Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-5g6vh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T09:25:22.370Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scholasticism

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Marleen Rozemond
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

One of Descartes’ central aims is to substitute his own views for those of the Scholastics. At the same time, Descartes also owes significant debts to the Scholastics, who were a powerful force during his time and whose teachings were fundamental to his Jesuit education at La Flèche. So relating his thought to Scholasticism is important for understanding his targets as well as for interpreting the ideas he inherited from his predecessors.

Central to Scholasticism were the teachings of Aristotle, whom Descartes singles out as a target of his Meditations: “These six Meditations contain all the foundations of my physics. But please do not tell people, for that might make it harder for supporters of Aristotle to approve them. I hope that readers will gradually get used to my principles, and recognize their truth, before they notice that they destroy the principles of Aristotle” (AT III 298, CSMK 173). He criticizes those who rely on Aristotle rather than reason (AT III 432, 796; CSMK 195, 215) and repeatedly expresses frustration with the strong influence of Aristotle (AT I 522, CSMK 79; AT III 349, CSMK 177). He describes the views of the Scholastics as mostly doubtful as well as useless for the purposes of explanation (AT VIIIB 26, CSMK 221). In 1640 he conceives of a plan to publish a work that would include Eustachius a Sancto Paulo's Summa philosophica quadripartita, with his own views juxtaposed (AT III 523, CSMK 209–10), a plan he never carries out.

At the same time, Descartes sometimes notes agreements with Aristotle (AT IV 141, 157; CSMK 238, 240). Given his criticisms of Aristotle elsewhere, his doing so is likely motivated by prudence. He expresses a sense of intellectual indebtedness to the Jesuits and recommends a Jesuit education in philosophy, in particular, La Flèche (AT II 378). But he also indicates that he felt it was in his interest to be on good terms with the Jesuits (AT IV 157, CSMK 240). His strategy is often to offer his own views while remaining silent about Scholastic views in the hope that his own views will be accepted instead of those of the Scholastics, as we saw him indicate in regard to Aristotle. For instance, while in letters he is often very critical of the notions of real quality and substantial form, he avoids discussing them in his published works.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ariew, Roger. 2011. Descartes among the Scholastics. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carriero, John. 2009. Between Two Worlds: A Reading of Descartes's Meditations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cronin, Timothy, S.J. 1966. Objective Being in Descartes and in Suárez, Analecta Gregoriana, 154. Rome: Gregorian University Press.Google Scholar
Dalbiez, Roland. 1929. “Les sources scolastiques de la théorie cartésienne de l’être objectif. A propos du ‘Descartes’ de M. Gilson,” Revue d'Histoire de la Philosophie 3: 464–72.Google Scholar
Des Chene, Dennis. 2000. Life's Form: Late Aristotelian Conceptions of the Soul. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Des Chene, Dennis. 1996. Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1986. “Semel in vita: The Scientific Background to Descartes’ Meditations,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Rorty, A. O.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 81–116.Google Scholar
Gilson, Étienne. 1930. Étude sur le role de la pensée médiévale dans la formation du système cartésien. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Gilson, Etienne. 1913. Index scolastico-cartésien. Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
Hattab, Helen. 2009. Descartes on Forms and Mechanism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Paul. 2009. Essays on Descartes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Paul. 1986. “The Unity of Descartes's Man,” Philosophical Review 95: 339–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Normore, Calvin. 1986. “Meaning and Objective Being: Descartes and His Sources,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Rorty, A. O.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 223–41.Google Scholar
Renault, Laurence. 2000. “La réalité objective dans les premières objections aux Méditations métaphysiques: Ockham contra Descartes,” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 29–38.Google Scholar
Rozemond, Marleen. 1999. “Mind-Body Interaction: What's the Problem?,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 37: 435–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozemond, Marleen. 1998. Descartes's Dualism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schepers, Heinrich. 1966. Commercium mentis et corporis. Stuttgard-Bad Canstadtt: Friedrich Frommann Verlag.Google Scholar
Wells, Norman. 1990. “Objective Being in Descartes, Suárez and Caterus,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 78: 33–61.Google Scholar
Wells, Norman. 1967. “Objective Being: Descartes and his Sources,” Modern Schoolman 45: 49–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Scholasticism
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.227
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Scholasticism
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.227
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Scholasticism
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.227
Available formats
×