need of Clarification. Public Health Ethics, 5: 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Department of Health (2007). Cabinet Office and Department of Health Responding to Pandemic Influenza: The Ethical Framework for Policy and Planning. London: Department of Health.Google Scholar
Department of Health (2010). Independent review of the swine flu response: Memorandum by the Department of Health. See www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/61261/doh.pdf.Google Scholar
Faust, H., Bensimon, C. & Upshur, R. (2009). The role of faith-based organisations in the ethical aspects of pandemic flu planning: Lessons learned from the Toronto SARS experience. Public Health Ethics, 2: 105112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faust, H. S. & Upshur, R. (2009). Public health ethics. In Singer, P. & Viens, A. M., editors, Cambridge Textbook on Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 274280.Google Scholar
Gluckman, P. (2016). Making Decisions in the Face of Uncertainty: Understanding Risk. Auckland: Office of the Prime Minister’s Chief Scientific Advisor.Google Scholar
Grill, K. & Dawson, A. (2015). Ethical frameworks in public health decision-making: Defending a value-based and pluralist approach. Health Care Analysis, 25: 291307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1983). Between utility and rights. In Hart, H. L. A., editor, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 198222.Google Scholar
Hine, D. (2010). The 2009 Influenza Pandemic: An Independent Review of the UK Response to the 2009 Influenza Pandemic. London: Cabinet Office.Google Scholar
IRAP (2014a). Report of the Independent Restraint Advisory Panel to the Ministry of Justice. Implementation of the Minimising and Managing Physical Restraint System in Secure Training Centres and Young Offender Institutions. London: Independent Restraint Advisory Panel.Google Scholar
IRAP (2014b). Report of the Independent Restraint Advisory Panel to the Ministry for Education. A Review of Restraint Systems Commissioned for Use with Children Who are Resident in Secure Children’s Homes. London: Independent Restraint Advisory Panel.Google Scholar
Kaposy, C. & Bandrauk, N. (2012). Prioritizing vaccine access for vulnerable but stigmatized groups. Public Health Ethics, 5: 283295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kayman, H., Radest, H. & Webb, S. (2009). Emergency and disaster scenarios. In Singer, P. & Viens, A. M., editors, Cambridge Textbook on Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 281288.Google Scholar
Lee, C., Rogers, W. A. & Braunack-Mayer, A. (2008). Social justice and pandemic influenza planning: The role of communication strategies. Public Health Ethics, 1: 223224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lucassen, A., Montgomery, J. & Parker, M. (2017). Ethics and the social contract for genomics in the NHS. In Davies, S. C., editor, Annual Report of the Chief Medical Officer 2016, Generation Genome. London: Department of Health, ch. 16.Google Scholar
Malecki, J. (2001). Letters Laced with Anthrax. Palm Beach, FL: Health Commission.Google Scholar
Montgomery, J. (2013). Reflections on the nature of public ethics. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 22: 921.Google Scholar
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2007). Public Health Ethics. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.Google Scholar
Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2012). Emerging Biotechnologies: Technology, Choice and the Public Good. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. (2002). A Question of Trust: The BBC Reith Lectures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. (2011). Broadening bioethics: Clinical ethics, public health and global health. Nuffield Council on Bioethics Lecture. See http://nuffieldbioethics.org/wp-content/uploads/Broadening_bioethics_clinical_ethics_public_health_global_health.pdf.Google Scholar
Phillips, N. (2000). Report of the Inquiry into BSE and Variant CJD in the United Kingdom. London: Stationery Office. See https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/20060525120000/http://www.bseinquiry.gov.uk/report/index.htm.Google Scholar
Rawls, A. (1971). Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Restraint Advisory Board (2011). Report of the Restraint Advisory Board to the Ministry of Justice. Assessment of Behaviour Recognition & Physical Restraint (BRPR) for Children in the Secure Estate. London: Restraint Advisory Board.Google Scholar
Sandman, P. M. (1989). Hazard versus outrage in the public perception of risk. In Covello, V. T., McCallum, D. B. & Pavlova, M.T., editors, Effective Risk Communication: The Role and Responsibility of Government and Nongovernmental Organizations. New York, NY: Plenum Press, pp. 4549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stiglitz, J. (2012). The Price of Inequality. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2017a). Minimum Core Obligations: Human Rights in the Here and Now. Washington, DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
Tasioulas, J. (2017b). The Minimum Core of the Human Right to Health. Washington, DC: World Bank.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, A. K., Faith, K., Gibson, J. L. & Upshar, R. E. G. (2006). Pandemic preparedness: An ethical framework to guide decision-making. BMC Medical Ethics, 7: 12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
US Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2015). Ethics and Ebola: Public health planning and response. See https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcsbi/sites/default/files/Ethics-and-Ebola_PCSBI_508.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welsh Assembly Government (2007). An Ethical Framework for Commissioning Health Services to Achieve the Healthcare Standards for Wales: WHC (2007) 076. Cardiff: The Welsh Assembly Government.Google Scholar
World Health Organization (2008). The right to health: Factsheet 31. See www.ohchr.org/Documents/Publications/Factsheet31.pdf.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, R. & Pickett, K. (2009). The Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do Better. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Wolff, J. (2012). The Human Right to Health. New York, NY: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×