Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T04:32:00.376Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Experiment

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Theo Verbeek
Affiliation:
Universiteit Utrecht
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes is not usually associated with an empirical, let alone experimental, approach to science. According to the textbook version of Descartes’ philosophy, the fundamental principles of Cartesian physics are established independently of all experience; all one has to do would be to identify them through a process of systematic doubt and to justify them with an appeal to divine veracity. Although this idea of Cartesian science is not entirely false, there is considerable room for qualification. Moreover, Descartes’ correspondence shows that, despite a deep distrust in the observations and experiments of others, Descartes rarely rejects them as being irrelevant, usually asks to be informed of the precise circumstances, and quite often suggests new experiments of his own. The bottom line, however, is that for him no observation or experiment can ever be useful without a correct general theory; without it, experiments are mere “curiosity,” which, being a kind of wonder, is of little use in science (AT X 371, CSM I 16) and even “perverts the use of reason” (AT XI 385–86, CSM I 355–56).

The Discourse is one of the few places where Descartes explicitly discusses experiments and affirms their necessity. Descartes situates himself in a distinctly Baconian perspective, emphasizing both the practical and, in a limited way, the collective aspects of science. He also admits the necessity of experiments but is eager to point out their limitations. Observations and experiments are necessary “the more we advance in our knowledge” but not when we begin: “If we begin, instead of seeking those [observations] which are more unusual and rather contrived it is better to take those only into account which, presenting themselves spontaneously to our senses, cannot remain unknown after a little reflection” (AT VI 63, CSM I 143). Unusual observations (which includes experiments) would be misleading if we did not know the explanation of the more general ones.

As a result, Cartesian natural philosophy, or physics, consists of two levels: one dealing with the most general features of nature and based on ordinary experience, and the other dealing with particular effects. The first level, general physics, in turn, can be divided into two parts: the derivation of “the principles or first causes of everything” from “seeds of truth that are naturally in our souls”; and an examination of the “first and most ordinary effects that can be deduced from those causes” (AT VI 64, CSM I 144).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buchdahl, Gerd. 1969. Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Buchwald, J. Z. 2008. “Descartes's Experimental Journey Past the Prism and through the Invisible World to the Rainbow,” Annals of Science 65: 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond. 2006. Descartes: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond. 1982. Descartes’ Philosophy of Science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, Desmond. 1977. “Descartes’ Use of ‘Demonstration’ and ‘Deduction,’Modern Schoolman 44: 333–44.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1993. “Descartes and Experiment in the Discourse and Essays,” in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Rene Descartes, ed. Voss, S.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 288–310.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Georgescu, Laura, and Giurgea, Madalina. 2012. “Redefining the Role of Experience in Bacon's Natural History: How Baconian Was Descartes before Emerging from His Cocoon,” Early Science and Medicine 17: 158–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milhaud, Gaston. 1921. Descartes savant. Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
Sabra, A. I. 1967. Theories of Light from Descartes to Newton. London: Oldbourne.Google Scholar
Sakellariados, Spyros. 1982. “Descartes's Use of Empirical Data to Test Hypotheses,” Isis 73: 68–76.Google Scholar
Schuster, John. 2013. Descartes-Agonistes: Physico-Mathematics, Method and Corpuscular-Mechanism, 1618–33. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuster, John, and Brody, Judit. 2013. “Descartes and Sunspots: Matters of Fact and Systematizing Strategies in the Principia Philosophiae,” Annals of Science 70: 1–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Experiment
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.099
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Experiment
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.099
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Experiment
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.099
Available formats
×