Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-wq484 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T19:24:05.362Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Geulincx, Arnold (1624–1669)

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

J. A. Van Ruler
Affiliation:
Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Arnold (or Arnout) Geulincx was baptized in Antwerp in late January 1624. He reportedly spoke Latin fluently even as a child, matriculated at Leuven University in January 1640, and became professor primarius there in 1652. Six years later, he seems to have made the decision to move to Leiden because he intended to marry his niece Susanna Strickers, a step his Leuven career as canon and professor prohibited.

It was in Leiden that Geulincx became a Cartesian. Apart from the idea of mind-body dualism, his Cartesianism was inspired by the notion of epistemological growth found in the paragraphs on childhood prejudice in Descartes’ Principles of Philosophy. Yet Geulincx also went beyond Descartes. Instead of dealing only with sensations, he developed a parallel notion of conceptual projections on reality, arguing that it is on the basis of our “ways of thinking” (modi cogitandi) that we misrepresent things “as they are in themselves.” This may well be seen as a prefiguration of Kant, as long as it is kept in mind that Geulincx was not thinking in terms of necessary categories, but rather of epistemological distortions – the misrepresentations of reality consolidated in the concepts of Aristotelian metaphysics. According to Geulincx (1891–93, 2:301), to regard things in themselves as substances (or even as “things”) was simply a way of applying intellectual phasmata to the outside world alongside our phasmata of sense. Wisdom, on the other hand, results from the fact that “something divine within us” tells us that “it is not so.”

Geulincx's epistemology has been read in terms of both an illumination theory (Vleeschauwer 1953) and a theory of vision in God (Aalderink 2009). Against this, it must be said that Geulincx never explicitly discussed the question “where” our ideas originate. Indeed, unlike Augustine and Malebranche, but very much like Descartes himself, Geulincx conceived the dissimilarity between sensual information and its intellectual reinterpretation in such a way that there was no need to address the Platonic question as to how ideas might represent objects (see representation).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Geulincx, Arnold. 2006. Ethics, with Samuel Beckett's Notes, ed. van Ruler, H., Uhlmann, Anthony and Wilson, M.. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Geulincx, Arnold. 1891–93. Opera Philosophica, 3 vols., ed. Land, J. P. N.. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff (reprint, Sämtliche Schriften in fünf Bänden, ed. de Vleeschauwer, H. J., 3 vols., Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1965–68).Google Scholar
Aalderink, Mark Jan Herman. 2009.“Philosophy, Scientific Knowledge, and Concept Formation in Geulincx and Descartes,” Ph.D. dissertation, Utrecht.
Armogathe, Jean-Robert, and Carraud, Vincent. 2003. “The First Condemnation of Descartes’ Œuvres: Some Unpublished Documents from the Vatican Archives,” Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 1: 67–109.Google Scholar
Renz, Ursula, and van Ruler, Han. 2010. “Okkasionalismus,” Enzyklopädie Philosophie, 3 vols., ed. Sandkühler, H. Jörg. Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 2:1843–46.Google Scholar
Van Ruler, J. A. 2003. “Geulincx, Arnold (1624–69),” in The Dictionary of 17th and 18th-Century Dutch Philosophers, ed. van Bunge, W. et al. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1:322–31.Google Scholar
Vleeschauwer, Herman Jan De. 1953. “Les antécédants du transcendentalisme kantien: Geulincx et Kant,” Kantstudien 45: 245–73.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×