Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5b777bbd6c-f9nfp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-06-25T21:44:43.034Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Spin ½: the Pauli theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 January 2010

Get access

Summary

Introduction

The claim that it is impossible to construct a realistic physical model of quantum matter is often presented as definitively and finally proved in the case of systems with spin ½, or internal angular momentum of magnitude ħ/2, which exhibit a characteristic ‘nonclassical two-valuedness’. Nevertheless, the extension of the causal interpretation to embrace nonrelativistic spin ½ systems was successfully carried through in the 1950s (Bohm, Schiller & Tiomno, 1955; Bohm & Schiller, 1955; Takabayasi, 1955; Takabayasi & Vigier, 1957) and developed more recently (Dewdney, Holland & Kyprianidis, 1986, 1987a, b; Dewdney, Holland, Kyprianidis & Vigier, 1988). The idea is to assume that the spinor wave represents a new type of physical field propagating in spacetime that exerts an influence on a corpuscle moving within it. The additional information conveyed by the spinor beyond that contained in the spinless Schrödinger wave implies that the state of the particle is not exhausted by specifying its position and momentum, but that it is endowed with further properties such as an internal angular momentum.

The equation governing the dynamics of the spinor wavefunction is the Pauli equation:

where the Hamiltonian operator is given by

Here e, m and μ are respectively the charge, mass and magnetic moment of the particle, A0 and A are the electromagnetic potentials, B = ∇ × A is the magnetic field, V is any other external scalar potential, and σ is a vector whose components are the 2 × 2 Pauli matrices. The Hamiltonian (9.1.2) istherefore a 2 × 2 matrix operator and the wavefunction ψ(x, t) has two complex components.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Quantum Theory of Motion
An Account of the de Broglie-Bohm Causal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
, pp. 379 - 423
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Book purchase

Temporarily unavailable

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×