Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-18T15:54:17.100Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Eight Fallacies About Liberty and Security

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 August 2009

David Luban
Affiliation:
Professor of Law and Philosophy, Georgetown University's Law Center and Department of Philosophy
Richard Ashby Wilson
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut
Get access

Summary

We often hear it said that in times of danger we confront difficult trade-offs between national security and civil liberties, or between national security and human rights. We nod our heads, and reflect that tough times call for tough measures. An American official, commenting on the harsh and even brutal techniques that U.S. interrogators use on suspected terrorists, put it bluntly. “If you don't violate someone's human rights some of the time, you probably aren't doing your job” (Priest & Gelman 2002). While some people might find such talk appalling, others find it realistic, tough-minded, and oddly reassuring. We face terrible threats posed by ruthless international terrorists who have already proven themselves eager for mass murder – and who may well gain access to weapons of apocalyptic power. Confronted with these threats, excessive concern with human rights and civil liberties seems legalistic and, however well-meaning it is, misguided. Trade-offs are inevitable, and the only important question then becomes where to draw the line. How much liberty should be sacrificed in the name of security? How many human rights can we afford to respect?

The constitutional scholar John Hart Ely once remarked that no answer is what the wrong question begets (Ely 1980: 72). In this chapter, I argue that the questions in the last paragraph are the wrong ones to ask; unfortunately, it is not non-answers they beget, but wrong answers.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bentham, J. (1824). Anarchical Fallacies, Article II
Bork, R. H. (1990). The Tempting of America. New York: Free PressGoogle Scholar
Bumiller, E. (2003, October 26). ‘Evangelicals Sway White House on Human Rights Issues Abroad’. New York Times, p. 1Google Scholar
Cole, D. (2003). Enemy Aliens: Double Standards and Constitutional Freedoms in the War on Terrorism. New York: New PressGoogle Scholar
Ely, J. H. (1980). Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Ex parte Milligan, 71 U.S. 2, 120–1 (1866)
Ex parte Quirin, 317 U.S. 1 (1942)
Golden, T. (2004, October 24). ‘After Terror, a Secret Rewriting of Military Law’. New York Times, p. A12Google Scholar
Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 124 S. Ct. 2633, 159 L. Ed. 2d 578, 72 U.S.L.W. 4607, 2004 LEXIS 4761 (2004)
Humanitarian Law Project v. Reno, 205 F.3d 1130, 1137 (9th Cir. 2000)
Humanitarian Law Project v. United States DOJ, 352 F.3d 382, 404 (9th Cir. 2003)
Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 414 (1944)
Lowman, D. D. (2000). MAGIC: The Untold Story of U.S. Intelligence and the Evacuation of Japanese Residents from the West Coast During WW II. Utah: Athena PressGoogle Scholar
Malkin, M. (2004). In Defense of Internment: The Case for “Racial Profiling” in World War II and the War on Terror. NAACP v. Alabama, 357 U.S. 449 (1958). RegneryGoogle Scholar
Padilla v. Bush, 233 F. Supp. 2d 564 (S.D.N.Y. 2002)
Posner, R. A. (2002, Summer). ‘The Truth About Our Liberties’. The Responsive Community, pp. 4–5Google Scholar
Power, S. (2002). “A Problem From Hell”: America and the Age of Genocide. New York: Basic BooksGoogle Scholar
Priest, D. & Gelman, B. (2002, December 26). ‘U.S. Decries Abuse but Defends Interrogations; “Stress and Duress” Tactics Used on Terrorism Suspects Held in Secret Overseas Facilities’. Washington Post, p. A1Google Scholar
Rasul v. Bush, 124 S. Ct. 2686, 159 L. Ed. 2d 548, 72 U.S.L.W. 4596, 2004 LEXIS 4760 (2004)
Rumsfeld v. Padilla, 124 S. Ct. 2711, 159 L. Ed. 2d 513, 72 U.S.L.W. 4584, 2004 LEXIS 4759 (2004)
Tushnet, M. (2003). ‘Defending Korematsu?: Reflections on Civil Liberties in Wartime’. Wisconsin Law Review 2003, pp. 273–307Google Scholar
U.S. v. Czubinski, 106 F.3d 1069 (1st Cir. 1997)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×