Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 September 2016
To supply a connection between the modal syllogistic developed in Aristotle's Prior Analytics and the rest of his philosophy interpreters frequently assume that the modal syllogistic must somehow have been intended for use in Aristotle's theory of demonstration as found in the Posterior Analytics, and, on this basis, try to find explanations for some of its peculiarities. According to the most common such proposal, Aristotle's claims about necessity syllogisms are often explained by making a distinction between essential and accidental predication and supposing that the necessary premises of demonstrations are necessary because they rest on definitional or essential predications. The evidence adduced for such claims is essentially that if we suppose Aristotle to have some notions in mind that appear in the Posterior Analytics when he develops the modal syllogistic, then we can see why he makes the claims that he does about what is or is not a necessary proposition, or a valid inference, etc. However, these are at best speculative answers to the question why Aristotle developed the modal syllogistic as he did, given that he had already decided to develop it. They do not explain why he might have wanted to develop such a theory in the first place. They do not tell us what use the modal syllogistic might have been to him in his theory of demonstration – or, more precisely, what use he might have had in mind for it. In order even to speculate productively about that, we should really like to identify some puzzles or difficulties concerning demonstrative science that results of the modal syllogistic might help resolve. At the very least, we would hope to find some evidence in the Posterior Analytics of use of even some general results found in the modal syllogistic. However, all we see is the claim that if what is demonstrated is itself necessary, then the premises from which it is demonstrated must also be necessary.
In order to link the modal syllogistic with the rest of Aristotle's philosophy we must look elsewhere. It turns out that there is a passage in the Prior Analytics in which Aristotle articulates a principle about possibility, which is almost word for word identical with a passage which appears in book Θ of the Metaphysics.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.