Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T10:10:32.228Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Geometrical Exposition

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Noa Shein
Affiliation:
Ben Gurion University of the Negev
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

In the Second Set of Objections to the Meditations, Descartes is asked to “set out the entire argument in geometrical fashion, starting from a number of definitions, postulates and axioms” (see Objections and Replies). The objectors then add, “You are highly experienced in employing this method, and it would enable you to fill the mind of each reader so that he could see everything as it were at a single glance, and be permeated with awareness of the divine power” (AT VII 128, CSM II 92). Mersenne and his fellow objectors, in effect, are asking Descartes to do for his metaphysics what Euclid had done for geometry. Euclid in The Elements systematizes geometry by using what came to be known as the geometrical method. That is, by using a small set of stipulated definitions, axioms, which are taken to be self-evident, along with postulates, which are sometimes understood to be assumptions that are not self-evident (Heath 1926, 1:123–24), together with the rules of deduction, various theorems can then be demonstrated.

Descartes replies to the second set of objectors’ request by making a distinction between the order and the method of demonstration when writing in a “geometrical manner.” The geometrical order, as he describes it in both the Second Replies and the synopsis to the Meditations, is one by which claims or items that come first must be entirely known without the aid of those that come later in the demonstration (AT VII 154, CSM II 110; AT VII 4, CSM II 5). In turn, what comes later in the demonstration must rely solely on what came before. Some have wondered whether Descartes means these items to be ontologically or epistemically prior – that is, first in the order of being or first in the order of discovery (CSM II 110 n. 2 and 112 n. 1). However, given that Descartes proves God's existence in the Third Meditation and his own existence, which depends on God, in the Second Meditation, it seems fair to assume that he means first in the order of discovery and not in the order of being.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Euclid, . 1926. The Thirteen Books of Euclid's “Elements” Translated from the Text of Heiberg, 2nd ed., 3 vols., ed. and trans. Heath, T. L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (reprint, New York: Dover, 1956).Google Scholar
Spinoza, Baruch. 1985. The Collected Works of Spinoza, vol. 1, ed. and trans. Curley, E.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Curley, Edwin. 1986. “Analysis in the Meditations: The Quest for Clear and Distinct Ideas,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Rorty, A. O.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 153–76.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 1989. Cartesian Logic: An Essay on Descartes's Conception of Inference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Kurt. 2010. Matter Matters: Metaphysics and Methodology in the Early Modern Period. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Geometrical Exposition
    • By Noa Shein, Ben Gurion University of the Negev
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.116
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Geometrical Exposition
    • By Noa Shein, Ben Gurion University of the Negev
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.116
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Geometrical Exposition
    • By Noa Shein, Ben Gurion University of the Negev
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.116
Available formats
×